Notes on General Equilibrium

Similar documents
First Welfare Theorem

General Equilibrium. General Equilibrium, Berardino. Cesi, MSc Tor Vergata

The Ohio State University Department of Economics. Homework Set Questions and Answers

EC487 Advanced Microeconomics, Part I: Lecture 5

General Equilibrium and Welfare

Lecture 1. History of general equilibrium theory

Market Equilibrium and the Core

The Debreu-Scarf Theorem: The Core Converges to the Walrasian Allocations

Competitive Equilibrium

Introduction to General Equilibrium

1 Second Welfare Theorem

Question 1. (p p) (x(p, w ) x(p, w)) 0. with strict inequality if x(p, w) x(p, w ).

Differentiable Welfare Theorems Existence of a Competitive Equilibrium: Preliminaries

Introduction to General Equilibrium: Framework.

Advanced Microeconomics

In the Name of God. Sharif University of Technology. Microeconomics 1. Graduate School of Management and Economics. Dr. S.

Notes on Consumer Theory

Second Welfare Theorem

Mathematical models in economy. Short descriptions

Advanced Microeconomic Theory. Chapter 6: Partial and General Equilibrium

Economics 501B Final Exam Fall 2017 Solutions

Microeconomic Theory -1- Introduction

Week 6: Consumer Theory Part 1 (Jehle and Reny, Chapter 1)

Lecture #3. General equilibrium

ECONOMICS 001 Microeconomic Theory Summer Mid-semester Exam 2. There are two questions. Answer both. Marks are given in parentheses.

Adding Production to the Theory

1 General Equilibrium

Positive Theory of Equilibrium: Existence, Uniqueness, and Stability

Microeconomics, Block I Part 2

The Consumer, the Firm, and an Economy

PhD Qualifier Examination

Department of Economics The Ohio State University Final Exam Questions and Answers Econ 8712

Microeconomics II. MOSEC, LUISS Guido Carli Problem Set n 3

A MATHEMATICAL MODEL OF EXCHANGE

General Equilibrium with Production

The Fundamental Welfare Theorems

Economics 201b Spring 2010 Solutions to Problem Set 1 John Zhu

Lecture Notes October 18, Reading assignment for this lecture: Syllabus, section I.

Structural Properties of Utility Functions Walrasian Demand

Fundamental Theorems of Welfare Economics

Problem Set Suggested Answers

Ph.D. Preliminary Examination MICROECONOMIC THEORY Applied Economics Graduate Program June 2016

Advanced Microeconomics Problem Set 1

Welfare Economics: Lecture 12

EconS 501 Final Exam - December 10th, 2018

Economic Core, Fair Allocations, and Social Choice Theory

3. THE EXCHANGE ECONOMY

Notes IV General Equilibrium and Welfare Properties

Alfred Marshall s cardinal theory of value: the strong law of demand

Recitation #2 (August 31st, 2018)

Noncooperative Games, Couplings Constraints, and Partial Effi ciency

Foundations of Neoclassical Growth

Simon Fraser University, Department of Economics, Econ 201, Prof. Karaivanov FINAL EXAM Answer key

Problem Set 1 Welfare Economics

Unlinked Allocations in an Exchange Economy with One Good and One Bad

Economics 101. Lecture 2 - The Walrasian Model and Consumer Choice

Core. Ichiro Obara. December 3, 2008 UCLA. Obara (UCLA) Core December 3, / 22

EconS Microeconomic Theory II Homework #9 - Answer key

Recitation 2-09/01/2017 (Solution)

Economics 201B Second Half. Lecture 12-4/22/10. Core is the most commonly used. The core is the set of all allocations such that no coalition (set of

Can everyone benefit from innovation?

KIER DISCUSSION PAPER SERIES

Duality. for The New Palgrave Dictionary of Economics, 2nd ed. Lawrence E. Blume

Representation of TU games by coalition production economies

Market Outcomes: Efficient or Fair?

Economics 200A part 2 UCSD Fall quarter 2011 Prof. R. Starr Mr. Troy Kravitz1 FINAL EXAMINATION SUGGESTED ANSWERS

Discussion Papers in Economics

A : a b c d a : B C A E B : d b c a b : C A B D E C : d c a c : E D B C D : a d b d : A D E B C E : a b d. A : a b c d a : B C A D E

Uniqueness, Stability, and Gross Substitutes

Microeconomics. Joana Pais. Fall Joana Pais

Competitive Market Mechanisms as Social Choice Procedures

Public Economics Ben Heijdra Chapter 9: Introduction to Normative Public Economics

Econ 201: Problem Set 3 Answers

Week 7: The Consumer (Malinvaud, Chapter 2 and 4) / Consumer November Theory 1, 2015 (Jehle and 1 / Reny, 32

Contracts under Asymmetric Information

The Walrasian Model and Walrasian Equilibrium

Algorithmic Game Theory and Applications

General equilibrium with externalities and tradable licenses

Equilibrium and Pareto Efficiency in an exchange economy

Short correct answers are sufficient and get full credit. Including irrelevant (though correct) information in an answer will not increase the score.

Preferences and Utility

Core equivalence and welfare properties without divisible goods

Lecture 7: General Equilibrium - Existence, Uniqueness, Stability

Week 9: Topics in Consumer Theory (Jehle and Reny, Chapter 2)

Notes I Classical Demand Theory: Review of Important Concepts

Short correct answers are sufficient and get full credit. Including irrelevant (though correct) information in an answer will not increase the score.

Economic Growth: Lecture 8, Overlapping Generations

The B.E. Journal of Theoretical Economics

ANSWERS TO ODD NUMBERED EXERCISES IN CHAPTER 3

2.9. V = u(x,y) + a(x-f(l x,t x )) + b(y-g(l y,t y )) + c(l o -L x -L y ) + d(t o -T x -T y ) (1) (a) Suggested Answer: V u a 0 (2) u x = -a b 0 (3)

Advanced Microeconomic Analysis, Lecture 6

1 Two elementary results on aggregation of technologies and preferences

ECON FINANCIAL ECONOMICS

Advanced Microeconomics

GARP and Afriat s Theorem Production

(ii) An input requirement set for this technology is clearly not convex as it

Pareto Efficiency (also called Pareto Optimality)

5. Externalities and Public Goods. Externalities. Public Goods types. Public Goods

The Fundamental Welfare Theorems

Firms and returns to scale -1- John Riley

Transcription:

Notes on General Equilibrium Alejandro Saporiti Alejandro Saporiti (Copyright) General Equilibrium 1 / 42

General equilibrium Reference: Jehle and Reny, Advanced Microeconomic Theory, 3rd ed., Pearson 2011: Ch. 5. Behind the superficial chaos of countless market transactions by selfish individuals, Adam Smith (1776) saw a harmonizing force (the invisible hand) operating in a competitive economy. Smith believed that force guides individuals to coordinate their choices, i.e. their consumption and productions plans, in such a way that all markets in the economy are brought into balance simultaneously. He also believed that the resulting equilibrium possesses socially desirable properties, in the sense that it maximizes social welfare through no conscious collective intention of its members. Does this vision of the competitive markets possess any substance? Alejandro Saporiti (Copyright) General Equilibrium 2 / 42

Exchange economy To answer that question, consider first a society without organized markets. There are i = 1,..., I individuals and j = 1,..., N consumption goods. Each individual i is endowed by nature with A certain (nonnegative) amount e i = (e i 1,..., ei N ) RN + of the consumption goods, and A preference relation i over R N + represented by the utility function u i : R N + R. The utility function u i is continuous, increasing and quasiconcave. Agents can eat their initial endowment or engage in trade with others. Exchange is voluntary and private ownership is respected. Alejandro Saporiti (Copyright) General Equilibrium 3 / 42

Exchange economy Consumer i s consumption bundle is denoted x i = (x i 1,..., xi N ) RN +. An allocation is a vector of consumption bundles x = (x 1,..., x I ). Let e = (e 1,...,e I ) and u = (u 1,...,u I ). The set of feasible allocations in this pure exchange economy E = (e, u) is given by F(e) = { I I x R I N + : x i j = i=1 i=1 e i j j = 1,..., N How does trade take place in this exchange economy? Where does this system of voluntary exchanges might come to rest? }. Alejandro Saporiti (Copyright) General Equilibrium 4 / 42

Bilateral exchange To simplify the analysis, let s focus on a 2 2 economy, i.e., an economy with two consumers, A and B, and two goods, 1 and 2. The main advantage of the 2 2 economy is that it can be graphically described through the so called Edgeworth box. The Edgeworth box has height e A 2 + eb 2 and width ea 1 + eb 1, and every point x represents a feasible allocation, where for all j = 1, 2, x A j + x B j = e A j + e B j. The box offers a complete picture of every feasible distribution of the existing commodities between the consumers. Alejandro Saporiti (Copyright) General Equilibrium 5 / 42

The Edgeworth box x B 1 x A 2 e B 1 0 B 0 A and B s initial endowments are given by (e A 1, ea 2 ) and (eb 1, eb 2 ). All bundles inside the indifference lenticular are preferred to e by both A and B. e A 2 0 A 0 e A 1 e x B 2 e B 2 x A 1 To achieve these gains, consumers must exchange part of their initial endowments. Alejandro Saporiti (Copyright) General Equilibrium 6 / 42

The Edgeworth box x B 1 x A 2 y B 1 e B 1 0 B 0 For instance, y is preferred by both A and B to their initial endowment. y A 2 e A 2 0 A 0 y y A 1 e A 1 e x B 2 y B 2 e B 2 x A 1 But y doesn t exhaust the possibilities for beneficial trade between A and B. Alejandro Saporiti (Copyright) General Equilibrium 7 / 42

The Edgeworth box x B 1 x A 2 z B 1 e B 1 0 B 0 z A 2 z z B 2 Only at a point like z there are no more mutually beneficial trades between A and B. The no worse than (upper counter) sets touch only at z. e A 2 0 A 0 z A 1 e A 1 e x B 2 e B 2 x A 1 Alejandro Saporiti (Copyright) General Equilibrium 8 / 42

Pareto efficiency We would expect rational agents will trade until all possibilities for mutually beneficial trade are exhausted. Such allocations are said to be Pareto efficient. Definition 1 (Pareto efficiency in consumption) A feasible allocation z F(e) is said to be Pareto efficient (PE) if there is no other feasible allocation ẑ F(e) such that u i (ẑ i ) u i (z i ) for all i = 1,..., I, with strict inequality for some i. Geometrically in the Edgeworth box, PE allocations are points x = (x A, x B ) at which consumers indifference curves are tangent; i.e., points at which the marginal rates of substitution are all equal: MRS1,2 A (xa 1, xa 2 ) = MRSB 1,2 (xb 1, xb 2 ). (1) Alejandro Saporiti (Copyright) General Equilibrium 9 / 42

Pareto efficiency Figure 1: Pareto efficiency in consumption. Definition 2 (Contract curve) The set CC of all feasible and Pareto efficient allocations is called the Pareto set or contract curve. Alejandro Saporiti (Copyright) General Equilibrium 10 / 42

Contract curve and the core y OA Core: set of possible equilibrium which improve utility relative to endowment, e2 e e 1 2 Contract Curve: Locus of points of tangency between MRS e 3 Figure 2: Contract curve and the core. x OB The equilibrium of the exchange process is going to be a point on the subset of the contract curve determined by consumers indifference curves through e. This set is called the core of the economy. However, we don t know where exactly the agents will end up. Alejandro Saporiti (Copyright) General Equilibrium 11 / 42

Generalizing the core Definition 3 (Blocking coalitions) A set of agents S blocks x F(e) if there exists an allocation y such that (i) i S yi = i S ei, and (ii) u i (y i ) u i (e i ) for all i S, with strict inequality for some i. Definition 4 (The core) The core of an exchange economy E = (e, u), denote C(E), is the set of all unblocked feasible allocations. Apart from the the fact that the core might be pretty big (see Fig. 2) and therefore lack any prediction power, the amount of information needed to arrange mutually beneficial trade and converge to C(E) might also be huge! The next step is to examine how market economies deal with these problems. Alejandro Saporiti (Copyright) General Equilibrium 12 / 42

Competitive markets Let s now add to our primitive economy E = (e, u) of pure exchange a few other assumptions: Markets exist for all goods. Agents can freely participate in markets without cost. Standard consumer theory assumptions: Preferences (strictly) monotone & represented by utility function; Some convexity if needed; All agents are price-takers; Finite number of perfectly divisible goods; Linear prices; Perfect information about goods and prices. All agents face the same prices. Alejandro Saporiti (Copyright) General Equilibrium 13 / 42

Walrasian equilibrium Given prices p 0, denote by y i (p) = j p j e i j consumer i s initial income, and by B i (p) = {x i R L + : p xi y i (p)} the budget set for i. Definition 5 (Walrasian equilibrium) A price vector p = (p 1,...,p N ) and an allocation x = (x 1,...,x I ) are said to be a Walrasian or competitive equilibrium (WE) iff (i) For all i = 1,..., I, x i arg max x B i (p) u i (x); i.e., x i is consumer i s Walrasian demand at prices p and income y i (p); and (ii) Markets clear at p; i.e, for all j = 1,..., N, the excess demand function z j (p) I I x i j e i j = 0. i=1 i=1 Alejandro Saporiti (Copyright) General Equilibrium 14 / 42

Walrasian equilibrium In words, a WE is a set of prices such that (i) Each agent chooses his most-preferred affordable bundle; and (ii) Consumers choices are compatible among each other, in the sense that total demand equals total supply in every market. Actually, this definition of a WE is stronger than necessary: It turns out that if the aggregate excess demand for N 1 goods is zero, then the excess demand for the remaining good must be zero too. This follows from a property of the excess demand function called Walras law: the value of the aggregate excess demand is zero for all possible prices (see Exercise 3.1): N p j z j (p 1,..., p N ) = 0. j=1 Alejandro Saporiti (Copyright) General Equilibrium 15 / 42

Walrasian equilibrium The offer curve traces out Walrasian demand as prices change. Walrasian equilibria are at the intersection of the offer curves. The intersection and thereby the Walrasian equilibrium need not be unique. Alejandro Saporiti (Copyright) General Equilibrium 16 / 42

Equilibrium existence For arbitrary prices (p 1, p 2 ) there is no guarantee that supply will equal demand, i.e., there is no guarantee that (ii) is satisfied. Figure 3: No equilibrium. Alejandro Saporiti (Copyright) General Equilibrium 17 / 42

Equilibrium existence How do we know that there exists a set of prices such that (i) and (ii) are simultaneously satisfied? This is known as the question of the existence of a competitive equilibrium. Early economists thought that equilibrium prices would always exist because the system has N 1 independent (excess demand) equations (by Walras law) and N 1 independent prices. There are in fact N prices, but we are free to choose one of the prices and set it equal to a constant, namely, equal to 1 (recall Walrasian demands are homogeneous of degree zero in prices). This price plays the role of numeraire, and all other prices are measured relative to it. Alejandro Saporiti (Copyright) General Equilibrium 18 / 42

Equilibrium existence However, counting the number of equations and unknowns is not sufficient to prove that a WE exists. Wald (1936) was the first to points out Walras error by offering a simple counterexample: x 2 + y 2 = 0 and x 2 y 2 = 1. The key issue is to ensure that the aggregate excess demand function is continuous (less than that is actually necessary). z 1 (p 1 ) That means that a small change in the prices shouldn t result in a big jump in the quantity demanded. Figure 4: Two goods. Alejandro Saporiti (Copyright) General Equilibrium 19 / 42 p 1

Excess demand Under what conditions will the aggregate excess demand functions be continuous? Definition 6 (Excess demand) The excess demand of agent i is z i (p) = x i (p, y i (p)) e i, where x i (p, y i (p)) is i s Walrasian demand at prices p and income y i (p) = p e i. The aggregate excess demand is z(p) = I i=1 zi (p). Note that a WE is a price vector p R N + such that z(p ) = 0. Some of the properties of the aggregate excess demand are the following. Alejandro Saporiti (Copyright) General Equilibrium 20 / 42

Properties of the excess demand Suppose u i is continuous, increasing, and concave, and e i 0 for all i. z( ) is continuous. Continuity of u i implies continuity of Walrasian demand x i (p, y i (p)). z( ) homogenous of degree zero (only relative prices matter). x i (p, y i (p)) homogeneous of degree zero in p. z i (p) = x i (p, y i (p)) e i homogeneous of degree zero in p. i zi (p) homogeneous of degree zero in p. Therefore, we can normalize one price N 1 unknowns. z( ) verifies Walras law; i.e., p z(p) = 0 p. u i increasing implies p x i (p, y i (p)) = p e i. p z i (p) = p [x i (p, y i (p)) e i ] = 0. p i zi (p) = 0. Therefore, we have N 1 excess demand equations. Alejandro Saporiti (Copyright) General Equilibrium 21 / 42

Equilibrium existence Theorem 1 (Existence of WE) Suppose for all i = 1,..., I, 1. u i ( ) is continuous; 2. u i ( ) is increasing; i.e., u i (ˆx) > u i (x) for any ˆx x; 3. u i ( ) is concave; 4. e i 0; i.e., agent i has at least a little bit of every good. Then there exists a price system p R N + such that z(p ) = 0. Wald (1936) offered the first correct proof of equilibrium existence, but for a restrictive class of preferences (separable & decreasing MU). McKenzie (1954) and Arrow & Debreu (1954) were the first to provide general proofs (based on fixed point theorems). The fascinating story behind the proof of equilibrium existence is very well described in a recent paper by Roy Weintraub, J of Econ Perspectives, 2011. Alejandro Saporiti (Copyright) General Equilibrium 22 / 42

Equilibrium existence: two-good case Consider a two-good economy. We can find a WE whenever z 1 (p 1, 1) = 0. z 1 (p 1, 1) continuous in p 1. lim p1 + 0 z 1 (p 1, 1) = because u i is increasing and e i 2 > 0 (every i has some money to spend on x 1 even if p 1 + 0). lim p1 z 1 (p 1, 1) < 0 because u i is increasing and e i 1 > 0 (every i spends money in both goods and value of e i 1 becomes huge relative to value of x i 1 ). z 1 (p 1 ) p 1 p 1 z 1 (,1) 0 p 1 Figure 5: Two goods. By the intermediate value theorem, there exists p 1 such that z 1(p 1, 1) = 0. Alejandro Saporiti (Copyright) General Equilibrium 23 / 42 p 1

Uniqueness As Figs 5 and 6 indicate, the Walrasian equilibrium need not be unique. Figure 6: Multiplicity of WE. Alejandro Saporiti (Copyright) General Equilibrium 24 / 42

Uniqueness z 1 (p 1 ) There could be one Walrasian equilibrium. z 1 (,1) 0 p 1 p 1 z 1 (p 1 ) There could be two WE (though this is non-generic ). z 1 (,1) p 0 1 p 1 p 1 Alejandro Saporiti (Copyright) General Equilibrium 25 / 42

Uniqueness There could be three Walrasian equilibria. z 1 (p 1 ) p 1 p 1 z 1 (,1) 0 p 1 p 1 There could be infinite WE (though this is again non-generic ). z 1 (p 1 ) z 1 (,1) 0 p 1 p 1 p 1 Alejandro Saporiti (Copyright) General Equilibrium 26 / 42

Uniqueness It seems (and can be formally shown) that: WE are globally non-unique (generically). WE are locally unique (generically). There are a finite number of WE (generically). There are an odd number of WE (generically). Alejandro Saporiti (Copyright) General Equilibrium 27 / 42

Equilibrium and the core Do competitive markets exhaust all of the gains from trade? We said that a Walrasian equilibrium requires individual optimality, which translates into the well known condition MRS i l,k (xi ) = p l p k for all l k and all i = 1,..., I. (2) Hence, since all individuals face the same prices, (2) implies that MRS i l,k (xi ) = MRS j l,k (xj ) for all l k and all i j. (3) Walrasian equilibrium involves tangency between consumers indifference curves through their demanded bundles, as illustrated in Fig. 6. Thus, for an exchange economy E = (u i, e i ) I i=1 satisfying the assumptions of Theorem 1, every Walrasian equilibrium allocation is in the core. Alejandro Saporiti (Copyright) General Equilibrium 28 / 42

Equilibrium and efficiency If we denote by W(e) the set of Walrasian equilibrium allocations x(p ) = (x 1 (p, y 1 (p )),..., x I (p, y I (p ))), then, Theorem 2 For an exchange economy E = (u i, e i ) I i=1 satisfying the assumptions of Theorem 1, W(e) C(e). And we also get the following two results: Corollary 1 (Nonemptiness of the core) For an exchange economy E = (u i, e i ) I i=1 satisfying the assumptions of Theorem 1, C(e). Theorem 3 (First Welfare Theorem (FWT)) Under the hypotheses of Theorem 1, every Walrasian equilibrium allocation x(p ) is Pareto efficient. Alejandro Saporiti (Copyright) General Equilibrium 29 / 42

Equilibrium and efficiency The FWT guarantees that a competitive economy will exhaust all of the gains from trade: a market mechanism, with each agent seeking to maximize his own utility, results in a PE allocation. That was Adam Smith s conjecture! FWT says nothing about the distribution of economic benefits. That is, a Walrasian equilibrium allocation might not be a fair or desirable allocation. Having said that, note that in a market economy Pareto efficiency is achieved without demanding much information: each consumer needs to know only his own preferences and endowments and the market prices. The fact that competitive markets economize on the use of information in the way just described is a strong argument in favor of using them to allocate scarce resources. Alejandro Saporiti (Copyright) General Equilibrium 30 / 42

Efficiency and equilibrium What about the converse of FWT? That is, given a Pareto efficient allocation, can we find prices such that those prices and the resulting allocation constitute a Walrasian equilibrium? It turns out that, under certain conditions, the answer is yes. The intuition is the following: Pick any PE allocation, say z; The indifference curves are tangent at z; Draw a straight line representing the common slope; Suppose now the initial endowments are reallocate such that the straight line denotes the budget constraint; The individual s demands associated to that budget line constitute a WE that coincides with the initial PE allocation z. Alejandro Saporiti (Copyright) General Equilibrium 31 / 42

Efficiency and equilibrium x B 1 z A 2 x A 2 z B 1 z e B 1 0 B 0 z B 2 There exists a straight budget line separating the two upper counter sets at z. e A 2 0 A 0 z A 1 e A 1 e p1 p2 x B 2 e B 2 x A 1 The line connects points e and z and has a slope of p 1 /p 2. Alejandro Saporiti (Copyright) General Equilibrium 32 / 42

Efficiency and equilibrium Is it always possible the construction of such budget line? Unfortunately, the answer is no. In the graph, X is PE, but at the budget line that is tangent to the indifference curves at X, agent A demands Y and agent B demands X, so demand doesn t equal supply at these prices. Alejandro Saporiti (Copyright) General Equilibrium 33 / 42

Efficiency and equilibrium This observation gives us the Second Welfare Theorem (SWT). Theorem 4 (Second Welfare Theorem (SWT)) Suppose an exchange economy E = (u i, e i ) I i=1 satisfies the assumptions of Theorem 1. If z F(e) is Pareto efficient, then z is a Walrasian equilibrium allocation for some Walrasian equilibrium prices p after redistribution of initial endowments to any allocation e F(e), such that p e i = p z i. SWT says that if all agents have convex preferences, there exists a set of prices such that every PE allocation is a WE for an appropriate redistribution of the initial endowments. SWT implies the problems of distribution and efficiency can be separated. Whatever PE allocation we wish to achieve can be implemented by the market mechanism, i.e., markets are distributionally neutral. Alejandro Saporiti (Copyright) General Equilibrium 34 / 42

Efficiency and equilibrium Prices play two roles in the market system: 1. Allocate role: they indicate (signal) the relative scarcity of the goods. 2. Distributive role: they determine the value of the initial endowments, thereby how much of the different goods each agent can affort. SWT tells us these two roles can be separated: endowments can be redistributed, and then prices can be used to indicate relative scarcity. In fact, what is needed is to transfer the purchasing power of the physical endowments, which can be done using nondistortionary (lump-sum) taxes that don t depend on economic agents choices. Alejandro Saporiti (Copyright) General Equilibrium 35 / 42

General equilibrium with production Reference: Jehle and Reny, Advanced Microeconomic Theory, 3rd ed., Pearson 2011: Ch. 5. The important properties of competitive markets saw before continue to hold. However, production brings with it new matters: Firms profits must be distributed back to the consumers who own the firms. Distinction between inputs and outputs become obscure when we view the production size of the economy as a whole (an input for one firm might be an output for another). Alejandro Saporiti (Copyright) General Equilibrium 36 / 42

Economy The economy is made of (i) j = 1,..., J firms; (ii) i = 1,..., I consumers; and (iii) k = 1,..., N goods. Each firm j possesses a production possibility set Y j. Assumption 1 0 Y j R N. Profits are bounded from below by zero. Y j is closed and bounded. Single-value and continues output supply and input demand functions. Y j strongly convex: for all y, y Y j, there exists ȳ Y j such that ȳ αy + (1 α)y for all α (0, 1). Rules out constant and increasing returns to scale; ensures profit maximizer is unique. Alejandro Saporiti (Copyright) General Equilibrium 37 / 42

Producers A production plan for firm j is a vector y j Y j, with the convention that y j k < 0 (resp. yj k > 0) if good k is an input (resp. an output) for j. Given a nonnegative price vector p R N +, each firm j solves the profit maximization problem (PMP) The objective function is continuous. The constraint set is bounded and closed. max p y j. (4) y j Y j By the Weierstrass Theorem, a maximum always exists. For all p R N +, let Πj (p) max y j Y j p y j be firm s j profit function. Alejandro Saporiti (Copyright) General Equilibrium 38 / 42

Consumers Each individual i = 1,..., I is endowed by nature with A certain (nonnegative) amount e i = (e i 1,..., ei N ) RN + of each good; A continuous, increasing and quasiconcave utility function u i : R N + R; A fraction (share) 0 θ ij 1 of firm j s profits, with I θ ij = 1 for all j. i=1 For any p 0, let m i (p) = p e i + J j=1 θij Π j (p) be consumer i s income. In this economy with production and private ownership of firms, consumer i s utility maximization problem (UMP) is max x i B i (p) u i (x i ), (5) where B i (p) {x i R N + : p xi m i (p)} denotes consumer i s budget set. Alejandro Saporiti (Copyright) General Equilibrium 39 / 42

Equilibrium Denote by y j (p) and x i (p, m i (p)) the solutions of (4) and (5), respectively. The aggregate excess demand function in market k is z k (p) = I x i k (p, mi (p)) i=1 and the aggregate excess demand vector is J y j k (p) j=1 I e i k, (6) i=1 z(p) = (z 1 (p),..., z N (p)). (7) A Walrasian equilibrium for the economy E = (u i, e i,θ ij, Y j ) is a price vector p R N + such that z(p ) = 0. Theorem 5 (Equilibrium existence with production) Consider the economy E = (u i, e i,θ ij, Y j ), where each u i and Y j satisfy the assumptions made above and y + I i=1 ei 0 for some aggregate production vector y J j=1 Yj. Then there exists a price system p R N + for E such that z(p ) = 0. Alejandro Saporiti (Copyright) General Equilibrium 40 / 42

Welfare An allocation (x, y) = (x 1,..., x I, y 1,...,y J ) is feasible if x i R N + for all i, y j Y j for all j, and I I J x i = e i + y j. (8) i=1 i=1 Definition 7 (Pareto efficiency with production) A feasible allocation (x, y) is said to be Pareto efficient (PE) if there is no other feasible allocation (ˆx, ŷ) such that u i (ˆx i ) u i (x i ) for all i = 1,..., I, with strict inequality for some i. Theorem 6 (First Welfare Theorem with production) If each u i is strictly increasing on R n +, then every Walrasian equilibrium allocation (x, y) is Pareto efficient. j=1 Alejandro Saporiti (Copyright) General Equilibrium 41 / 42

Welfare Theorem 7 (Second Welfare Theorem with production) Suppose the economy E = (u i, e i,θ ij, Y j ) satisfies the following assumptions: 1. u i is a continuous, increasing and quasiconcave; 2. Y j verifies Assumption 1; 3. I i=1 ei + J j=1 yj 0 for some (y 1,..., y J ). If (ˆx, ŷ) is a Pareto efficient allocation, then there are (i) income transfers T 1,..., T I, with I i=1 Ti = 0, and (ii) a price vector ˆp R N + such that: For all i = 1,..., I, ˆx i maximizes u i (x i ) subject to ˆp x i m i (ˆp) + T i ; For all j = 1,..., J, ŷ j maximizes ˆp y j subject to y j Y j. Alejandro Saporiti (Copyright) General Equilibrium 42 / 42