CAS LX 522 Syntax I Fall 2000 October 10, 2000 Week 5: Case Theory and θ Theory. θ-theory continued

Similar documents
Ch. 2: Phrase Structure Syntactic Structure (basic concepts) A tree diagram marks constituents hierarchically

(7) a. [ PP to John], Mary gave the book t [PP]. b. [ VP fix the car], I wonder whether she will t [VP].

Raising and Passive. Jean Mark Gawron. Linguistics 522 San Diego State University

Ling 98a: The Meaning of Negation (Week 5)

1. Background. Task: Determine whether a given string of words is a grammatical (well-formed) sentence of language L i or not.

CAS LX 523 Syntax II Spring 2001 March 13, (1) A qp. Kayne, Richard (1995). The antisymmetry of syntax. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

2 A not-quite-argument for X-bar structure in noun phrases

X-bar theory. X-bar :

CAS LX 522 Syntax I November 4, 2002 Week 9: Wh-movement, supplement

HPSG: Binding Theory

CAS LX 500 Topics in Linguistics: Questions Spring 2006 March 2, b: Prosody and Japanese wh-questions

2013 ISSN: JATLaC Journal 8: t 1. t t Chomsky 1993 I Radford (2009) R I t t R I 2. t R t (1) (= R's (15), p. 86) He could have helped

Logical Translations Jean Mark Gawron San Diego State University. 1 Introduction 2

Categories and Transformations 321

An introduction to German Syntax. 1. Head directionality: A major source of linguistic divergence

Semantics and Generative Grammar. Quantificational DPs, Part 3: Covert Movement vs. Type Shifting 1

Introduction to Semantics. The Formalization of Meaning 1

Constituency. Doug Arnold

Wh-movement. CAS LX 522 Syntax I Fall 2001 November 6, 2001

CS 712: Topics in NLP Linguistic Phrases and Statistical Phrases

Time Zones - KET Grammar

Stepanov 2007: The End of CED? Minimalism and Extraction Domains

Control and Tough- Movement

Proseminar on Semantic Theory Fall 2013 Ling 720 The Proper Treatment of Quantification in Ordinary English, Part 1: The Fragment of English

a. Develop a fragment of English that contains quantificational NPs. b. Develop a translation base from that fragment to Politics+λ

Ling 240 Lecture #15. Syntax 4

Control and Tough- Movement

The Semantics of Questions Introductory remarks

THE DRAVIDIAN EXPERIENCER CONSTRUCTION AND THE ENGLISH SEEM CONSTRUCTION. K. A. Jayaseelan CIEFL, Hyderabad

Binding Theory Different types of NPs, constraints on their distribution

Semantics 2 Part 1: Relative Clauses and Variables

Artificial Intelligence

HPSG II: the plot thickens

Other types of Movement

The Formal Architecture of. Lexical-Functional Grammar. Ronald M. Kaplan and Mary Dalrymple

Generalized Quantifiers & Categorial Approaches & Intensionality

Quantification: Quantifiers and the Rest of the Sentence

Grundlagenmodul Semantik All Exercises

Semantics and Generative Grammar. Pronouns and Variable Assignments 1. We ve seen that implicatures are crucially related to context.

CS1800: Strong Induction. Professor Kevin Gold

Spring 2018 Ling 620 Introduction to Semantics of Questions: Questions as Sets of Propositions (Hamblin 1973, Karttunen 1977)

Grammar and Feature Unification

Computationele grammatica

Model-Theory of Property Grammars with Features

One hint from secondary predication (from Baker 1997 (8) A secondary predicate cannot take the goal argument as subject of predication, wheth

Proseminar on Semantic Theory Fall 2010 Ling 720 The Basics of Plurals: Part 1 1 The Meaning of Plural NPs and the Nature of Predication Over Plurals

Semantics and Generative Grammar. Quantificational DPs, Part 2: Quantificational DPs in Non-Subject Position and Pronominal Binding 1

Ling 5801: Lecture Notes 7 From Programs to Context-Free Grammars

Word Order and the Floating Quantifier in Cebuano

564 Lecture 25 Nov. 23, Continuing note on presuppositional vs. nonpresuppositional dets.

Some binding facts. Binding in HPSG. The three basic principles. Binding theory of Chomsky

Models of Adjunction in Minimalist Grammars

27. THESE SENTENCES CERTAINLY LOOK DIFFERENT

Semantics and Pragmatics of NLP Pronouns

1 Classical scalar implicature

Quantification in the predicate calculus

Uniformity of Theta- Assignment Hypothesis. Transit i ve s. Unaccusatives. Unergatives. Double object constructions. Previously... Bill lied.

Spring 2017 Ling 620. An Introduction to the Semantics of Tense 1

The Logical Structure of Natural Language Expressions

September 13, Cemela Summer School. Mathematics as language. Fact or Metaphor? John T. Baldwin. Framing the issues. structures and languages

Semantics I, Rutgers University Week 3-1 Yimei Xiang September 17, Predicate logic

INTENSIONS MARCUS KRACHT

Beliefs Mini-Story Text

Processing Difficulty and Structural Uncertainty in Relative Clauses across East Asian Languages

27. THESE SENTENCES CERTAINLY LOOK DIFFERENT

Homework assignment 1: Solutions

Generalized Quantifiers Logical and Linguistic Aspects

Semantics and Generative Grammar. The Semantics of Adjectival Modification 1. (1) Our Current Assumptions Regarding Adjectives and Common Ns

THEME BASED HOLIDAY HOMEWORK

Entropy. Leonoor van der Beek, Department of Alfa-informatica Rijksuniversiteit Groningen. May 2005

SEMANTICS OF POSSESSIVE DETERMINERS STANLEY PETERS DAG WESTERSTÅHL

Introduction to Semantics. Pronouns and Variable Assignments. We ve seen that implicatures are crucially related to context.

Basics of conversational implicatures

Presuppositions (introductory comments)

Recap: Lexicalized PCFGs (Fall 2007): Lecture 5 Parsing and Syntax III. Recap: Charniak s Model. Recap: Adding Head Words/Tags to Trees

Compound verbs and derived verbs in Swahili to English machine translation

SOME NOTES ON LOGIC AND QUANTIFIER RAISING

Homogeneity and Plurals: From the Strongest Meaning Hypothesis to Supervaluations

Parasitic Scope (Barker 2007) Semantics Seminar 11/10/08

Assignment 3. Solution. 1. Give trees showing the derivations of the following sentences; show all movements.

Another look at PSRs: Intermediate Structure. Starting X-bar theory

CS460/626 : Natural Language Processing/Speech, NLP and the Web

PENGUIN READERS. Five Famous Fairy Tales

On Strict Cyclicity and Label: Toward Elimination of Late Merge*

THE EVIL QUEEN AND THE RED CACTUS By Dilmehr Kaur. The. Story Analysis BY JIHAN KAMILA AULIRAHAM. And The

Introduction to Semantics. Common Nouns and Adjectives in Predicate Position 1

Chiastic Lambda-Calculi

Unterspezifikation in der Semantik Scope Semantics in Lexicalized Tree Adjoining Grammars

1 Propositional Logic

Chapter 18. Sampling Distribution Models. Copyright 2010, 2007, 2004 Pearson Education, Inc.

PRISON BREAK ACTS 16:16-34

Karttunen Semantics. Last week. LING 147. Semantics of Questions Week 4 Yimei Xiang September 22, I. Intensionality

LIN1032 Formal Foundations for Linguistics

Biology: First year English Language Course 5 July 2018 Time allowed: 2 hours

Mathmatics 239 solutions to Homework for Chapter 2

A Context-Free Grammar

NP-Completeness I. Lecture Overview Introduction: Reduction and Expressiveness

Denotation of Predicates

October 16 th 2015, Budapest Workshop on Linguistic and Cognitive aspects of Quantification

Colette Sciberras, PhD (Dunelm) 2016 Please do not distribute without acknowledging the author!

Transcription:

CAS LX 522 Syntax I Fall 2000 October 0, 2000 Paul Hagstrom Week 5: Case Theory and θ Theory θ-theory continued From last time: verbs have θ-roles (e.g., Agent, Theme, ) to assign, specified in the lexicon arguments chains receive θ-roles. an argument is a referring expression (excludes wh-words). a chain is a collection of positions the argument occupied. θ-criterion: each argument must get exactly one θ-role. each verb must assign each of its θ-roles to exactly one argument. checked at the end of the derivation (evidence was wh-in-situ) Some terminology: θ-position: a position in any given tree where a θ-role is assigned. (e.g., complement of V) θ -position: positions in any given tree where a θ-role is not assigned. Quantifiers, QR, and c-command () a. John suspects everyone. b. SS: [ IP John suspects everyone]. c. LF: [ IP everyone i [ IP John suspects ti ]]. (2) IP NP i IP everyone John tj V NP t i I j V [pres] suspect () For every person x: [John suspects x]. (4) Everyone suspects someone. a. For every person x [ there is a person y [ x suspects y ]]. For everyone x, you can find a person y such that x suspects y. b. There is a person y [ for every person x [ x suspects y ]]. There is a person y such that y is suspected by everyone. (5) IP NP i IP everyone NP j IP someone t i t k V+I k NP suspects (6) IP NP j IP someone NP i IP everyone t i t k V+I k NP suspects (7) Scope The scope of α is the set of nodes α c-commands in the LF representation. (8) C-command a c-commands b iff: i) the first branching node dominating α also dominates β. ii) α does not dominate β. (9) A B c-commands C, D, and E D c-commands E (and vice versa) B C C c-commands B (and vice versa) D E t j t j Informally: To find what a node c-commands, go up one level, and it is everything below it except the original node.

(0) IP NP j IP 2 someone NP i IP everyone () IP NP i IP 2 everyone NP j IP someone category (XP) (2) XP segment (XP ) adjunct XP 2 segment (XP 2 ) adjunct XP segment (XP ) Segments count for determining c-command. A-positions vs. A -positions; A-chains vs. A -chains An A-position (argument position) is a structural position where an argument can be found at LF. For example, subject position (SpecIP), object position (complement of V). An A -position is a structural position where a non-argument can be found at LF. It is also useful to distinguish movement chains into A-chains (movement to an A- position) and A -chains (movement to an A -position). Nonstandard arguments Passives () a. Mary ate the sandwich. b. The sandwich was eaten. The passive verb does not assign an external θ-role (to SpecIP). We create the passive verb by attaching -ed or -en to the verb (remains a verb). We consider this derivation to take place in the lexicon (prior to insertion into X trees). Attaching -en suppresses the external θ-role: (4) eat: Agent <Theme> eaten: <Theme> (5) IP SpecIP is an A-position. NP i I SpecIP is a θ -position. the sandwich {the sandwich i, t i } is an A-chain. I V j I be [+past] t j eaten t i EPP (SpecIP must be filled) forces movement of the sandwich to SpecIP. Unaccusatives (6) a. The vase broke. b. John broke the vase. (7) break: Ø <Theme> (8) [ IP [the vase] i [ broke t i ]] (9) [ IP John [ CAUSE+break the vase ]] (20) CAUSE+break: Agent <Theme> Adjectival passives (2) a. The island was uninhabited. b. The performance was interrupted. (22) a. CBS employees inhabited the island. b. John interrupted the performace.

(2) a. The uninhabited island b. The uninterrupted performance (24) a. The island seemed uninhabited. b. The performance remained uninterrupted. Derived in the lexicon with a category changing suffix (also -en, -ed): (25) inhabit: [+V N] inhabited: [+V +N] Agent <Theme> Ø <Theme> Case Theory (26) a. John-ka chayk-ul ilkessta. Korean John-SUBJ book-obj read(past) John read a book. b. John-ga hon-o katta. Japanese John-SUBJ book-obj bought John bought a book. c. Knigu on čital Russian book-obj he-subj read(past) He read the book. subjective forms objective forms possessive forms sg I me my 2sg you you your sg masculine he him his sg feminine she her her pl we us our 2pl you you your pl they them their (27) a. I met Pat. b. * me met Pat. c. * my met Pat. (28) a. * Pat met I. b. c. Pat met me. * Pat met my. (29) a. * I cousin met Pat. b. * Me cousin met Pat. c. My cousin met Pat. Suppose: In fact: Since we see some evidence of Case differentiation in English, all nouns in English get Case only on most nouns, you can t tell the difference between subjective, objective, and possessive forms. We ll suppose that all noun phrases in all languages get Case. A well-formed noun phrase is a noun phrase that has Case. (0) a. * John to leave suddenly is foolish. b. For John to leave suddenly is foolish. c. To leave suddenly is foolish. d. * For to leave suddenly is foolish. Overt subjects cannot appear in the subject position of a nonfinite clause unless they are precedent by a prepositional complementizer (that is, for). Suppose: NPs are assigned Case by something (like θ-roles are assigned by verbs) Overt NPs without Case are ill-formed (PRO can get away without Case). Slightly more specifically: Infl can assign subjective Case to NPs in its vicinity (Transitive) V assigns objective Case to NPs in its vicinity P assigns objective Case to NPs in its vicinity () IP She I V NP... met me (2) a. For him to leave suddenly was foolish. b. * For he to leave suddenly was foolish. c. * For his to leave suddenly was foolish. So: Finite Infl assigns subjective Case to the subject, but nonfinite Infl does not.

The explanation, then: for assigns objective Case finite Infl assigns subjective Case nonfinite Infl does not assign Case at all overt NPs need Case. (temporarily suppose that) PRO needs not to get Case. () Case Filter *NP if NP has phonetic content and has no Case. What it means to be in the vicinity of a Case-assigner: Government (4) PP P P NP V NP to me meet me (5) CP C C IP for me I [ fin] to (6) Government (first statement) α governs β iff i) α is an X category (that is, α is a head) ii) α c-commands β. (7) C-command α c-commands β iff i) the first branching node dominating α also dominates β ii) α does not dominate β. (8) Minimality Condition In the configuration [ XP X [ YP Y ZP ] ] X does not govern ZP. (9)... X YP X does not govern ZP. Spec Y Y does govern ZP (it s closer). Y ZP... (40) Government α governs β iff i) α is an X category (that is, α is a head) ii) α c-commands β iii) Minimality is respected. In English, there appears to be an additional constraint: An NP can only receive Case if it is (string) adjacent to the Case-assigner. (4) a. * John makes frequently mistakes. b. John frequently makes mistakes. (42) a. John knocked repeatedly on the door. b. John repeatedly knocked on the door. (4) a. John knocked on the door repeatedly b. John knocked t i repeatedly [on the door] i. (44) a. Mary gave the book to John. b. * Mary gave to John the book. Subjective case and Spec-Head agreement (45) IP She I... Here, Infl governs, but does not govern the NP in its specifier.

Two approaches have been taken to this in the past: Redefine c-command such that Infl c-commands the NP too. Suppose that Infl assigns Case via a mechanism other than government. (46) IP He [sg] I -s [sg] V NP eat lunch (47) Spec-Head Agreement A head (X ) and its specifier (SpecXP) must agree in relevant features. We said that person, number, gender features (φ-features) were relevant in terms of agreement. We can add to that [subjective Case], which is relevant for Case assignment. Issues of Objective Case (48) a. The boy relies [ PP on the girl]. b. * The boy relies. Ouhalla uses the term transitive to refer to verbs which assign Case. In this sense, rely is an intransitive verb although it still requires an argument. (49) a. I listened *(to) him. listen: intransitive b. I heard him. hear: transitive We also find examples where verbs assign Case to something which is not its argument at all: Exceptional Case Marking (ECM). (50) a. Mary believes [John to be intelligent]. Embedded subject gets b. Mary believes [him to be intelligent]. objective Case c. * Mary believes [he to be intelligent]. d. e. Mary sincerely believes [him to be intelligent]. * Mary believes sincerely [him to be intelligent]. Adjacency (5) [For him to leave suddenly] would be foolish. (52)... V IP believe him I [ fin] to... (5) a. Mary considers [ AP John [ A intelligent]]. b. Mary considers [ AP him [ A intelligent]]. c. * Mary considers [ AP he [ A intelligent]]. d. Mary sincerely considers [ AP him [ A intelligent]]. e. * Mary considers sincerely [ AP him [ A intelligent]]. (54)... V AP considers NP A him A intelligent (55) *... V CP C C governs the NP John, so V can t. C IP John I[ fin] to...

Possessive Case and the DP hypothesis (56) a. His house b. Mary s translation of the book. (57) DP DP D Mary s D NP [GEN] N N PP translation of the book D here is for Determiner; this is a Determiner Phrase. (58) DP IP subject D subject I D NP I N N complement V object Gerundive phrases: (59) a. [Mary s watching TV] annoys her roommates. b. Her roommates are against [Mary s watching TV]. (60) DP DP D Mary s D # watching TV Incidentally, pronouns (despite their name) are also of category D. (6) DP D D we (62) a. You politicians are all alike. b. We linguists know the truth. c. People trust us linguists. (6) DP D D NP we N N linguists Ouhalla glosses over something which might be confusing Under the DP hypothesis DPs receive Case (rather than NPs). The genitive (possessive) Case is assigned to SpecDP by Spec-Head agreement (D has a feature [GEN] which agrees with a genitive Case DP in SpecDP). The case of the whole DP, however, is reflected in a pronoun in D. (D has a feature [ACC] which reflects the case assigned to the whole DP). (64) I saw [ DP Mary s homework]. Here, Mary s homework, the whole DP has accusative Case (cf. I saw him). Hence, D has an [Acc] feature (assigned by the verb to the whole DP). However, Mary s (in SpecDP) has genitive Case (assigned by D via Spec-Head agreement). Hence, D also has a [GEN] feature. It appears that in general, when D is spelled out as a pronoun, it can t assign genitive Case (doesn t have the [Gen] feature): *John admires Carol s us linguists. Head-movement in DPs (65) a. The army totally destroyed the city. b. * The army destroyed totally the city.

(66) a. The army s total destruction of the city b. * The army s destruction total of the city c. John s unfounded allegations d. * John s allegations unfounded e. f. People s continuous donations to the fund. * People s donations continuous to the fund. Case and movement (67) a. John i seems [ IP t i to be happy]. b. It seems [ CP that [ IP John is happy]]. c. * It seems [ IP John to be happy]. So, we have two reasons to move John in (67a): i) To satisfy the EPP, ii) to get Case on John. In raising constructions (e.g., seems) the DP moves because if it didn t it would violate the Case Filter. Passives and unaccusatives: (68) [The book] i was written t i. Attaching passive en/-ed to a verb removes ( absorbs ) the verb s ability to assign accusative Case. Unaccusative verbs: (69) [The vase] i broke t i. (70) Burzio s Generalization A verb (with an object) Case-marks its object iff it θ-marks (i.e. assigns a θ-role to) its subject. (72) a. IP QP i I Q DP I all the travelers should t i V PP drink from the well b. IP DP i I the travelers Incidentally: Movement and chains I should QP Q t i V PP all drink from the well This means that V can only assign Case via government and Infl can only assign Case via Spec-Head agreement. (7) Case Requirement A chain is Case-marked if it contains exactly one Case-marked position. (74) a. * John seems is happy b. * [John] i seems [ t i is happy]. (75) a. What i did John see t i? b. John suspects everyone. b. LF: [ IP [everyone] i [ IP John suspects t i ]] The -internal subject hypothesis (7) a. All the travelers should drink from the well. b. The travelers should all drink from the well.