Model theory, algebraic dynamics and local fields

Similar documents
Lecture 2: Syntax. January 24, 2018

The theory of integration says that the natural map

Model theory, algebraic dynamics and local fields

Model theory, stability, applications

VAUGHT S THEOREM: THE FINITE SPECTRUM OF COMPLETE THEORIES IN ℵ 0. Contents

Introduction to Model Theory

Model theory, algebraic dynamics and local fields

MODEL THEORY FOR ALGEBRAIC GEOMETRY

2010 SUMMER COURSE ON MODEL THEORY: CHAPTER 1

and this makes M into an R-module by (1.2). 2

Solutions to Unique Readability Homework Set 30 August 2011

This is logically equivalent to the conjunction of the positive assertion Minimal Arithmetic and Representability

Model Theory MARIA MANZANO. University of Salamanca, Spain. Translated by RUY J. G. B. DE QUEIROZ

1 Differentiable manifolds and smooth maps

ClC (X ) : X ω X } C. (11)

More Model Theory Notes

tp(c/a) tp(c/ab) T h(m M ) is assumed in the background.

Higher dimensional dynamical Mordell-Lang problems

Speirs, Martin. Autumn 2013

Model Theory and Modules, Granada

A MODEL-THEORETIC PROOF OF HILBERT S NULLSTELLENSATZ

Math 225A Model Theory. Speirs, Martin

Algebras with finite descriptions

THE ABSOLUTE MORDELL-LANG CONJECTURE IN POSITIVE CHARACTERISTIC. 1. Introduction

Propositional and Predicate Logic - XIII

Model theory of correspondences

Between proof theory and model theory Three traditions in logic: Syntactic (formal deduction)

FOUNDATIONS OF ALGEBRAIC GEOMETRY CLASS 24

Syntactic Characterisations in Model Theory

Propositional and Predicate Logic - VII

Model Theory of the Exponentiation: Abstract

Course 311: Michaelmas Term 2005 Part III: Topics in Commutative Algebra

Chapter 3. Introducing Groups

Axiomatic set theory. Chapter Why axiomatic set theory?

ALGEBRAIC GROUPS. Disclaimer: There are millions of errors in these notes!

Lecture 1: Overview. January 24, 2018

CS 468: Computational Topology Group Theory Fall b c b a b a c b a c b c c b a

HOW DO ULTRAFILTERS ACT ON THEORIES? THE CUT SPECTRUM AND TREETOPS

We begin with a standard definition from model theory.

Topos Theory. Lectures 17-20: The interpretation of logic in categories. Olivia Caramello. Topos Theory. Olivia Caramello.

Handbook of Logic and Proof Techniques for Computer Science

Fundamentals of Model Theory

Categories of imaginaries for additive structures

The Axiom of Infinity, Quantum Field Theory, and Large Cardinals. Paul Corazza Maharishi University

CHAPTER 2. FIRST ORDER LOGIC

Definability in fields Lecture 1: Undecidabile arithmetic, decidable geometry

Hilbert s Nustellensatz: Inner Model Theory: Ahmed T Khalil. Elliot Glazer. REU Advisor: Dr. Grigor Sargsyan. A Model-Theoretic Approach

ISAAC GOLDBRING AND THOMAS SINCLAIR

1 Notations and Statement of the Main Results

Summer Algebraic Geometry Seminar

Unbounded quantifiers and strong axioms in topos theory

Exploring the Exotic Setting for Algebraic Geometry

MODEL THEORY OF DIFFERENCE FIELDS

Boolean Algebras, Boolean Rings and Stone s Representation Theorem

Geometric motivic integration

Chapter 4. Basic Set Theory. 4.1 The Language of Set Theory

p-jets and Uniform Unramified Manin-Mumford

3. The Sheaf of Regular Functions

Lecture 9. Model theory. Consistency, independence, completeness, categoricity of axiom systems. Expanded with algebraic view.

CONSTRUCTION OF THE REAL NUMBERS.

Advances in the theory of fixed points in many-valued logics

CHEVALLEY S THEOREM AND COMPLETE VARIETIES

2. Introduction to commutative rings (continued)

Foundations of Mathematics

Classification of definable groupoids and Zariski geometries

Introduction to Kleene Algebras

WUCT121. Discrete Mathematics. Numbers

What are the recursion theoretic properties of a set of axioms? Understanding a paper by William Craig Armando B. Matos

MAGIC Set theory. lecture 1

2 C. A. Gunter ackground asic Domain Theory. A poset is a set D together with a binary relation v which is reexive, transitive and anti-symmetric. A s

via Topos Theory Olivia Caramello University of Cambridge The unification of Mathematics via Topos Theory Olivia Caramello

cse541 LOGIC FOR COMPUTER SCIENCE

HOMOLOGY THEORIES INGRID STARKEY

LINDSTRÖM S THEOREM SALMAN SIDDIQI

First-Order Logic. 1 Syntax. Domain of Discourse. FO Vocabulary. Terms

Π 0 1-presentations of algebras

Part II. Logic and Set Theory. Year

Three notions of geometry

Equational Logic. Chapter Syntax Terms and Term Algebras

Boolean Algebra CHAPTER 15

EXAMPLES AND EXERCISES IN BASIC CATEGORY THEORY

October 12, Complexity and Absoluteness in L ω1,ω. John T. Baldwin. Measuring complexity. Complexity of. concepts. to first order.

Boolean Algebra and Propositional Logic

3. Only sequences that were formed by using finitely many applications of rules 1 and 2, are propositional formulas.

Herbrand Theorem, Equality, and Compactness

What is the Langlands program all about?

About the relationship between formal logic and complexity classes

MATH 101B: ALGEBRA II PART A: HOMOLOGICAL ALGEBRA

Amalgamation and the finite model property

Boolean Algebra and Propositional Logic

On expansions of the real field by complex subgroups

CHAPTER 0 PRELIMINARY MATERIAL. Paul Vojta. University of California, Berkeley. 18 February 1998

Yuriy Drozd. Intriduction to Algebraic Geometry. Kaiserslautern 1998/99

Formal power series rings, inverse limits, and I-adic completions of rings

Reconsidering MacLane. Peter M. Hines

Mathematics 114L Spring 2018 D.A. Martin. Mathematical Logic

2.2 Lowenheim-Skolem-Tarski theorems

University of Oxford, Michaelis November 16, Categorical Semantics and Topos Theory Homotopy type theor

FINITE MODEL THEORY (MATH 285D, UCLA, WINTER 2017) LECTURE NOTES IN PROGRESS

On The Classification of Geometries of Strongly Minim. Minimal Structures

Transcription:

Model theory, algebraic dynamics and local fields Thomas Scanlon University of California, Berkeley 7 June 2010 Thomas Scanlon (University of California, Berkeley) Model theory, algebraic dynamics and local fields 7 June 2010 1 / 16

Model theory as a mathematical tool In spite of its successes, the Model theory did not enter into a tool box of mathematicians and even many of mathematicians working on Motivic integrations are content to use the results logicians without understanding the details of the proofs. Thomas Scanlon (University of California, Berkeley) Model theory, algebraic dynamics and local fields 7 June 2010 2 / 16

Kazhdan on model theory I don t know any mathematician who did not start as a logician and for whom it was easy and natural to learn the Model theory. Often the experience of learning of the Model theory is similar to the one of learning of Physics: for a [short] while everything is so simple and so easily reformulated in familiar terms that there is nothing to learn but suddenly one find himself in a place when Model theoreticians jump from a tussock to a hummock while we mathematicians don t see where to put a foot and are at a complete loss. Thomas Scanlon (University of California, Berkeley) Model theory, algebraic dynamics and local fields 7 June 2010 3 / 16

Kazhdan on model theory, continued So we have two questions: a) Why is the Model theory so useful in different areas of Mathematics? b) Why is it so difficult for mathematicians to learn it? But really these two questions are almost the same- it is difficult to learn the Model theory since it appeals to different intuition. But exactly this new outlook leads to the successes of the Model theory. Thomas Scanlon (University of California, Berkeley) Model theory, algebraic dynamics and local fields 7 June 2010 4 / 16

What kinds of material will be covered? With this tutorial I shall discuss some essential results from model theory which belong in every mathematician s tool box (eg the compactness theorem), some theorems in algebraic model theory which have direct applications to problems in number theory and geometry (eg the trichotomy theorem for difference fields), and the proofs of some theorems in Diophantine geometry using methods from model theory (eg Pila s proof of the André-Oort conjecture) Thomas Scanlon (University of California, Berkeley) Model theory, algebraic dynamics and local fields 7 June 2010 5 / 16

What will be omitted? Even with the parts of model theory most directly related to problems in Diophantine geometry, I will address only a small part of the theory. I will say a little about model theory as a subject in its own right, but I will focus on its interface with number theory. As such, we risk missing the source of the alternative intuitions provided by model theory. I will say nothing (other than to acknowledge now their existence) about the spectacular recent theorems of Hrushovski on approximate subgroups and of Goldbring on Hilbert s Fifth Problem. Thomas Scanlon (University of California, Berkeley) Model theory, algebraic dynamics and local fields 7 June 2010 6 / 16

Languages and structures A model M of a theory T is an L (τ)-structure for some signature τ which models every sentence from T. A signature τ consists of three sets C τ (constant symbols), F τ (function symbols), and R τ (relation symbols) together with functions arity : F τ Z + and arity : R τ Z + An L (τ)-structure M (sometimes called an interpretation) consists of a non-empty set M, for each c C τ an element c M M, for each f F a function f M : M arity(f ) M, and for each relation symbol R R τ a set R M =: R(M) M arity(r). Thomas Scanlon (University of California, Berkeley) Model theory, algebraic dynamics and local fields 7 June 2010 7 / 16

Example:Language of ordered rings The signature τ for the language of ordered rings has two constant symbols 0 and 1, three function symbols +, and where arity(+) = arity( ) = 2 and arity( ) = 1, and a single relation symbol with arity( ) = 2. Any ordered ring is naturally an L (τ)-structure, though we may have to write our functions in a somewhat nonstandard form in order to conform with the definition of an L (τ)-structure. For example, to regard R as an L (τ)-structure we would write + R (x, y) = x + y where + on the right is the usual addition operation. Just because we call τ the signature of ordered rings, there is no reason an L (τ)-structure must actually be an ordered ring. Thomas Scanlon (University of California, Berkeley) Model theory, algebraic dynamics and local fields 7 June 2010 8 / 16

Languages Given a signature τ we build the language L (τ) associated to τ by recursion. First, we define the set of terms, T (τ), to be the smallest set containing C τ, the set of variables {x i : i N}, and closed under the rule that if f F τ, t 1,..., t arity(f ) T (τ), then so is f (t 1,..., t arity(f ) ). Next, we define the atomic formulae to be the expressions of the form t = s and R(t 1,..., t n ) where t, s, t 1,..., t n T (τ), R R τ, and n = arity(r). Finally, the language L (τ) is the smallest set containing all of the atomic formulae and closed under the operations φ L (τ), then φ L (τ), φ, ψ L (τ), then (φ&ψ) L (τ) and (φ ψ) L (τ), and φ L (τ) and i N, then ( x i )φ L (τ) and ( x i )φ L (τ). Thomas Scanlon (University of California, Berkeley) Model theory, algebraic dynamics and local fields 7 June 2010 9 / 16

Truth For an L (τ)-structure M and sentence φ of L (τ) we define the relation M = φ (read M models φ or φ is true in M ) by recursion on the construction of φ. Allow me to omit the formal definition, but I will note one place where one should take care. If φ = ( x i )ψ, then the meaning of M = φ should be that there is some element a of M for which ψ is true of a in M. To formalize this, we ask that there be an expansion of M to a structure M in a language with a new constant symbol c and that M = ψ(c/x i ) where ψ(c/x i ) is obtained from φ by substituting c for each free occurrence of x i. Given a set T of L (τ)-sentences we say that M = T if for every φ T we have M = T Thomas Scanlon (University of California, Berkeley) Model theory, algebraic dynamics and local fields 7 June 2010 10 / 16

Examples The class of groups is axiomatizable in L (, e) by the usual axioms of group theory properly formalized. For example associativity is expressed by ( x 1 )( x 2 )( x 3 ) (x 1, (x 2, x 3 )) = ( (x 1, x 2 ), x 3 ) The class of infinite groups may be axiomatized by the above sentence and the infinite set of sentences expressing that the cardinality is at least n for each natural number n: ( x 1 )( x 2 ) ( x n ) i<j (x i = x j ) (Here we write i I φ i for the conjunction of all the formulae φ i indexed by i I. The class of cyclic groups is not axiomatizable in first-order logic. Thomas Scanlon (University of California, Berkeley) Model theory, algebraic dynamics and local fields 7 June 2010 11 / 16

Definable sets For an L (τ)-formula φ(x 1,..., x n ) with free variables amongst x 1,..., x n and an L (σ)-structure M the set defined by φ in M, φ(m) := {(a 1,..., a n ) M n : M = φ(a 1,..., a n )} While we speak of a definable set, we really think of a definable set as an assignment (functor with the appropriate notion of morphism) from the category of L (τ)-structures to the category of sets, M φ(m). If we wish to specify the actual set of points φ(m) we may speak of a definable set in M. We usually implicitly allow the possibility that the formula φ uses parameters from the model. If we need to restrict the set of possible parameters to some set A, then we say that the set is A-definable. Thomas Scanlon (University of California, Berkeley) Model theory, algebraic dynamics and local fields 7 June 2010 12 / 16

Elementary extensions The right notion of morphism to make a definable set a functor is that of an elementary embedding. Definition Given two L (τ)-structures M and N an elementary embedding f : M N is given by a function f : M N having the property that for any L (τ) formula φ(x 1,..., x n ) with free variables amongst x 1,..., x n and tuple a M n we have M = φ(a) N = φ(f (a)). We write M N when M N and the inclusion is an elementary embedding. Thomas Scanlon (University of California, Berkeley) Model theory, algebraic dynamics and local fields 7 June 2010 13 / 16

Examples of elementary embeddings If f : M N is an isomorphism, then it is an elementary embedding. The map Φ : C(t) C(t) given by f (t) f (t 2 ) is isomorphism between C(t) and the image of Φ, but it is is not elementary as C(t) = ( x)x 2 = t but C(t) = ( x)x 2 = Φ(t). It follows from the Hilbert Nullstellensatz that is K L is an extension of algebraically closed fields, then the extension is elementary. Thomas Scanlon (University of California, Berkeley) Model theory, algebraic dynamics and local fields 7 June 2010 14 / 16

Examples of definable sets If (K, +,, 0, 1) is an algebraically closed field, then a definable in K is simply a Zariski-constructible set. An -definable set is a Zariski-constructible set defined over Z (in the algebraic geometric sense). If τ is a signature having only a binary relation symbol R, then an L (τ)-structure is a directed graph. In any such graph, the set of points with at most two out arrows is definable, but the set of points with the same number of in arrows as out arrows is not definable. In a group (G,, e) for any a G the centralizer of a in G is definable with a as a parameter, but the group generated by a is not generally definable. Thomas Scanlon (University of California, Berkeley) Model theory, algebraic dynamics and local fields 7 June 2010 15 / 16

More examples: periodic points Let k be any Noetherian commutative ring and X A n k be a closed subscheme of affine n-space over the integers. Then the associated functor of points h X : k Alg Set may be identified with a definable set (relative to the theory of k-algebras). However, it is not the case that every definable set has this form. For example, if φ(x) := ( y)y 2 = x, then there are k-algebras R for which φ(r) = {a R : ( b R)b 2 = a} is not the set of R-valued points of any k-scheme. If f : X X is a regular self-map and n Z + then the set of points of exact period n is definable, but unless the order of the f -periodic points is uniformly bounded, the set of periodic points is not definable, even though for specific k-algebras R the set of f -periodic points in X (R) might be definable for accidental reasons. Thomas Scanlon (University of California, Berkeley) Model theory, algebraic dynamics and local fields 7 June 2010 16 / 16