Bell s Theorem. Ben Dribus. June 8, Louisiana State University

Similar documents
Einstein-Podolsky-Rosen paradox and Bell s inequalities

Introduction to Bell s theorem: the theory that solidified quantum mechanics

EPR Paradox Solved by Special Theory of Relativity

Quantum Entanglement. Chapter Introduction. 8.2 Entangled Two-Particle States

EPR Paradox and Bell s Inequality

J = L + S. to this ket and normalize it. In this way we get expressions for all the kets

Modern Physics notes Spring 2007 Paul Fendley Lecture 27

EPR Paradox and Bell Inequalities

Photons uncertainty removes Einstein-Podolsky-Rosen paradox. Abstract

Cosmology Lecture 2 Mr. Kiledjian

Identical Particles in Quantum Mechanics

Singlet State Correlations

B. BASIC CONCEPTS FROM QUANTUM THEORY 93

Closing the Debates on Quantum Locality and Reality: EPR Theorem, Bell's Theorem, and Quantum Information from the Brown-Twiss Vantage

Hardy s Paradox. Chapter Introduction

String Theory. Quantum Mechanics and Gravity: Cliff Burgess, McGill. The start of a beautiful relationship?

226 My God, He Plays Dice! Entanglement. Chapter This chapter on the web informationphilosopher.com/problems/entanglement

Contextuality and the Kochen-Specker Theorem. Interpretations of Quantum Mechanics

Has CHSH-inequality any relation to EPR-argument?

Topic 3: Bohr, Einstein, and the EPR experiment

NON HILBERTIAN QUANTUM MECHANICS ON THE FINITE GALOIS FIELD

Q8 Lecture. State of Quantum Mechanics EPR Paradox Bell s Thm. Physics 201: Lecture 1, Pg 1

A single quantum cannot be teleported

Lecture 29 Relevant sections in text: 3.9

A proof of Bell s inequality in quantum mechanics using causal interactions

Why quantum field theory?

Introduction to Quantum Mechanics

1 1D Schrödinger equation: Particle in an infinite box

Solving the Einstein Podolsky Rosen puzzle: The origin of non-locality in Aspect-type experiments

Bell s inequalities and their uses

Lecture 14, Thurs March 2: Nonlocal Games

1 1D Schrödinger equation: Particle in an infinite box

Lecture 4. QUANTUM MECHANICS FOR MULTIPLE QUBIT SYSTEMS

Problems with/failures of QM

A No-Go Result on Common Cause Approaches via Hardy s Paradox

Hilbert Space, Entanglement, Quantum Gates, Bell States, Superdense Coding.

Deterministic Entanglement Leads to Arrow of Time, Quantum Mechanics, Freewill and Origin of Information

The nature of Reality: Einstein-Podolsky-Rosen Argument in QM

Why we need quantum gravity and why we don t have it

Particle Physics Dr. Alexander Mitov Handout 2 : The Dirac Equation

Basics on quantum information

The controlled-not (CNOT) gate exors the first qubit into the second qubit ( a,b. a,a + b mod 2 ). Thus it permutes the four basis states as follows:

David Bohm s Hidden Variables

Particle Physics. Michaelmas Term 2011 Prof. Mark Thomson. Handout 2 : The Dirac Equation. Non-Relativistic QM (Revision)

Attempts at relativistic QM

Fundamental Interactions (Forces) of Nature

Incompatibility Paradoxes

Lecture 2: Introduction to Quantum Mechanics

ON THE EINSTEIN PODOLSKY ROSEN PARADOX* I. Introduction

Basics on quantum information

Quantum Mechanics: Fundamentals

What is spin? Thomas Pope and Werner Hofer. School of Chemistry Newcastle University. Web: wernerhofer.eu

Quantum Field Theory

A very efficient two-density approach to atomistic simulations and a proof of principle for small atoms and molecules

Entanglement. arnoldzwicky.org. Presented by: Joseph Chapman. Created by: Gina Lorenz with adapted PHYS403 content from Paul Kwiat, Brad Christensen

The Einstein-Podolsky-Rosen thought experiment and Bell s theorem

Logical difficulty from combining counterfactuals in the GHZ-Bell theorems

Laboratory 1: Entanglement & Bell s Inequalities

COLLEGE PHYSICS. Chapter 30 ATOMIC PHYSICS

Bell s Theorem...What?! Entanglement and Other Puzzles

Lecture 01. Introduction to Elementary Particle Physics

A review on quantum teleportation based on: Teleporting an unknown quantum state via dual classical and Einstein- Podolsky-Rosen channels

Logical difficulty from combining counterfactuals in the GHZ-Bell theorems

Quantum Entanglement, Quantum Cryptography, Beyond Quantum Mechanics, and Why Quantum Mechanics Brad Christensen Advisor: Paul G.

The Einstein-Podolsky-Rosen thought-experiment and Bell s theorem

3 Quantization of the Dirac equation

Quantum Entanglement, Beyond Quantum Mechanics, and Why Quantum Mechanics

ON EPR PARADOX, BELL S INEQUALITIES AND EXPERIMENTS THAT PROVE NOTHING

QUANTUM MECHANICS. Franz Schwabl. Translated by Ronald Kates. ff Springer

Quantum Field Theory

Quantum Field Theory

EPR paradox, Bell inequality, etc.

Quantum Physics & Reality

Bell s Theorem 1964 Local realism is in conflict with quantum mechanics

9 Fundamental Nonlocality

Lecture notes for QFT I (662)

QM and Angular Momentum

Quantum Gravity and Entanglement

THE DELAYED CHOICE QUANTUM EXPERIMENT

The Relativistic Quantum World

Understanding Long-Distance Quantum Correlations

conventions and notation

6.896 Quantum Complexity Theory September 9, Lecture 2

Violation of Bell Inequalities

arxiv:quant-ph/ v4 17 Jan 2005

Classical Bell s Inequalities. Vesselin C. Noninski

QUANTUM ENTANGLEMENT AND ITS ASPECTS. Dileep Dhakal Masters of Science in Nanomolecular Sciences

3. Quantum Mechanics in 3D

1.1.1 Bell Inequality - Spin correlation

Quantum Mechanics and No-Hidden Variable Theories

Continuous quantum states, Particle on a line and Uncertainty relations

Lecture 20: Bell inequalities and nonlocality

Solving the instantaneous response paradox of entangled particles using the time of events theory

Quantum Computing. Vraj Parikh B.E.-G.H.Patel College of Engineering & Technology, Anand (Affiliated with GTU) Abstract HISTORY OF QUANTUM COMPUTING-

Physics 280 Quantum Mechanics Lecture III

3/10/11. Which interpreta/on sounds most reasonable to you? PH300 Modern Physics SP11

Today s Outline - April 18, C. Segre (IIT) PHYS Spring 2017 April 18, / 23

ON THE EINSTEIN PODOLSKY ROSEN PARADOX* ]. S. BELLt Department of Physics, University of Wisconsin, Madison, Wisconsin

The Building Blocks of Nature

Review of Quantum Mechanics, cont.

Transcription:

Bell s Theorem Ben Dribus Louisiana State University June 8, 2012

Introduction. Quantum Theory makes predictions that challenge intuitive notions of physical reality. Einstein and others were sufficiently troubled by these predictions to suggest in the 1930 s that quantum theory is incomplete. The missing data was thought to be described by hidden variable theories. In 1964, John Bell showed how to experimentally test for hidden variables. Experiments based on Bell s Theorem seem to rule out hidden variables and support quantum theory. Researchers studying the foundations of quantum theory are still trying to understand the implications of Bell s theorem.

Local Realism. From the dawn of the scientific revolution until the beginning of the twentieth century, most scientists accepted the following two principles of local realism without question: Locality: A physical system is directly influenced only by its immediate environment; distant influences are always mediated by the immediate environment. Counterfactual Definiteness: It makes sense to talk about properties of a system without measuring them. For example, without measuring the position of a particle, it makes sense to say it has some position.

Quantum Theory I. Beginning in the first years of the twentieth century, and particularly during the 1920 s and 1930 s, local realism was seriously challenged and eventually almost completely overturned by quantum theory, which is based on the following principles: The state of a physical system is represented by a vector ψ in a Hilbert space. Observable quantities such as position and momentum are represented by self-adjoint operators on the Hilbert space. (continued on next slide)

Quantum Theory II. If a system is in a state ψ, then measurement of the observable quantity corresponding to the operator Ω yields one of the eigenvalues of Ω. The probability of obtaining a particular value depends on the projections of the state vector ψ onto the various eigenspaces of Ω, and the measurement immediately alters the state to the projection of ψ on the eigenspace corresponding to the measured eigenvalue. The evolution of the state vector is described by the Schrödinger equation: where H is the Hamiltonian. i ψ = H ψ t

Quantum Theory III: Uncertainty Principle. Operators representing two observable quantities may not commute (example: Pauli spin matrices) The Heisenberg uncertainty principle states that it is impossible to simultaneously know precise values of two observable quantities corresponding to noncommuting operators.

Quantum Theory III: Violation of Local Realism. The quantum theory of entangled states seems to violate both counterfactual definiteness and locality. Counterfactual definiteness is violated because of the uncertainty principle. Locality is violated because measurement of one particle instantaneously determines properties of the other.

Why is Violation of Locality a Problem? If distant phenomena can directly effect a system without propagation through the intervening spacetime, then influence can travel at arbitrary speeds. Einstein s special theory of relativity implies that superluminal communication, the transfer of information at speeds faster than the speed of light, can result in violation of causality.

Superluminal Communication. t t Superluminal motion in the (x, t)-frame can result in backward time-travel in the (x, t )-frame and vice versa Future light cone of A Successive generations in (x, t )-frame B x A A Successive generations in (x, t)-frame Past light cone of A x

Is Quantum Theory Complete? At first glance, it seems that a hidden variable theory could rescue both counterfactual definiteness and locality in the quantum theory of entangled states. Counterfactual definiteness would be preserved because the hidden variable would contain the missing information obscured by the uncertainty principle. Locality would be preserved because the existence of well-defined properties (specified by the hidden variable) for each separate part of the entangled state would eliminate the need to hypothesize that the properties of one particle are instantaneously determined by measuring the properties of the other.

The EPR Paper. In 1935, Einstein, Podolsky, and Rosen authored a paper entitled Can Quantum-Mechanical Description of Physical Reality Be Considered Complete? Their conclusion was NO. Their argument was based on a thought experiment involving entangled states.

Physical Background I: Entangled Pairs. Under appropriate circumstances a high-energy photon can convert into an electron and positron. This is symbolized by the equation γ e + e + where γ is the photon, e the electron, and e + the positron. This process is called pair production. Pair production is often represented by diagrams like the following, called Feynman diagrams: e e + γ

Physical Background II: Spin. The electron e is a fermion, a type of particle with intrinsic angular momentum, called spin. the measured value S l (e ) of the electron spin along an arbitrary axis l always has a value of ± 2, where is Planck s reduced constant. The positron is the antiparticle corresponding to the electron, and thus has the same spin magnitude. Photons are bosons with zero spin. By conservation of angular momentum, the spin measurements of the electron-positron pair along any given axis must be equal and opposite.

Physical Background III: Choice of Coordinates. Choose coordinates x, y, and z such that the Pauli spin matrices take the form σ x = ( 0 1 1 0 ) ( 0 i, σ y = i 0 ) σ z = ( 1 0 0 1 ) Recall that S x (e ) means the spin of the electron e measured along the x-axis. In this way, the measured values S x, S y, and S z correspond to the operators σ x, σ y, and σ z.

Physical Background III: The Entangled State. In the x, y, z coordinate system, the entangled state of the electron-positron pair is given by ψ = 1 ) ( + x x x + x 2 where + x 1 2 ( 1 1 ), x 1 ( 2 1 1 )

The EPR Experiment I. Produce an electron-positron pair in the state ψ and separate the two particles by a large distance. If S x (e ) is measured, this determines S x (e + ) without performing another measurement, by conservation of momentum. The same is true for any other axis; in particular, the z-axis.

The EPR Experiment II. A z Large spatial separation B z x e e + source x

EPR Argument I: Spin Determined at the Source? Now reason as follows: First suppose that the value of S x (e ), and therefore S x (e + ), is determined at the source, when the particles are first produced. If now S z (e ) is measured instead of S x (e ), this yields a definite value of S z (e + ). There are two possibilities: 1. The positron e + has precise simultaneous values of S x and S z. This violates the uncertainty principle. 2. Measuring S z (e ), thus obtaining S z (e + ), instantaneously affects the spin of e + along the x-axis in such a way that e + no longer has a precise value of S x. This violates locality.

EPR Argument II: Spin Determined by Measurement? Suppose instead that the value of S x (e ), and therefore S x (e ), is only determined when S x (e ) is actually measured. This immediately violates counterfactual definiteness. Further, the measurement of S x (e ) instantaneously affects the spin of e + along the x-axis in such a way that the two spins cancel, so locality is violated as well.

Uncertainty Principle or Local Realism? One way or the other, either the uncertainty principle or local realism is violated. Einstein, Podolsky, and Rosen chose to believe local realism. They concluded that their argument proves the incompleteness of quantum mechanics. In this view, the uncertainty principle is a shortcoming of quantum theory, not a fundamental principle of nature.

Bell s Theorem I: Hidden Variables Detectable! In a 1964 paper, John Bell showed that the presence of hidden variables has experimental consequences. Bell s result applies to hidden variables affecting an entangled system at the source of entanglement. For simplicity, we will consider the case where the entangled system is an electron-positron pair in the state ψ = 1 ) ( + x x x + x 2 Bell s result is a statistical one, so we need to produce many copies of this state (note that this is allowed!).

Setup for Bell s Theorem. Imagine that two distant observers, A and B, make measurements on the copies of ψ. Observer A measures e. She uses one of two detector settings, either a or a. For example, a and a might be spin measurements along different axes. Observer B measures e +. He uses one of two detector settings, either b or b. For example, b and b might be spin measurements along different axes.

Adding Hidden Variables. To include the possibility of hidden variables, we explicitly take the measurements to depend on an additional variable λ as well as the detector settings. λ is the hidden variable. It affects the entangled pair at the source. We denote by A(a, λ) the value measured by A with detector setting a and hidden variable value λ. Similarly for A(a, λ), B(b, λ), and B(b, λ). The value of λ may differ for different pairs. Formally, λ belongs to a probability space Λ with probability measure ρ(λ) giving the probability that a representative pair has hidden variable value λ.

Bell s Theorem II: Bell s Inequality. Bell proved an inequality about the correlations among the measurements performed by A and B, assuming the presence of a hidden variable. The form of Bell s inequality we will use is 2 C 2 where, C, called the correlation, is given by C := C(A(a), B(b)) C(A(a), B(b ))+C(A(a ), B(b))+C(A(a ), B(b )) The hidden variable λ does not appear in this formula because the correlations are obtained by integrating over the probability space Λ. This is as it should be, since A and B cannot measure λ.

Quantum Theory Contradicts Bell s Inequality. Bell then specified a particular type of experiment for which quantum theory predicts a violation of Bell s inequality. We will examine the following experimental version: The detector setting a represents the measurement of the electron spin S z (e ). The detector setting a represents the measurement of the electron spin S x (e ). The detector settings b and b represent spin measurements along axes rotated by 135 with respect to the x, z coordinates.

Bell s Experimental Setup. A Large spatial separation B z x e e + 135 source x Value of hidden variable λ determined at the source z

Calculating the Quantum Correlations I. Next, we compute the values of the correlations among the measurements A(a), B(b), etc. predicted by quantum theory. A straightforward though slightly tedious calculation shows that = C(A(a), B(b)) = A(a)B(b) ( σ z I 1 ) I (σ x + σ z ) ψ ψ 2 = 1 2

Calculating the Quantum Correlations II. Similarly, and C(A(a, λ), B(b, λ)) = C(A(a, λ), B(b, λ)) = 1 2 Thus, the total correlation is This violates Bell s inequality. C(A(a, λ), B(b, λ)) = 1 2 C = 2 2

Experiments Seem to Support Quantum Theory. Bell s Theorem not only showed that a wide class of hidden variable theories disagree with quantum theory rather than merely supplementing it, but also indicated how to test which idea is right experimentally. Experimental tests involving optics (different than the experiment described here) have repeated seemed to show violation of Bell s inequality. At face value, this supports quantum theory and implies that local realism is false. However, not everyone is convinced.

Experimental Objections. To date, experimental tests of Bell s theorem are not as clean and straightforward as the hypothetical experiment involving entangled pairs. Interpretation of optical tests of Bell s theorem involve particular assumptions about the electromagnetic field that are generally believed to be true but are not essential to quantum theory. If these assumptions are false, existing experimental results could agree with both local realism and quantum theory.

Possible Interpretations I. The most popular and mainstream interpretation of Bell s Theorem and the associated experimental results is that quantum theory is true and local realism is false. As stated above, some scientists are not prepared to accept the experimental results because of possible experimental flaws or extra assumptions. Others have advocated nonlocal hidden variable theories. In such theories, counterfactual definiteness holds, but particles can exchange information at arbitrary speeds to produce the necessary correlations.

Possible Interpretations II. Another idea is that the histories of the particles do not agree at first, but the history is corrected (1984-style) before we can tell the difference. Superdeterminism would eliminate the need for instantaneous communication by simply specifying every detail of every event at the outset. Finally, it is possible that quantum nonlocality reflects small-scale non-manifold structure of spacetime. Let us explore this idea a little further.

A Property of Manifolds. Manifolds have the following obvious but nontrivial property: if there is one path between two points of a given length l, there are many other paths of length close to l between the two points. length l

What does Locality Really Mean? Consider again the locality principle as stated above: A physical system is directly influenced only by its immediate environment. For this statement to have any meaning, we must be able to define the immediate environment independently of actual influences among systems. In other words, we are assuming that the spacetime manifold has a metric structure independent of the causal structure of the universe. But spacetime may not even be a manifold on small scales! In this case, the principle of locality loses its meaning.

An Alternative View of Locality I. Consider the following alternative to the locality principle: The local environment of a system is the region of the universe that directly interacts with the system. This viewpoint turns the discussion on its head by redefining locality. It takes the causal structure to be fundamental, rather than the metric structure. In classical physics (general relativity), this definition is indistinguishable from the locality principle, since the causal and metric structures agree (we think!).

An Alternative View of Locality II. With this definition, entangled systems are always local, even though there may be only one short path between them, with every other path being long. Since no metric space has these properties, the phenomenon of entanglement is viewed as evidence of the non-manifold structure of spacetime at small scales.

Other Hints of Non-manifold Structure: Quantum Gravity. In quantum field theory, continuous fields are quantized to produce discrete particles. General Relativity describes the metric structure of spacetime itself as a continuous tensor field, but it is hard to quantize (if it is even correct). Presumably, a quantum theory of gravity would involve discrete units of spacetime; i.e. a non-manifold structure at small scales. Attempts in this direction include string theory, loop quantum gravity, causal dynamical triangulation, and more generally, discrete causal theory.

My Pet Idea: Discrete Causal Theory I. Discrete causal theory may be able to reconcile Bell s theorem and the accompanying experiment results with an appropriate version of locality. In particular, this would eliminate the troubling causal consequences of nonlocality. The following slide shows a model of an entangled system in a non-manifold-like discrete causal structure.

My Pet Idea: Discrete Causal Theory II. Manifold-like Non-manifold-like BDDCT

References. Bell, John. On the Einstein Podolsky Rosen Paradox, Physics 1 3, 195-200, Nov. 1964. Can Quantum-Mechanical Description of Physical Reality Be Considered Complete? Einstein, Podolsky, Rosen, Phys. Rev. 47, 777780 (1935) Principles of Quantum Mechanics, Shankar, Plenum Press, New York, 1980. Quantum Information, Barnet, Oxford University Press, 2009. Foundations of Discrete Causal Theory, Ben Dribus, 2011 (unpublished).