Ideal, First-kind Measurements in a Proposition-State Structure

Similar documents
The Square of Opposition in Orthomodular Logic

COMPACT ORTHOALGEBRAS

CONDITIONS THAT FORCE AN ORTHOMODULAR POSET TO BE A BOOLEAN ALGEBRA. 1. Basic notions

POSITIVE AND NEGATIVE CORRELATIONS FOR CONDITIONAL ISING DISTRIBUTIONS

Physical justification for using the tensor product to describe two quantum systems as one joint system

Equivalence of the Combinatorial Definition (Lecture 11)

EQUIVALENCE RELATIONS AND OPERATORS ON ORDERED ALGEBRAIC STRUCTURES. UNIVERSITÀ DEGLI STUDI DELL'INSUBRIA Via Ravasi 2, Varese, Italy

Atomic effect algebras with compression bases

DOCTORAL THESIS SIMION STOILOW INSTITUTE OF MATHEMATICS OF THE ROMANIAN ACADEMY BOOLEAN SUBALGEBRAS AND SPECTRAL AUTOMORPHISMS IN QUANTUM LOGICS

ON SPECTRAL THEORY IN EFFECT ALGEBRAS

Topological Test Spaces 1 Alexander Wilce Department of Mathematical Sciences, Susquehanna University Selinsgrove, Pa

Finite homogeneous and lattice ordered effect algebras

GENERALIZED DIFFERENCE POSETS AND ORTHOALGEBRAS. 0. Introduction

ON THE UNIQUENESS PROPERTY FOR PRODUCTS OF SYMMETRIC INVARIANT PROBABILITY MEASURES

Quantum logics with given centres and variable state spaces Mirko Navara 1, Pavel Ptak 2 Abstract We ask which logics with a given centre allow for en

ON MATCHINGS IN GROUPS

FUNCTION BASES FOR TOPOLOGICAL VECTOR SPACES. Yılmaz Yılmaz

Universal Algebra for Logics

Weak Relative Pseudo-Complements of Closure Operators

arxiv: v1 [math.ra] 1 Apr 2015

HOPF S DECOMPOSITION AND RECURRENT SEMIGROUPS. Josef Teichmann

Egoroff Theorem for Operator-Valued Measures in Locally Convex Cones

AN ALGEBRAIC APPROACH TO GENERALIZED MEASURES OF INFORMATION

arxiv: v1 [math-ph] 23 Jul 2010

Jónsson posets and unary Jónsson algebras

SIMPLE LOGICS FOR BASIC ALGEBRAS

Regular Actions on Generalized Polygons

ENUMERATION OF TREES AND ONE AMAZING REPRESENTATION OF THE SYMMETRIC GROUP. Igor Pak Harvard University

The seed order. Gabriel Goldberg. October 11, 2018

SELF-ADJOINTNESS OF DIRAC OPERATORS VIA HARDY-DIRAC INEQUALITIES

COINCIDENCE AND THE COLOURING OF MAPS

Math 249B. Geometric Bruhat decomposition

KODAIRA DIMENSION OF LEFSCHETZ FIBRATIONS OVER TORI

THE EQUATIONAL THEORIES OF REPRESENTABLE RESIDUATED SEMIGROUPS

Spectral Automorphisms in Quantum Logics

Positive operator valued measures covariant with respect to an irreducible representation

Morphisms of polar spaces

AW -Convergence and Well-Posedness of Non Convex Functions

Foundations of non-commutative probability theory

Introduction to the Mathematics of the XY -Spin Chain

Equational Logic. Chapter Syntax Terms and Term Algebras

Rough Approach to Fuzzification and Defuzzification in Probability Theory

k k would be reducible. But the zero locus of f in A n+1

P-Spaces and the Prime Spectrum of Commutative Semirings

Topological properties

be a sequence of positive integers with a n+1 a n lim inf n > 2. [α a n] α a n

arxiv: v1 [math.gr] 8 Nov 2008

Exponents in R of Elements in a Uniformly Complete Φ-Algebra

A CONTINUOUS MOVEMENT VERSION OF THE BANACH TARSKI PARADOX: A SOLUTION TO DE GROOT S PROBLEM

Why the Logical Disjunction in Quantum Logic is Not Classical

Rapporto di Ricerca CS G. Busetto, E. Jabara

Part V. 17 Introduction: What are measures and why measurable sets. Lebesgue Integration Theory

On the Statistical Meaning of Complex Numbers in Quantum Mechanics

Completely regular Bishop spaces

PREDICTABLE REPRESENTATION PROPERTY OF SOME HILBERTIAN MARTINGALES. 1. Introduction.

James J. Madden LSU, Baton Rouge. Dedication: To the memory of Paul Conrad.

A proof of Pohlke s theorem with an analytic determination of the reference trihedron

Gorenstein rings through face rings of manifolds.

On non negative solutions of some quasilinear elliptic inequalities

AN ABSTRACT DISINTEGRATION THEOREM

EXISTENCE OF STRONG SOLUTIONS OF FULLY NONLINEAR ELLIPTIC EQUATIONS

Notes on Ordered Sets

SUBLATTICES OF LATTICES OF ORDER-CONVEX SETS, III. THE CASE OF TOTALLY ORDERED SETS

Disjointness conditions in free products of. distributive lattices: An application of Ramsay's theorem. Harry Lakser< 1)

SYMMETRY OF POSITIVE SOLUTIONS OF SOME NONLINEAR EQUATIONS. M. Grossi S. Kesavan F. Pacella M. Ramaswamy. 1. Introduction

The category of linear modular lattices

A PROOF OF A CONVEX-VALUED SELECTION THEOREM WITH THE CODOMAIN OF A FRÉCHET SPACE. Myung-Hyun Cho and Jun-Hui Kim. 1. Introduction

(1.) For any subset P S we denote by L(P ) the abelian group of integral relations between elements of P, i.e. L(P ) := ker Z P! span Z P S S : For ea

Counting extremal lattices.

On Uniform Spaces with Invariant Nonstandard Hulls

Coreflections in Algebraic Quantum Logic

THE INVERSION OF A CLASS OF LINER OPERATORS

A SHORT AND CONSTRUCTIVE PROOF OF TARSKI S FIXED-POINT THEOREM

LECTURE: KOBORDISMENTHEORIE, WINTER TERM 2011/12; SUMMARY AND LITERATURE

Topology Proceedings. COPYRIGHT c by Topology Proceedings. All rights reserved.

AN APPROXIMATION THEOREM FOR MAPS INTO KAN FIBRATIONS

MGP versus Kochen-Specker condition in hidden variables theories

THE FORM SUM AND THE FRIEDRICHS EXTENSION OF SCHRÖDINGER-TYPE OPERATORS ON RIEMANNIAN MANIFOLDS

Thermo Field Dynamics and quantum algebras

arxiv:quant-ph/ v2 21 May 1998

Foundations of Mathematics MATH 220 FALL 2017 Lecture Notes

Concrete Domains. Gilles Kahn INRIA Sophia Antipolis Gordon D. Plotkin University of Edinburgh

Valuations. 6.1 Definitions. Chapter 6

Restricted versions of the Tukey-Teichmüller Theorem that are equivalent to the Boolean Prime Ideal Theorem

ON LATTICE-ORDERED REES MATRIX Γ-SEMIGROUPS

THE JORDAN DECOMPOSITION AND HALF-NORMS

MATH 54 - TOPOLOGY SUMMER 2015 FINAL EXAMINATION. Problem 1

A Class of Infinite Convex Geometries

The Skorokhod reflection problem for functions with discontinuities (contractive case)

5-DESIGNS IN AFFINE SPACES

Basic Concepts of Group Theory

SYMPLECTIC GEOMETRY: LECTURE 5

The Global Defect Index

A NOTE ON FAITHFUL TRACES ON A VON NEUMANN ALGEBRA

Classification of root systems

Some remarks on symmetric correspondences

DISPERSION-FREE STATES AND THE EXCLUSION OF HIDDEN VARIABLES S. P. GUDDER

MATH 101: ALGEBRA I WORKSHEET, DAY #1. We review the prerequisites for the course in set theory and beginning a first pass on group. 1.

Pure Operations and Measurements*

ORDERED INVOLUTIVE OPERATOR SPACES

Transcription:

Commun. math. Phys. 40, 7 13 (1975) by Springer-Verlag 1975 Ideal, First-kind Measurements in a Proposition-State Structure G. Cassinelli and E. G. Beltrametti Istituto di Scienze Fisiche, Universita di Genova, I.N.F.N., Sezione di Genova, Genova, Italy Received May 9, 1974 Abstract. Let j? be an orthomodular lattice and y a strongly ordering set of probability measures on «? such that supports of measures exist in Jzf. Then we show the existence of a set of mappings of ^ into f that are physically interpretable as ideal, first-kind measurements. 1. In the conventional formulation [1-3] of the so called logic of quantum mechanics the basic mathematical structure associated to a physical system is the pair (JSf, f} where JSf is the set of propositions (yes-no experiments), ^ the set of states; each αe^ defines on J^ a probability measure α : 5f > [0,1], and α(α), a e JS?, is interpreted as the probability of the yes answer of α, when the initial state of the system is α. «? is given the appropriate structure of orthomodular lattice by means of suitable axioms which elude any requirement on the transformations of the state of the system caused by the measurement of α: the usual postulates of quantum theory of measurement are considered as independent from the structure of Jδf (for details and further bibliography we refer to [4]). Pool [5, 6] has suggested an alternative approach which uses as basic mathematical structure the proposition-state-operation triple («?, ^, Ω) 1, where the operation Ω α e Ω associated to a e JS? is understood as the transformation of the state of the system induced by an ideal, first-kind measurement (with yes answer) of the proposition α. By use of the postulates of quantum theory of measurement and of the remarkable connections between orthomodular lattices and Baer*-semigrouρs, he deduces for Jίf the structure of orthomodular lattice (see also [7]). In this paper, we shall examine the possibility of reversing the Pool approach: we are going to study whether the assumption of a (jsf, ί?) structure, with 3? orthomodular lattice, is sufficient to deduce the 1 (J2?, Sf] is denoted by Pool as (, &>, P) and called an event-state structure; (&, y, Ω) is denoted as (β, ^, P, Ω} and called an event-state-operation structure.

G. Cassinelli and E. G. Beltrametti existence of a set of transformations of ^ into f which admit the physical interpretation of ideal, first-kind measurements, hence the existence of operations in the sense of Pool. 2. We sum up several usual assumptions about 3? and y by the following Axiom 1. JS? is a complete orthomodular lattice, f is a strongly ordering, σ-convex set of probability measures on 52. Here, and in the sequel, the definitions and the notations about lattices are from [8], the definitions about probability measures on orthomodular posets are from [5, 6]. We say that α e «? is support of α e & when α(b) = 0, be^o a-lb. For every α e 5^ there exists at most one a e? such that a is support of α: we shall denote such element, when it exists, by σ(α). We refer to [6] for properties of supports: the following will be used {a G J? : αlσ(α)} = {a e & : α(α) = 0}, {a e es? :σ(α) ^ α} - {α e J^ : α(α) = 1}. Then we adopt, as in [6], the following Axiom 2. If α e ^ ίλen ίfte support of α ex/sis m jsf. // α 6 jsf \{0, 1} then there exists α e f such that a = σ(α). Hence it is defined a surjective mapping which is always canonically decomposable in the composition of a surjective mapping ω of f onto ^/σ (the set of the equivalence classes of the states with the same support) with a bijection/of f/σ onto S \{0, 1}. Thus/defines an one-to-one correspondence between f/σ and «Sf \{0, 1} such that every element of ϊf/σ corresponds to the common support of the states belonging to that element. Let S(cSf) be the Baer*- semigroup of residuated mappings (or emimorphisms) of ^2, let P'(S(JSf)) be the lattice of the closed projections of S(JSf). For every α 6 JSf, let 2 We refer to [5, 6, 8] for definitions, properties and bibliography on Baer *-semigroups, residuated mappings of orthomodular lattices, and their connections.

Ideal First-kind Measurements φ a is an element of P'(8(^))\ conversely every element of P'( is of the form φ a for some a e 5f. The pair (, f} will be definitely assumed to satisfy Axioms 1 and 2: we shall call it the (JS?, f) structure. Lemma 1. For any given a e there exists a unique mapping ω fl :^-»^/σ such that (i) the following diagram is commutative (ii) ί/ie domain ^[ω α ] o/ω α is groerc / Given α E =?, α E ^, a known property of closed projections of S(J5?) ensures that φ α (σ(α))φo if and only if σ(α) ^ α. Thus, if oce{βe^:σ(β) ^ α}, φ fl (σ(α)) e^?\{0, 1}. Since / is a bijection it is well defined f~ 1 (φ a (σ(a)))ε y /σ. Then we put ω fl (α) =/- 1 (φ β (σ(α))) if σ(α) Jz α. In this way we have defined a mapping of y 7 into f/σ whose domain is Q) [ω α ] = {α e ^ : σ(α) J/ α}. Clearly ω α makes the diagram commutative and is uniquely determined by the Properties (i) and (ii). Q.E.D. Lemma 2. Given a e, α e ^ [ω fl ], (i) ifa(a)= 1 f/zerc ω α (α) {α}, where {α} is ίte equivalence class of a in^/σ; (ii) ifβeω a (a}thenβ(a)=i. Proof. (i)α(α)=l implies σ(α)^α, hence σ(α)cα, hence σ(α)cα 1 [in an orthomodular lattice we say that α commutes with b, and we write a C b when a = (a Λ i?) v (α Λ b 1 )]. Therefore α, α 1, σ(α) form a distributive triple so that φ β (σ(α)) = (σ(α) v α 1 ) Λ a = (σ(α) Λ α) v (α 1 Λ α) = σ(α), whence /- 1 (φ a (σ(ot))) = ω β (α) = {α}. (ii) Owing to the commutativity of the diagram of Lemma 1 we have /(ω fl (α)) = φ α (σ(α))? Vα E ^ [ω α ], hence /(ω α (α)) ^ α for φ fl projects «? onto the sublattice [0, a], lϊ β e ω α (α), by the definition of/ we get σ(j8) =/(ω α ( α )) g α, whence j8(α) - 1. Q. E. D.

10 G. Cassinelli and E. G. Beltrametti Lemma 3. If a, b e 5, acb, &e$) [ωj, β e ω α (α) then (i) α(b) - 1 implies β(b) = 1 Proof, (i) α(fe) = l implies σ(α)^b, hence φ α (σ(α)) ^ φ α (b) for φ a is monotone (as every residuated mapping). From acb it follows that α, α 1, fo form a distributive triple, hence φ a (b) = (b v α 1 ) Λ α (b Λ a) v (α 1 Λ α) = b Λ α. The commutativity of the diagram of Lemma 1 ensures that if β e ω fl (α) then σ(β) = φ a (σ(a)). Therefore σ(β) ^ φ a (b) = b Λ a ^ b, whence (ii) We write α C b in the form b = (b Λ α) v (b Λ α 1 ) and remark that (feλα 1 ) 1^1 vα^bλα; thus ί?λα and ^Λα 1 are orthogonal so that β(b) = β(b Λ a) + js(fe Λ α 1 ) = j3(& Λ α) + 1 - βφ 1 v α). On account of Lemma 2 (ii) we have β(b ± va)=i for b L va^a\ therefore β(b) = β(b Λ a). Q. E. D. Theorem 1. For every ae <&, there exists at least one mapping Ω a :^-^^ such that (A) Ω a has domain @[β J = 3) [ω J, (B) ί/α e ^ [βj, αnrf α(α) - 1 then β β (α)- α, (C) ι/α e ^ [βj, and β = β α (α) ίλβn j8(α) - 1, (D) if a e [βj, j5 = β fl (α), be^.acb, and α(b) = 1 ίλen j8(b) - 1, (E) if α e [βj, β = β α (α), bε >,andacb then β(b) = β(a Λ ft), (F) ifae@lωj 9 andβ = Ω a (a)thenσ(β) = φ a (σ(a)). Proof. We notice that ^/σ is a partition of f (in disjoint classes) and we make use of the so called choice axiom (see, e.g., [9]): composing ω a with any choice function which maps ω α (α) e 5^/σ into some single state belonging to ω α (α) we get, for every a e Jδf, a mapping Ώ α of ^ into 5^. By construction Ω fl fits (A). On account of Lemma 2(i), and remarking that α e {α}, we are allowed to adopt a choice function which, whenever α(α) = l, maps ω fl (α) into α itself: thus Ω fl satisfies (B). The Properties (C), (D), ( ), (F) are then direct consequences of Lemmas 2 (ii), 3 (i), 3 (ii), 1 (i), respectively. Q. E. D. 3. The previous theorem answers affirmatively the problem rised at the end of Section 1 the («?, ^) structure (equipped with the Axioms 1 and 2) is sufficient to deduce, for every ae^f, the existence of a mapping Ω a of ^ into ^ which admits the following interpretation: if the initial state of the system is α then Ω a (a) is the final state of the system after an ideal, first-kind measurement of a which has given the yes answer. Let us examine briefly the Properties (A)-(F) of that theorem.

Ideal First-kind Measurements 1 1 Since the condition σ(α) ^ a (occuring in ^[ΩJ) is equivalent to α (α) Φ 0, we rephrase (^4) by saying that Ω a is defined for every state α which has a non vanishing probability α(α) of giving the yes answer of the yes-no experiment α. Then (B) and (C) correspond to the definition of first kind measurement [10]. The commutativity relation C previously used is fully equivalent to the physical notion of compatible experiments [3, 7, 8]. Thus the Property (D) corresponds to the commonly accepted definition of ideal measurement. When β = Ω α (α) and a C b the Property (E) suggests for β(b) the interpretation of conditional probability of compatible events; however, to guarantee that interpretation one should require, according to conventional probability theory, one further property, viz: (G) if a, be^e, a^b, αe^[ωj, and β = Ω a (a) then )8(fe) =. α(α) The Property (F), which determines uniquely the support of β = Ω α (α) from the support of α, is the essential step to equip J2? with the covering property [6]. We come now to a comparison with the assumptions occuring in the Pool approach. The Properties (.4), (B\ and (C) coincide, respectively, with his Axioms II. 1, II. 2, and II. 3. The Property (D) goes beyond the Pool axioms : actually he uses an alternative definition of ideal measurement resting on the Properties (E) and (G), which coincide, respectively, with his Axioms II.7 and Π.6. However, these two axioms enter into the Pool approach only as instruments to prove a property weaker than (F), viz: if αe [ΩJ, and j8 = Ω α (α) then σ(jβ)^φ α (σ(α)). This inequality can also be proved by use of the characterization (D) of ideal measurement [4, 7] without any reference to (E) and (G); anyhow it is used by Pool only as a hint for adopting the stronger Property (F) which coincides with his Axiom II. 8. Thus we have to conclude that the (=Sf, f) structure contains into itself the relevant properties of Pool's operations 3 with just one significant exception: the unicity of the ideal, first-kind measurement associated to a e <=?, (which is necessary to deduce the orthomodular lattice properties of J&? from the proposition-state-operation structure). However, in our approach, the problem of the unicity of Ω a has connections with the further hypotheses, about the atomicity of X and the pure states of 5^, which are needed to introduce the covering property (called semimodularity in [6]). For the last we shall refer to the definition: J&? has the covering property if φ a (p) is an atom for every a e 5 and 1 The Axioms II.4 and 11.5 of Pool evade the framework of the present analysis.

12 G. Cassinelli and E. G. Beltrametti every atom pe^f such that p ^ a L. This definition is equivalent [11] to the one found in [8]. Then we have: Theorem 2. If, in the structure ( >?\ 3? is atomic and σ determines a bijective mapping between the atoms of ^ and the pure states of f, then (i) the covering property of ^ implies that the restriction of Ω a to the pure states of^[ω^\ is uniquely determined by a and transforms pure states into pure states (ii) 3? has the covering property and the restriction of Ω a to the pure states of @[Ω a ~] is uniquely determined by a if Ω a transforms pure states into pure states. Proof, (i) Due to the covering property φ α (σ(α)) is an atom; by (F) of Theorem 1 this atom is the support of β = Ω a (a). Hence this state is pure and uniquely determined by a and α. (ii) By hypothesis, if αe^[ωj is pure, also Ω α (α) is pure, hence φ a (σ(<x)) is an atom, by (F) of Theorem 1. This is equivalent to say that φ a (p) is an atom whenever p E is an atom such that p ^ a ±. The uniqueness of β = Ω a ((ή follows from σ(β) = φ α (σ(α)). Q.E.D. The hypotheses of Theorem 2 about atomicity and pure states are equivalent to the ones adopted in [6] (see Axiom 1.9 and Theorem II. 1). We conclude that also the connections between covering property and pure operations are contained, in a natural way, into the (, <?) structure. The role of the unicity of the ideal, first-kind measurement associated to αe= f has been particularly studied by Ochs [12]. He restricts ^ to the set &" of pure states, assumes & to be an atomic orthomodular lattice with a bijective mapping of ίf' onto the set of the atoms of JSf, postulates the existence and the unicity of an ideal, first-kind measurement [i.e. the Properties (A), (B\ (C\ (D) of Theorem 1 with Ω a replaced by τ α ], and proves the covering property [i.e. the Property (F) of Theorem 1 with Ω a replaced by τj. On account of Theorem 2, the restriction of Ω a to the pure states coincides with τ a. Thus, when dealing with pure states, the requirement of unicity of the ideal, first-kind measurement is equivalent to adopt our construction of Ω α, made explicit by (F) of Theorem 1. References 1. Piron,C.: Helv. Phys. Acta 37, 439 468 (1964) 2. Jauch,J.M.: Foundations of quantum mechanics. Reading, Mass.: Addison-Wesley 1968 3. Varadarajan,V.S.: Geometry of quantum theory, Vol. 1. Princeton: Van Nostrand 1968 4. Beltrametti,E.G., Cassinelli,G.: Z. Naturforsch. 28a, 1516 1530 (1973) 5. Pool,J.C.T.: Commun. math. Phys. 9, 118 141 (1968)

Ideal First-kind Measurements 13 6. PoolJ.C.T.: Commun. math. Phys. 9, 212 228 (1968) 7. Beltrametti,E.G., Cassinelli,G.: On the structure of the proposition lattice associated with quantum systems. In: Atti del colloquio internazionale sulle teorie combinatorie. Roma: Ace. Naz. Lίnceί, in press 8. Maeda,F., Maeda,S.: Theory of symmetric lattices. Berlin-Heidelberg-New York: Springer 1970 9. Dieudonne,J.: Foundations of modern analysis. New York: Academic Press 1969 (in particular p. 6) 10. Pauli, W.: Die allgemeinen Prinzipien der Wellenmechanik. In: Handbuch der Physik, Vol. 1, Part 1, pp. 1 168. Berlin-Gόttingen-Heidelberg: Springer 1958 11. Schreiner,E.A.: Pacific J. Math. 19, 519 528 (1966) 12. Ochs.W.: Commun. math. Phys. 25, 245 252 (1972) Communicated by R. Haag G. Cassinelli E. G. Beltrametti Universita di Genova Istituto di Scienze Fisiche Viale Benedetto XV, 5 I-16132 Genova, Italy