Philosophy of Mathematics Structuralism

Similar documents
Instrumental nominalism about set-theoretic structuralism

Philosophy of Mathematics Intuitionism

Russell s logicism. Jeff Speaks. September 26, 2007

PROOF-THEORETIC REDUCTION AS A PHILOSOPHER S TOOL

The Foundations of Mathematics. Frege s Logicism

Shapiro s and Hellman s Structuralism

A Height-Potentialist View of Set Theory

A Structuralist Account of Logic

Axioms as definitions: revisiting Hilbert

Mathematical Descriptions

Philosophy 5340 Epistemology. Topic 3: Analysis, Analytically Basic Concepts, Direct Acquaintance, and Theoretical Terms. Part 2: Theoretical Terms

THE SYDNEY SCHOOL AN ARISTOTELIAN REALIST PHILOSOPHY OF MATHEMATICS

Williamson s Modal Logic as Metaphysics

Realism and Idealism External Realism

ANTE REM STRUCTURALISM AND THE MYTH OF IDENTITY CRITERIA

MODAL STRUCTURALISM SIMPLIFIED

Kaplan s Paradox and Epistemically Possible Worlds

Chapter 4. Basic Set Theory. 4.1 The Language of Set Theory

Discrete Mathematics for CS Fall 2003 Wagner Lecture 3. Strong induction

Reflections on Mathematics

The Philosophical Significance of Tennenbaum s Theorem

A Logically Coherent Ante Rem Structuralism

Seminar 7: The Logic of Principia Mathematica

UNIVERSITY OF CALGARY. Indiscernibility and Mathematical Structuralism. Teresa Kouri A THESIS SUBMITTED TO THE FACULTY OF GRADUATE STUDIES

Description Logics. Foundations of Propositional Logic. franconi. Enrico Franconi

Neale and the slingshot Fabrice Correia

On an Unsound Proof of the Existence of Possible Worlds

Geometry and Philosophy

A Way of Getting Rid of Things:

On the Gödel-Friedman Program (for the Conference in Honor of Harvey Friedman) Geoffrey Hellman

PHIL12A Section answers, 14 February 2011

Metaphysics of Modality

A Puzzle for Structuralism

Introduction to Philosophy Philosophy 110W Spring 2011 Russell Marcus

Ante rem structuralism and the myth of. identity criteria. Introduction. Charlie Siu. March 2, 2008

Gödel s Programm and Ultimate L

Spring 2018 Ling 620 The Basics of Intensional Semantics, Part 1: The Motivation for Intensions and How to Formalize Them 1

The Converse of Deducibility: C.I. Lewis and the Origin of Modern AAL/ALC Modal 2011 Logic 1 / 26

Published in Analysis, 2004, 64 (1), pp

Beliefs, we will assume, come in degrees. As a shorthand, we will refer to these. Syracuse University

Once Upon a Spacetime. Bradford Skow

Sortals and Criteria of Identity

Making Sense. Tom Carter. tom/sfi-csss. April 2, 2009

Frege: Logical objects by abstraction and their criteria of identity. Matthias Schirn (University of Munich, Munich Center of Mathematical Philosophy)

Towards a Contemporary Ontology

AXIOMS AS DEFINITIONS: REVISITING POINCARÉ AND HILBERT

Doxastic Logic. Michael Caie

Meta-logic derivation rules

7 Classical Quantified Logic

The Application of Gödel s Incompleteness Theorems to Scientific Theories

Introduction to Logic and Axiomatic Set Theory

Structuralism: A Defense

Propositions and Proofs

A Little Deductive Logic

Lecture 17: Floyd-Hoare Logic for Partial Correctness

09. Kant and Logical Positivism Topics:

Critical Notice: Bas van Fraassen, Scientific Representation: Paradoxes of Perspective Oxford University Press, 2008, xiv pages

Forms of Anti-Individualism

Quantifier variance without collapse

CAUSATION. Chapter 14. Causation and the Direction of Time Preliminary Considerations in Support of a Causal Analysis of Temporal Concepts

INCOMPLETENESS I by Harvey M. Friedman Distinguished University Professor Mathematics, Philosophy, Computer Science Ohio State University Invitation

A Way of Getting Rid of Things:

The two-dimensionalism of The Conscious Mind

All psychiatrists are doctors All doctors are college graduates All psychiatrists are college graduates

Foundations for Mathematical Structuralism

Are Objects Ontologically Dependent on Processes?

Conceivability and Modal Knowledge

Comments on Markosian s How Fast Does Time Pass?

Introduction to Metalogic

A Little Deductive Logic

Chapter 2. Mathematical Reasoning. 2.1 Mathematical Models

Philosophy of Mathematics Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy

Logical Form, Mathematical Practice, and Frege s Begriffsschrift. Danielle Macbeth Haverford College

Précis of Modality and Explanatory Reasoning

HOW TO WRITE PROOFS. Dr. Min Ru, University of Houston

Ibn Sina s explanation of reductio ad absurdum. Wilfrid Hodges Herons Brook, Sticklepath, Okehampton November 2011

References A CONSTRUCTIVE INTRODUCTION TO FIRST ORDER LOGIC. The Starting Point. Goals of foundational programmes for logic:

A DEFINITION OF NECESSITY. George Bealer Yale University

KRIPKE S THEORY OF TRUTH 1. INTRODUCTION

Ontology on Shaky Grounds

240 Metaphysics. Frege s Puzzle. Chapter 26

Accuracy, Language Dependence and Joyce s Argument for Probabilism

Truthmaker Maximalism defended again. Eduardo Barrio and Gonzalo Rodriguez-Pereyra

Non-normal Worlds. Daniel Bonevac. February 5, 2012

CMPSCI 601: Tarski s Truth Definition Lecture 15. where

Philosophies of Mathematics. The Search for Foundations

Peano Arithmetic. by replacing the schematic letter R with a formula, then prefixing universal quantifiers to bind

Marc Lange -- IRIS. European Journal of Philosophy and Public Debate

The central problem: what are the objects of geometry? Answer 1: Perceptible objects with shape. Answer 2: Abstractions, mere shapes.

Proseminar on Semantic Theory Fall 2010 Ling 720. Remko Scha (1981/1984): Distributive, Collective and Cumulative Quantification

Contradictions in mathematics

Correspondence theory and logical postulates in metaphysics in an application to formal pragmatics

Direct Proof and Counterexample I:Introduction

PEANO AXIOMS FOR THE NATURAL NUMBERS AND PROOFS BY INDUCTION. The Peano axioms

Fibrational Semantics

Axiomatic set theory. Chapter Why axiomatic set theory?

Scientific Explanation- Causation and Unification

Direct Proof and Counterexample I:Introduction. Copyright Cengage Learning. All rights reserved.

CHAPTER 2 INTRODUCTION TO CLASSICAL PROPOSITIONAL LOGIC

Identity in Physics and Elsewhere

Transcription:

Philosophy of Mathematics Structuralism Owen Griffiths oeg21@cam.ac.uk St John s College, Cambridge 17/11/15

Neo-Fregeanism Last week, we considered recent attempts to revive Fregean logicism. Analytic logicists try to show that HP is an analytic truth. But HP is only satisfiable in infinite domains. Can an analytic truth be committing to infinitely many things? Neo-Fregean logicism tries to stipulate HP as an implicit definition of number. But stipulation must be sentential or subsentential. The former fails to fix a reference for the term-forming operator. The latter fails to guarantee that HP is true.

Implicit definition Over the past few weeks, we ve been discussing implicit definition: a functional characterisation of some notion in terms of its relation to other notions. A functionalist about the mental may define pain in the following way: Pain is caused by stubbing your toe and pain makes you wince and pain is unpleasant and... x is caused by stubbing your toe and x makes you wince and x is unpleasant and... Pain is then anything that satisfies this open sentence. But it may be multiply realizable, e.g. the physical state that satisfies the open sentence may be c-fibres in humans but d-fibres in akarpis.

Geometry We may take a similar approach in the philosophy of mathematics: Given any two points, exactly one line can be drawn which passes through them. Any line can be indefinitely extended. Given any two points, exactly one line can be drawn which passes through them AND Any line can be indefinitely extended AND... Given any two points, exactly one x can be drawn which passes through them AND Any x can be indefinitely extended AND... We may take this open sentence to implicitly define line. As with the mental case, there could be many entities that satisfy the open sentence.

Hilbert Every theory is only a scaffolding or schema of concepts together with their necessary relations to one another, and the basic elements can be thought of in any way one likes. If in speaking of my points, I think of some system of things, e.g. the system love, law, chimney-sweep... and then assume all my axioms as relations between these things, then my propositions, e.g., Pythagoras theorem, are also valid for these things... any theory can always be applied to infinitely many systems of basic elements. (see Frege, Philosophical and mathematical correspondence) Many systems of things may satisfy mathematical axioms. So mathematics isn t really about any of those things in particular, but the structure that those things instantiate.

Structuralism Further evidence for this structuralist line of thought is the existence of relative consistency proofs. A theory Θ 1 is proved consistent relative to Θ 2 by interpreting the nonlogical primitives of the former in the language of the latter and showing that the results are theorems of the latter. Hilbert initiated this method of consistency proof, which is now common practice. In particular, it is well known that virtually all of mathematics can be modelled in set theory. This all suggests a form of structuralism.

What numbers could not be Many philosophers of mathematics have identified the natural numbers with set-theoretic objects. Even Frege, who wrote before the development of set theory, identified numbers with the extensions of second-level concepts, which are set-like objects. But, as Paul Benacerraf points out in his famous 1965 paper What Numbers Could Not Be, this identification can be made in infinitely many ways. Without loss of generality, let s think about 2 ways that we may go about making this identification. We ll consider 2 ways of identifying natural numbers with pure sets (sets with no urelements).

Two identifications I II 0 = 1 = { } 2 = {{ }} 3 = {{{ }}}. 0 = 1 = { } 2 = {, { }} 3 = {, { }, {.{ }}}.

Identification problem Which of I and II is to be preferred? It seems that there is nothing to choose between them. We can define successor, addition and multiplication on I and II to make them isomorphic, so they make precisely the same sentences true. And yet they cannot both be true collections of identity claims. By I, 2 = {{ }}. By II, 2 = {, { }}. So, by the transitivity of identity, {{ }} = {, { }}. But that s false. The correct conclusion seems to be that neither I nor II is correct. Rather, the numbers are to be identified structurally: 2 picks out a certain position in a structure, which can be instantiated by {{ }} and can be instantiated by {, { }}.

Systems Following the Hilbert quote, a system is a collection of objects concrete or abstract with relations between them. We could think of a family as a system of objects with certain relations holding between them. A mathematical number system is a countably infinite collection of objects with a designated initial object and a successor relation that satisifes the usual axioms. The Arabic numerals are such a system, as are an infinite sequence of temporal points. A Euclidean system is three collections of objects, one called points, one lines and one called planes, with relations between them that ensure they satisfy the Euclidean axioms.

Structures A structure is the abstract form of a system. It abstracts away from all properties of the system other than the structural relations that hold between the objects. The Arabic numerals and the infinite sequence of temporal points share the natural number structure.

Varieties of structuralism All structuralists contend that mathematics is the science of structure, but they differ as to the nature of these structures. The main distinction is between platonist and nominalist structuralists. Platonist structuralists, most notably Stewart Shapiro and Michael Resnik, hold that the structures exist. Nominalist structuralists, most notably Geoffrey Hellman and Charles Chihara, hold that the structures can be eliminated. Let s take them in turn.

Platonic and aristotelian universals In the literature on universals, authors disagree about the spatio-temporal location of universals. Platonic universals are not spatio-temporally located: they are abstract entities. Aristotelian universals are spatio-temporally located: they are located in their instances. The defender of aristotelian universals may have a metaphysical advantage. They need not accept anything abstract over and above the concrete instances. But they also have to say that one universal can be wholly present at different places at the same time, and that two universals can occupy the same place at the same time.

Ante rem and in re structuralists Platonist structuralists generally come in two sorts: ante rem and in re. The former contend that structures are platonic universals, the latter that they are aristotelian universals. In re structuralists have to say that the structures are ontologically dependent on their systems: destroy the systems and you destroy the structures. But while this may have some appeal in the non-mathematical case, it seems problematic here: if mathematical truths are necessary, then we want to say that they hold in all worlds, even those without any instantiating systems. We ll proceed with ante rem structuralism as our paradigm example of Platonist structuralism.

Advantages of Platonist structuralism The Platonist structuralist can read mathematical sentences at face value. The sentence there are at least 2 primes less than 7 appears to have the same form as there are at least 2 cities smaller than Paris. They can also accommodate the Benacerraf s insights, and have a straightforward explanation for e.g. relative consistency proofs.

Epistemology Like most Platonist positions, Platonist structuralism has epistemological problems If the objects are abstract, how do we manage to access them? Shapiro has the most sophisticated epistemological story for Platonist structuralism. Let s look at his explanation of how we gain access to ante rem structures. Notice the Kantian echoes in Shapiro s story.

Shapiro s epistemology Abstraction We are able to discern small, instantiated patterns. E.g. we can recognise the 2-pattern in all systems consisting of just 2 objects, and so on. By attending to such tokens, we can apprehend the types. Projection We can gain knowledge of larger structures, e.g. the 10,000-pattern, by recognising the order of smaller abstractions, and projecting further. Description Projection will only get us as far as denumerable infinities, however. To deal with larger structures, we can use our powers of description. If we can know the coherence of such descriptions, we can gain knowledge of the structures described.

Problems for projection It seems plausible that we are capable of something like abstraction. But Fraser MacBride (1997) casts doubt on whether projection and description can deliver knowledge of structures. It seems plausible that we do in fact project our abstractions about smaller patterns to larger cases, e.g. we discern the 2-, 3- and 4-patterns and believe that this progression will continue indefinitely. But such belief does not suffice for knowledge without (at least) some sort of warrant or justification.

Problems for projection We need more than the descriptive claim that we do project. We need the normative claim that we are right to project. But how can the normative claim be supported? It can t be that the projection is supported by best mathematical theories, on pain of circularity. And if we can t appeal to that, we face rule-following worries: how do we know that we should not be following some less standard rule?

Problems for description Here, Shapiro echoes Hilbert: if we establish the consistency of an axiomatization, we can establish the existence of the structure described. Shapiro doesn t use Hilbert s notion of consistency but the wider notion of coherence. Coherence gets explicated in terms of set-theoretic satisfiability.

Problems for description If we know that an axiomatization is coherent, and we know that it is categorical, then we know that the structure corresponds to the descriprion. But how do we come to know that a description is coherent and categorical? These notions get spelt out in set-theoretic terms, and the question of their justification gets pushed back to mathematical theory. Again, these are the very things we re out to justify.

Nominalist structuralism Given the problems faced by Platonist structuralists, some have endorsed a form of nominalist structuralism. We ll focus on Hellman s modal structuralism. The central idea is that we can enjoy the benefits of Platonist structuralism but without the ontological commitment. Rather than thinking about actual structures, we need only be concerned with possible structures.

Modal structuralism Consider some arithmetic sentence S. Hellman would paraphrase S: X (X is an ω-sequence S holds in X ) In words: necessarily, if there is an ω-sequence, then S is true in that sequence. Hellman calls this the hypothetical component of his view.

Vacuity This paraphrase faces an immediate vacuity problem. The nominalist structuralist does not want to be committed to mathematical objects, since they are abstract and so present e.g. access problems. These are the very things that caused issues for Shapiro. But, for all we know, the universe may not contain enough physical objects for all of mathematics. E.g. if the universe contains only 10 100,000 objects, then there won t be any ω-sequences.

Vacuity Even if we are convinced that the universe contains enough objects for arithmetic, there may be some limit to the number of objects it contains, and there will be branches of mathematics that require more. If there are not enough objects, then the antecedent of the hypothetical component will be false and so the whole conditional will be vacuously true. For this reason, Hellman introduces the categorical component: X (X is an ω-sequence) In words: it is possible that an ω-sequence exists.

The categorical component The categorical component guarantees that, if the hypothetical component is true, it is non-vacuously true. There s one wrinkle. Both components are expressed in second-order S5. But it had better be S5 without the Barcan Formula: BF xfx x Fx With BF, the categorical component entails: X (X is an ω-sequence) which Hellman obviously doesn t want.

Modality Overall, then, the thought is that mathematical sentences are elliptical for longer sentences in second-order S5 (without BF). They have a hypothetical component to achieve this, and a categorical component to avoid vacuity. The account therefore avoids Shapiro s metaphysical burden, but does so at the cost of respecting mathematical sentences at face value.

Modality Further, the nature of the invoked modality must also be explained. Is it metaphysical possibility, or logical, or mathematical? Hellman says logical, but now there s a problem. Logical modality usually gets explicated in set-theoretic terms, but that is to let abstract objects back in. Instead, he refuses to explicate the logical modality at all, but leave it primitive.

Ontology vs ideology Quine says that a theory carries an ontology and an ideology The ontology consists of the entities which the theory says exist. The ideology consists of the ideas expressed within the theory using predicates, operators, etc. Ontology is measured by the number of entities postulated by a theory. Ideology is measured by the number of primitives. It is often thought that ideological economy has epistemological benefits. A theory with fewer primitives is likely to be more unified, which may aid understanding.

Ontology vs ideology So Hellman has increased ideology in order to reduce ontology. Is this satisfactory? We ll discuss this further next week in light of Hartry Field s nominalism.