Products, Relations and Functions

Similar documents
VI I : The Axiom of Choice and related properties

Exercises for Unit VI (Infinite constructions in set theory)

Report 1 The Axiom of Choice

Section 0.7. The Axiom of Choice, Order, and Zorn s Lemma

SOME TRANSFINITE INDUCTION DEDUCTIONS

Category Theory. Categories. Definition.

The Axiom of Choice. Contents. 1 Motivation 2. 2 The Axiom of Choice 2. 3 Two powerful equivalents of AC 4. 4 Zorn s Lemma 5. 5 Using Zorn s Lemma 6

Notes on ordinals and cardinals

Introduction to Logic and Axiomatic Set Theory

ABOUT THE CLASS AND NOTES ON SET THEORY

The Axiom of Choice and Zorn s Lemma

Sets, Models and Proofs. I. Moerdijk and J. van Oosten Department of Mathematics Utrecht University

Dr. Bob s Axiom of Choice Centennial Lecture Fall A Century Ago

Infinite constructions in set theory

Math 300 Introduction to Mathematical Reasoning Autumn 2017 Inverse Functions

SETS AND FUNCTIONS JOSHUA BALLEW

A BRIEF INTRODUCTION TO ZFC. Contents. 1. Motivation and Russel s Paradox

GENERAL TOPOLOGY JESPER M. MØLLER

Chapter 1. Sets and Mappings

Mathematics 205A. Topology I. Course Notes. Revised, Fall 2005, and Fall 2008

In N we can do addition, but in order to do subtraction we need to extend N to the integers

Chapter 0. Introduction: Prerequisites and Preliminaries

CHAPTER 0: BACKGROUND (SPRING 2009 DRAFT)

In N we can do addition, but in order to do subtraction we need to extend N to the integers

Standard forms for writing numbers

ADVANCED CALCULUS - MTH433 LECTURE 4 - FINITE AND INFINITE SETS

{x : P (x)} P (x) = x is a cat

Axiomatic set theory. Chapter Why axiomatic set theory?

2.2 Lowenheim-Skolem-Tarski theorems

The Axiom of Choice and the Banach-Tarski Paradox

INFINITY: CARDINAL NUMBERS

Lecture Notes 1 Basic Concepts of Mathematics MATH 352

INTRODUCTION TO CARDINAL NUMBERS

Properties of the Integers

a + b = b + a and a b = b a. (a + b) + c = a + (b + c) and (a b) c = a (b c). a (b + c) = a b + a c and (a + b) c = a c + b c.

Connectedness. Proposition 2.2. The following are equivalent for a topological space (X, T ).

Zermelo-Fraenkel Set Theory

Section 31. The Separation Axioms

A Logician s Toolbox

Relations and Functions

The Measure Problem. Louis de Branges Department of Mathematics Purdue University West Lafayette, IN , USA

CITS2211 Discrete Structures (2017) Cardinality and Countability

Math 4603: Advanced Calculus I, Summer 2016 University of Minnesota Notes on Cardinality of Sets

VISUALIZATION OF INTUITIVE SET THEORY

The Axiom of Choice and Some Equivalences:

MAGIC Set theory. lecture 2

Chapter 1 : The language of mathematics.


Supplement. Algebraic Closure of a Field

PEANO AXIOMS FOR THE NATURAL NUMBERS AND PROOFS BY INDUCTION. The Peano axioms

INCOMPLETENESS I by Harvey M. Friedman Distinguished University Professor Mathematics, Philosophy, Computer Science Ohio State University Invitation

General Topology. Jesper M. Møller

Equivalent Forms of the Axiom of Infinity

2.1 Sets. Definition 1 A set is an unordered collection of objects. Important sets: N, Z, Z +, Q, R.

1 The Real Number System

INDEPENDENCE OF THE CONTINUUM HYPOTHESIS

DO FIVE OUT OF SIX ON EACH SET PROBLEM SET

The following techniques for methods of proofs are discussed in our text: - Vacuous proof - Trivial proof

MATH 220 (all sections) Homework #12 not to be turned in posted Friday, November 24, 2017

The Axiom of Choice and its Discontents

Set Theory and the Foundation of Mathematics. June 19, 2018

MAT 570 REAL ANALYSIS LECTURE NOTES. Contents. 1. Sets Functions Countability Axiom of choice Equivalence relations 9

Measure and Integration: Concepts, Examples and Exercises. INDER K. RANA Indian Institute of Technology Bombay India

Seminaar Abstrakte Wiskunde Seminar in Abstract Mathematics Lecture notes in progress (27 March 2010)

On numbers. A pearl seminar Mats Ehrnström

POL502: Foundations. Kosuke Imai Department of Politics, Princeton University. October 10, 2005

Handout 2 (Correction of Handout 1 plus continued discussion/hw) Comments and Homework in Chapter 1

KRIPKE S THEORY OF TRUTH 1. INTRODUCTION

Zermelo-Frankel Set Theory and Well Orderings

Class Notes on Poset Theory Johan G. Belinfante Revised 1995 May 21

Axioms for Set Theory

MAGIC Set theory. lecture 1

Sets and Functions. (As we will see, in describing a set the order in which elements are listed is irrelevant).

Krivine s Intuitionistic Proof of Classical Completeness (for countable languages)

Contents Propositional Logic: Proofs from Axioms and Inference Rules

Peano Arithmetic. CSC 438F/2404F Notes (S. Cook) Fall, Goals Now

Introduction. Chapter 1

The cardinal comparison of sets

Section 7.5: Cardinality

Functions and cardinality (solutions) sections A and F TA: Clive Newstead 6 th May 2014

SOLUTIONS TO EXERCISES FOR. MATHEMATICS 205A Part 1. I. Foundational material

THE CANTOR SET AND A CONTINUOUS MAP FROM THE INTERVAL ONTO THE SQUARE. Figure 1. Giuseppe Peano, Figure 2. David Hilbert,

5 Set Operations, Functions, and Counting

Discrete Mathematics: Lectures 6 and 7 Sets, Relations, Functions and Counting Instructor: Arijit Bishnu Date: August 4 and 6, 2009

Clearly C B, for every C Q. Suppose that we may find v 1, v 2,..., v n

MAT115A-21 COMPLETE LECTURE NOTES

Section 0. Sets and Relations

Math 455 Some notes on Cardinality and Transfinite Induction

Cardinality and ordinal numbers

CHAPTER 1. Preliminaries. 1 Set Theory

FUNCTIONS WITH MANY LOCAL EXTREMA. 1. introduction

Diagonalize This. Iian Smythe. Department of Mathematics Cornell University. Olivetti Club November 26, 2013

2. Prime and Maximal Ideals

Notes for Math 290 using Introduction to Mathematical Proofs by Charles E. Roberts, Jr.

Informal Statement Calculus

3.C. Further comments on axioms for geometry

1. Continuous Functions between Euclidean spaces

Axioms of separation

1. (B) The union of sets A and B is the set whose elements belong to at least one of A

Universal Totally Ordered Sets

Transcription:

Products, Relations and Functions For a variety of reasons, in this course it will be useful to modify a few of the settheoretic preliminaries in the first chapter of Munkres. The discussion below explains these differences specifically. Cartesian Products and Relations Given two set-theoretic objects a and b, there is a set-theoretic construction which yields an which has the fundamental property ordered pair (a, b) (a, b) = (c, d) if and only if a = c and b = d. Given two sets A and B, the Cartesian product A B is defined to be the set of all ordered pairs (a, b) where a A and b B. We shall define a binary relation from A to B to be a triple R = (A, R 0, B) where A and B are sets and R 0 is a subset of A B. This differs from the standard definitions and the one in Munkres in two respects. First of all, the description in Munkres requires A = B. Also, we take the sets A and B as specific pieces of extra structure. Following standard notation we say that R 0 is the graph of R, and for a A and b B we write a R b if and only if (a, b) R 0 and say that a R b is true or a is R related to b. If B = A then we often say that R is a binary relation on A. Important special cases of binary relations including partial orderings and equivalence relations are discussed in Munkres. Functions Formally speaking, a function is a special type of relation. The main difference between our definition and the standard one is that the source set A (formally, the domain) and the target set B (formally, the codomain) are included explicitly as part of the structure. This point is often ignored in discussions of set theory (but an equivalent piece of structure is mentioned on page 16 of Munkres). Given the importance of the concept of function in mathematics, we shall give a complete formal definition.

Definition. A function is a triple f = (A, Γ, B) where A and B are sets and Γ is a subset of A B with the following property: ($$) For each a A there is a unique element b B such that (a, b) Γ. The sets A and B are respectively called the domain and codomain of f, and Γ is called the graph of f. Frequently we write f : A B to denote a function with domain A and codomain B, and as usual we write b = f(a) if and only if (a, b) lies in the graph of f. Given a function and a subset of its domain or codomain, we shall often need to work with the image or inverse image of the subset as defined on page 19 or Munkres. As indicated in the course notes, we shall deviate slightly from the notation in Munkres, using f[s] to denote the image of a subset S A under f and f 1 [T] to denote the inverse image of a subset T B under f. Many important properties of these constructions are summarized in the exercises on pages 20 and 21 of Munkres. One further property of the same sort is the following identity: If f : A B and g : B C, then g( f[s] ) = (g f )[S] for all S A. Conceptually, the crucial point in our definition is that it keeps track of the codomain. This turns out to be crucial for many mathematical constructions (for example, the fundamental group that is discussed in the second half of Munkres book). In particular, if B is a subset of B then Γ can be viewed as the graph of a function A B as well as the graph of a function f : A B. Notation. If f : A B is a function whose image lies in C B (i.e., the graph of f is actually a subset of A C ), then the associated function (A, Γ, C) will be denoted by C f and called the corestriction of f to C. The notation is meant to suggest that this is somehow complementary (or dual ) to the notion of restriction defined on page 17 of Munkres; in our notation the latter can be expressed as where S A. Disjoint unions f S = (S, Γ (S B), B) In many situations it is useful or even necessary to have a set S created from disjoint copies of two given sets A and B. Formally, the disjoint sum (or disjoint union) is defined to be the set

A B = A C B = A {1} B {2} and the standard injection mappings i A : A A B and i B : B A B are defined by i A (a) = (a, 1) and i B (b) = (b, 2) respectively. By construction, the maps i A and i B determine 1 1 correspondences from A to i A [A] and from B to i B [B], the images of A and B are disjoint (because the second coordinates of the ordered pairs are unequal), and their union is all of A B.. The Natural Numbers It is nearly impossible to do much mathematical work at all without using the natural numbers (the nonnegative integers) in one way or another. At this point we shall only need enough information about them to work with finite sets and mathematical induction, and it will suffice to view the natural numbers using the axioms for them formulated by G. Peano. PEANO AXIOMS. The natural numbers are given by a pair (N, σ) consisting of a set N and a function σ :N N with the following properties [which reflect the nature of sigma as a map taking each natural number m to its successor m + 1]: (1) There is exactly one element (the zero element) not in the image of σ. (2) The map sigma is one-to-one. (3) If A is a subset of N such that (i) 0 A, (ii) for all k N, k A implies σ (k) A, then A = N. The third axiom is just the (weak) principle of finite mathematical induction. The Peano axioms are sufficient to yield all the properties of natural numbers that are used in Munkres. Strictly speaking, the proofs of results like Theorem 4.1 and 4.2 require our axioms for the real number system, but we shall not have any need for these results until after the real number system has been introduced. All of the results in

Sections 6 and 8 of Munkres except those requiring the real numbers explicitly follow as in the text. The Axiom of Choice and Logical Consistency Although set theory provides an effective framework for discussing questions involving finite sets, its initial and most important motivation came from questions about infinite sets. As research on such sets progressed during the late nineteenth and early twentieth century, it eventually became evident that most of the underlying principles involved constructing new sets from old ones and the existence of the set of natural numbers. However, it also became clear that some results depended upon the Axiom of Choice (AC), which is an abstract and basically nonconstructive existence statement. There are many equivalent ways of formulating set-theoretic assumptions that are logically equivalent to the Axiom of Choice. Here is a list of several that appear in Munkres: Axiom of Choice. If A is a nonempty set and P + (A) denotes the set of all nonempty subsets of A, there is a function f : P + (A) A such that f(b) B for all nonempty B A. Zermelo s Well-ordering Theorem. For every nonempty set A, there is a linear ordering such that each nonempty subset B of A has a least element (i.e., there is a well-ordering of A). Hausdorff Maximal Principle. Every partially ordered set has a maximal linearly ordered subset. Zorn s Lemma. If A is a partially ordered set in which linearly ordered subsets have upper bounds, then A has a maximal element. For some time there was uncertainty whether the Axiom of Choice should be included in the axioms for set theory. Concern over this point increased with the discovery of apparent paradoxes in set theory around the beginning of the twentieth century. One example of this involves attempts to discuss the set of all sets. Most of the paradoxes were resolved by a careful foundation of the axioms for set theory, but it was not known if adding AC might still lead to a logical contradiction. The discovery of the so-called Banach-Tarski paradox in the nineteen twenties illustrated that AC had extremely strong consequences that raised questions about whether it should be taken as an axiom for set theory. In its original form, the result of S.

Banach and A. Tarski states that if AC is assumed, then it is possible to take a solid ball in 3-dimensional space, cut it up into finitely many pieces and, moving them using only rotation and translation, reassemble the pieces into two balls the same size as the original one!! At first glance this may appear to violate the laws of physics, but the sets in question are mathematical rather than physical objects. In particular, there is no meaningful way to define the volumes of the individual pieces, and it is impossible to carry out the construction physically because if one does cut the solid ball into pieces physically (say with a knife or saw), each piece has a specific volume (physically, one can find the volumes by sticking the pieces into a large cylinder with the right amount of water). Even though the Banach-Tarski paradox does not yield a contradiction to the axioms of set theory, it does raise two fundamental questions: 1. If set theory with AC yields bizarre conclusions like the existence of the sets described above, is it possible that further pursuits will lead to a contradiction? 2. Is it worthwhile to consider such objects, and if not is it appropriate to have an axiomatic system for set theory that implies the existence of such physically unreal entities? One way of answering the second question is that AC also implies the existence of many things that mathematicians do want for a variety of reasons. For example, one needs AC to conclude that every (infinite-dimensional) vector space has a basis. Although some mathematicians think that the subject should only consider objects given by suitably constructive methods, the existence results that follow from AC are so useful that mathematicians would prefer to include it as part of the axioms if at all possible. Of course, if AC leads to a logical contradiction, then it should not be part of the axioms for set theory, so this brings us back to the first question. Two extemely important and fundamental pieces of research by K. Gödel in the nineteen thirties clarified the role of AC. The first of these was his work on the incompleteness properties of axiomatic systems, and the essential conclusion is that mathematics can never be sure that any reasonable set of axioms for set theory is logically consistent. His subsequent result showed that AC was relatively consistent with the other axioms for set theory; specifically, if there is a logical contradiction in set theory with the inclusion of AC, then there is also a logical contradiction if one does not assume AC. If there is an internal contradiction in the axioms for set theory, it must arise either from the assumptions about constructing sets by specifying them in terms of logical statements or from the basic assumption that one can carry out fundamental set theoretic constructions on N. Since most mathematicians would prefer to include as many objects as possible in set theory so long as these objects do not lead to a logical contradiction, the effective consequence of relative consistency is that inclusion of AC in the axioms for set theory is appropriate.

Subsequent work of P. Cohen in the nineteen sixties completed our current understanding of the role of AC. Specifically, he showed that one can construct models for set theory such that AC was true for some models and false for others. The Continuum Hypothesis Another question about set theory that arose very early in the study of the subject was the Continuum Hypothesis : (CH) If A is an infinite subset of the real numbers R and there is no one-to-one correspondence between A and the natural numbers N, then there is a one-to-one correspondence between A and R. Since there is a one-to-one correspondence between R and the set P (N ) of all subsets of N, one can reformulate this as the first case of a more sweeping conjecture known as the Generalized Continuum Hypothesis : (GCH) If S is an infinite set and T is a subset of P (S), then either ( i ) there is a one-to-one correspondence between T and a subset of S, or else ( ii ) there is a one-toone correspondence between T and P (S). G. Cantor originally formulated CH in his work establishing set theory, the motivation being that he could not find any subsets whose cardinal numbers were between those of N and R. As in the case of AC, the work of Gödel showed that if a contradiction to the axioms for set theory arose if one assumes CH or GCH, then one can also obtain a contradiction without such an extra assumption, and the work of P. Cohen shows that one can construct models for set theory such that CH was true for some models and false for others. In fact, one can construct models for which the number of cardinalities between those of N and R can vary to some extent (for example, there might be one or two cardinalities between them). Because of Cohen s work, most mathematicians are not willing to assume CH or GCH for the same reason that they are willing to assume AC: They would prefer to include as many objects as possible in set theory so long as these objects do not lead to a logical contradiction.