Solution to Tutorial 9

Similar documents
Solution to Tutorial 9

Game Theory. Wolfgang Frimmel. Perfect Bayesian Equilibrium

Introduction to Game Theory

EC319 Economic Theory and Its Applications, Part II: Lecture 7

Game Theory. Monika Köppl-Turyna. Winter 2017/2018. Institute for Analytical Economics Vienna University of Economics and Business

Bayesian Games and Mechanism Design Definition of Bayes Equilibrium

MS&E 246: Lecture 12 Static games of incomplete information. Ramesh Johari

Game Theory. Strategic Form Games with Incomplete Information. Levent Koçkesen. Koç University. Levent Koçkesen (Koç University) Bayesian Games 1 / 15

Economics 3012 Strategic Behavior Andy McLennan October 20, 2006

University of Warwick, Department of Economics Spring Final Exam. Answer TWO questions. All questions carry equal weight. Time allowed 2 hours.

Introduction to Game Theory

Microeconomics for Business Practice Session 3 - Solutions

Backwards Induction. Extensive-Form Representation. Backwards Induction (cont ) The player 2 s optimization problem in the second stage

SF2972 Game Theory Exam with Solutions March 15, 2013

Informed Principal in Private-Value Environments

A Solution to the Problem of Externalities When Agents Are Well-Informed

Theory of Auctions. Carlos Hurtado. Jun 23th, Department of Economics University of Illinois at Urbana-Champaign

Solution to Tutorial 8

9 A Class of Dynamic Games of Incomplete Information:

Module 16: Signaling

Limit pricing models and PBE 1

Equilibrium Refinements

Lecture Note II-3 Static Games of Incomplete Information. Games of incomplete information. Cournot Competition under Asymmetric Information (cont )

Basics of Game Theory

EC319 Economic Theory and Its Applications, Part II: Lecture 2

Government 2005: Formal Political Theory I

Game Theory Correlated equilibrium 1

EconS Advanced Microeconomics II Handout on Repeated Games

UC Berkeley Haas School of Business Game Theory (EMBA 296 & EWMBA 211) Summer 2016

Mechanism Design II. Terence Johnson. University of Notre Dame. Terence Johnson (ND) Mechanism Design II 1 / 30

. Introduction to Game Theory Lecture Note 8: Dynamic Bayesian Games. HUANG Haifeng University of California, Merced

Wireless Network Pricing Chapter 6: Oligopoly Pricing

Dynamic Games and Bargaining. Johan Stennek

EconS Advanced Microeconomics II Handout on Subgame Perfect Equilibrium (SPNE)

6.254 : Game Theory with Engineering Applications Lecture 13: Extensive Form Games

Introduction to Game Theory

EconS Advanced Microeconomics II Handout on The Intuitive Criterion

Bargaining, Contracts, and Theories of the Firm. Dr. Margaret Meyer Nuffield College

Bayesian-Nash Equilibrium

Adverse Selection, Signaling, and Screening in Markets

Negotiation: Strategic Approach

Advanced Microeconomics

3.3.3 Illustration: Infinitely repeated Cournot duopoly.

Extensive Form Games with Perfect Information

Oligopoly. Oligopoly. Xiang Sun. Wuhan University. March 23 April 6, /149

Problem Set 6 Solutions

Deceptive Advertising with Rational Buyers

Industrial Organization Lecture 3: Game Theory

NTU IO (I) : Auction Theory and Mechanism Design II Groves Mechanism and AGV Mechansim. u i (x, t i, θ i ) = V i (x, θ i ) + t i,

Platform Competition under Asymmetric Information preliminary

Oligopoly. Molly W. Dahl Georgetown University Econ 101 Spring 2009

6.207/14.15: Networks Lecture 11: Introduction to Game Theory 3

On Renegotiation-Proof Collusion under Imperfect Public Information*

Introduction to Game Theory

An empirical model of firm entry with endogenous product-type choices

Teoria das organizações e contratos

Mechanism Design: Implementation. Game Theory Course: Jackson, Leyton-Brown & Shoham

Industrial Organization Lecture 7: Product Differentiation

Refinements - change set of equilibria to find "better" set of equilibria by eliminating some that are less plausible

Industrial Organization II (ECO 2901) Winter Victor Aguirregabiria. Problem Set #1 Due of Friday, March 22, 2013

EC3224 Autumn Lecture #03 Applications of Nash Equilibrium

EconS Sequential Competition

EconS Microeconomic Theory II Midterm Exam #2 - Answer Key

Lecture 6 Games with Incomplete Information. November 14, 2008

A Centralized or a Decentralized Labor Market?

Long-Run versus Short-Run Player

Political Economy of Institutions and Development: Problem Set 1. Due Date: Thursday, February 23, in class.

Mechanism Design. Christoph Schottmüller / 27

Wars of Attrition with Budget Constraints

Entry under an Information-Gathering Monopoly Alex Barrachina* June Abstract

Advanced Economic Theory Lecture 9. Bilateral Asymmetric Information. Double Auction (Chatterjee and Samuelson, 1983).

On the Informed Principal Model with Common Values

PERISHABLE DURABLE GOODS

Bayesian Nash equilibrium

Industrial Organization

Overview. Producer Theory. Consumer Theory. Exchange

Microeconomics II Lecture 4: Incomplete Information Karl Wärneryd Stockholm School of Economics November 2016

Answers to Spring 2014 Microeconomics Prelim

On the Unique D1 Equilibrium in the Stackelberg Model with Asymmetric Information Janssen, M.C.W.; Maasland, E.

Inefficient Equilibria of Second-Price/English Auctions with Resale

Perfect Bayesian Equilibrium. Definition. The single-crossing property. This is a draft; me with comments, typos, clarifications, etc.

Advanced Microeconomics

ECO 199 GAMES OF STRATEGY Spring Term 2004 Precepts Week 7 March Questions GAMES WITH ASYMMETRIC INFORMATION QUESTIONS

PERISHABLE DURABLE GOODS

Answer Key: Problem Set 3

1 The General Definition

Industrial Organization, Fall 2011: Midterm Exam Solutions and Comments Date: Wednesday October

DEMB Working Paper Series N. 39. Limit pricing and secret barriers to entry. Luigi Brighi * Marcello D Amato ** December 2014

Solving Extensive Form Games

Lecture 10: Mechanism Design

Dynamic Games, II: Bargaining

Extensive Form Games I

On Decentralized Incentive Compatible Mechanisms for Partially Informed Environments

Outline for Static Games of Incomplete Information

EconS Advanced Microeconomics II Handout on Perfect Bayesian Equilibrium

Online Appendix Durable Goods Monopoly with Stochastic Costs

Some Notes on Adverse Selection

4: Dynamic games. Concordia February 6, 2017

COMPETITION IN MARKETS WITH NETWORK EXTERNALITIES. Fatma Busra Gunay

Game Theory: introduction and applications to computer networks

Transcription:

Solution to Tutorial 9 2011/2012 Semester I MA4264 Game Theory Tutor: Xiang Sun October 27, 2011 Exercise 1. A buyer and a seller have valuations v b and v s. It is common knowledge that there are gains from trade (i.e., that v b > v s ), but the size of the gains is private information, as follows: the seller s valuation is uniformly distributed on [0, 1]; the buyer s valuation v b = k v s, where k > 1 is common knowledge; the seller knows v s (and hence v b ) but the buyer does not know v b (or v s ). Suppose the buyer makes a single offer, p, which the seller either accepts or rejects. What is the perfect Bayesian equilibrium when k < 2? When k > 2? Solution. The extensive-form representation of this game is as follows: Nature Buyer v s p Seller Accept Reject v b p, p 0, v s Figure 1 Clearly, the buyer has no incentive to offer p > 1, since the seller will accept p v s and v s is uniformly distributed on [0, 1]. By backwards induction, the seller s best response is { s accept, if v s p s(v s p) = reject, if v s < p. Corrections are always welcome. Email: xiangsun@nus.edu.sg; Mobile: 9169 7677; Office: S17-06-14. 1

MA4264 Game Theory 2/10 Solution to Tutorial 9 Note that we assume seller will accept if v s = p. This will not affect the our analysis of the game since the probability is zero for v s = p. The buyer s maximization problem is: max E[v b p v s p]. 0 p 1 Since v b = kv s, the buyer s maximization problem is: max 0 p 1 p Therefore, the maximizer is 0 (kv s p) dv s = max 0 p 1 (k/2 1)p2. p = { 1, if k > 2 0, if k < 2. Each information set of buyer is reached, so buyer s belief is a uniform distribution on [0, 1]. To summarize, the perfect Bayesian equilibrium is: { s b = p 1, if k > 2 = 0, if k < 2, and for v s [0, 1], accept, s s(v s p) = accept or reject, reject, if v s < p if v s = p, if v s < p the buyer s belief about the seller s valuation is a uniform distribution on [0, 1]. Exercise 2. Find the Bayesian equilibria for the first case of the job-market signaling games in which the output is changed to (i) y(η, e) = 3η+e, and (ii) y(η, e) = 4η. Solution. (i) Assume y(η, e) = 3η + e. The extensive-form representation is as follows:

MA4264 Game Theory 3/10 Solution to Tutorial 9 24, 36 [p] e c η H e s [q] 29, 1 14, 246 [ 1 2 ] 19, 121 Nature 18, 81 [ 1 2 ] 24, 196 9, 1 [1 p] e c η L e s [1 q] 14, 16 Worker The normal-form representation is as follows: T = {η H, η L }, M = {e c, e s }, A = {, }. Payoff table: e c e c 21, 117/2 21, 117/2 23/2, 247/2 23/2, 247/2 e c e s 24, 116 19, 26 19, 221 14, 131 e s e c 47/2, 41 37/2, 101 19, 1 14, 61 e s e s 53/2, 197/2 33/2, 137/2 53/2, 197/2 33/2, 137/2 Therefore, there are two pure-strategy Nash equilibria (e c e c, w h ) and (e s e s, ). For (e c e c, ): Requirement 1: Assume the believes on left information set and right information set are (p, 1 p) and (q, 1 q), respectively, displayed in the figure. Requirement 2S: Holds automatically. (since (e c e c, ) is a Nash equilibrium) Requirement 2R: q 3 5. Requirement 3: p = 1, q [0, 1]. 2 Thus, (e c e c, ) with p = 1 2 and q 3 5 For (e s e s, ): is a perfect Bayesian equilibrium. Requirement 1: Assume the believes on left information set and right information set are (p, 1 p) and (q, 1 q), respectively, displayed in the figure.

MA4264 Game Theory 4/10 Solution to Tutorial 9 Requirement 2S: Holds automatically. (since (e s e s, ) is a Nash equilibrium) Requirement 2R: p 4 15. Requirement 3: p [0, 1], q = 1 2. Thus, (e c e c, ) with p 4 and q = 1 is a perfect Bayesian equilibrium. 15 2 To summarize, there are three pure-strategy perfect Bayesian equilibria: (e c e c, ) with p = 1 2 and q 3 5 ; (e c e c, ) with p 4 15 and q = 1 2. (ii) Assume y(η, e) = 4η. The extensive-form representation is as follows: 24, 36 [p] e c η H e s [q] 29, 36 14, 256 [ 1 2 ] 19, 256 Nature 19, 196 [ 1 2 ] 24, 196 9, 16 [1 p] e c η L e s [1 q] 14, 16 The normal-form representation is as follows: T = {η H, η L }, M = {e c, e s }, A = {, }. Payoff table: Worker e c e c 43/2, 116 43/2, 116 23/2, 136 23/2, 136 e c e s 24, 116 19, 26 19, 226 14, 136 e s e c 24, 116 19, 226 19, 26 14, 136 e s e s 53/2, 116 33/2, 136 53/2, 116 33/2, 136 Therefore, there are three pure-strategy Nash equilibria (e c e c, w h ), (e s e s, ) and (e s e s, ). For (e c e c, ):

MA4264 Game Theory 5/10 Solution to Tutorial 9 Requirement 1: Assume the believes on left information set and right information set are (p, 1 p) and (q, 1 q), respectively, displayed in the figure. Requirement 2S: Holds automatically. (since (e c e c, ) is a Nash equilibrium) Requirement 2R: q 9. 20 Requirement 3: p = 1, q [0, 1]. 2 Thus, (e c e c, ) with p = 1 and q 9 2 20 For (e s e s, ): is a perfect Bayesian equilibrium. Requirement 1: Assume the believes on left information set and right information set are (p, 1 p) and (q, 1 q), respectively, displayed in the figure. Requirement 2S: Holds automatically. equilibrium) Requirement 2R: p 9 20. Requirement 3: p [0, 1], q = 1 2. Thus, (e s e s, ) with p 9 and q = 1 20 2 For (e s e s, ): (since (e s e s, ) is a Nash is a perfect Bayesian equilibrium. Requirement 1: Assume the believes on left information set and right information set are (p, 1 p) and (q, 1 q), respectively, displayed in the figure. Requirement 2S: Holds automatically. (since (e s e s, ) is a Nash equilibrium) Requirement 2R: p 9 20. Requirement 3: p [0, 1], q = 1 2. Thus, (e s e s, ) with p 9 and q = 1 is a perfect Bayesian equilibrium. 20 2 To summarize, there are three pure-strategy perfect Bayesian equilibria: (e c e c, ) with p = 1 2 and q 9 20 ; (e s e s, ) with p 9 20 and q = 1 2 ; (e s e s, ) with p 9 20 and q = 1 2. Exercise 3. Consider the job-market signaling game where c(η, e) and y(η, e) are general functions and w is chosen from the action space [0, ). (i) For each of the separating strategies (e c, e s ) and (e s, e c ), write down conditions on c and y under which the separating perfect Bayesian equilibria exist.

MA4264 Game Theory 6/10 Solution to Tutorial 9 (ii) Find concrete and reasonable examples of c(η, e) and y(η, e) which satisfy the conditions you present in (i). Solution. (i) Suppose in a perfect Bayesian equilibrium, e c e s is worker s strategy. Then by Bayes rule, we have p = 1 and q = 0. For firm, given message e c, his maximization problem is max 0 w [w y(η H, e c )] 2, and hence the best choice is w c = y(η H, e c ). Similarly, given message e s, firm s best choice is w s = y(η L, e s ). For worker, given firm s strategy (wc, ws), when η H occurs, e c is the best response, that is, y(η H, e c ) c(η H, e c ) y(η L, e s ) e(η H, e s ). Similarly, when η L occurs, we have Thus, (ii) Exercise. y(η H, e c ) c(η L, e c ) y(η L, e s ) c(η L, e s ). c(η L, e c ) c(η L, e s ) y(η H, e c ) y(η L, e s ) c(η H, e c ) c(η H, e s ). Exercise 4. Suppose the HAL Corporation is a monopolist in the Cleveland market for mainframe computers. We will suppose that the market is a natural monopoly, meaning that only one firm can survive in the long run. HAL faces only one potential competitor, DEC. In the first period, HAL moves first and chooses one of two prices for its computers: High or Low. DEC moves second and decides whether to enter the market or not. Here are the first-period profits of the two firms: In the second HAL DEC Enter StayOut High 0, 0 5, 0 Low 0, 0 1, 0 period, three things can occur: (a) DEC did not enter in the first period. Then HAL retains its monopoly forever and earns monopoly profits of 125 C, where C is its costs. DEC earns zero profits. (b) DEC entered in the first period and has the lower costs. HAL leaves the market and DEC gets the monopoly forever, earning the monopoly profits of 100 = 125 25, where 25 are its costs, which is common knowledge. HAL earns zero profits.

MA4264 Game Theory 7/10 Solution to Tutorial 9 (c) DEC entered in the first period and HAL has the lower costs. In this case, DEC drops out of the market, HAL retains its monopoly forever, and it earns monopoly profits of 125 C, where C is its costs. DEC earns zero profits. DEC s payoff from playing this game equals 0 if it decides to stay out, and it equals the sum of its profits in the two periods minus entry costs of 40 if it decides to enter. HAL s payoff equals the sum of its profits in the two periods. HAL s costs, C, can be either 30 (high) or 20 (low). This cost information is private information. DEC only knows that Prob(C = 20) = 0.75 and Prob(C = 30) = 0.25. Formulate the problem as a signaling game and find all perfect Bayesian equilibria. Solution. The signaling game is as follows: T = {c L = 20, c H = 30}, M = {H(igh), L(ow)}, and A = {E(nter), S(tayout)}. The extensive-form representation is as follows: 105, 40 E [p] H c L L [q] E 105, 40 110, 0 S [ 3 4 ] S 106, 0 DEC Nature DEC 0, 60 E [ 1 4 ] E 0, 60 100, 0 S [1 p] H c H L [1 q] S 96, 0 The normal-form representation is: HAL DEC EE ES SE SS HH 78.75, 15 78.75, 15 107.5, 0 107.5, 0 HL 78.75, 15 102.75, 30 82.5, 15 106.5, 0 LH 78.75, 15 79.5, 15 103.75, 30 104.5, 0 LL 78.75, 15 103.5, 0 78.75, 15 103.5, 0 There are three pure-strategy Nash equilibria (HH, SE), (HH, SS) and (LL, ES). For (HH, SE): Requirement 1: Assume the believes on left information set and right information set are (p, 1 p) and (q, 1 q), respectively, displayed in the figure.

MA4264 Game Theory 8/10 Solution to Tutorial 9 Requirement 2S: Holds automatically. (since (HH, SE) is a Nash equilibrium) Requirement 2R: q 0.6. Requirement 3: p = 3, q [0, 1]. 4 Thus, (HH, SE) with p = 3 4 For (HH, SS): and q 0.6 is a perfect Bayesian equilibrium. Requirement 1: Assume the believes on left information set and right information set are (p, 1 p) and (q, 1 q), respectively, displayed in the figure. Requirement 2S: Holds automatically. (since (HH, SS) is a Nash equilibrium) Requirement 2R: q 0.6. Requirement 3: p = 3, q [0, 1]. 4 Thus, (HH, SS) with p = 3 4 For (LL, ES): and q 0.6 is a perfect Bayesian equilibrium. Requirement 1: Assume the believes on left information set and right information set are (p, 1 p) and (q, 1 q), respectively, displayed in the figure. Requirement 2S: Holds automatically. (since (LL, ES) is a Nash equilibrium) Requirement 2R: p 0.6. Requirement 3: p [0, 1], q = 3 4. Thus, (LL, ES) with p 0.6 and q = 3 is a perfect Bayesian equilibrium. 4 To summarize, there are three pure-strategy perfect Bayesian equilibria: (HH, SE) with p = 3 4 (HH, SS) with p = 3 4 and q 0.6; and q 0.6; (LL, ES) with p 0.6 and q = 3 4. Exercise 5. There are two Players in the game: Judge and Plaintiff. The Plaintiff has been injured. Severity of the injury, denoted by v, is the Plaintiff s private information. The Judge does not know v and believes that v is uniformly distributed on {0, 1,..., 9} (so that the probability that v = i is 1 for any i {0, 1,..., 9}). 10 The Plaintiff can verifiably reveal v to the Judge without any cost, in which case the Judge will know v. The order of the events is as follows. First, the Plaintiff decides whether to reveal v or not. Then, the Judge rewards a compensation R which can be any nonnegative real number. The payoff of the Plaintiff is R v, and the payoff of the Judge is (v R) 2. Everything described so far is common knowledge. Find a perfect Bayesian equilibrium.

MA4264 Game Theory 9/10 Solution to Tutorial 9 Solution. The signaling game is as follows: T = {0, 1,..., 9}; M = {R, N}, where R is Reveal and N is Not Reveal ; A = R +. From the extensive-form representation, there are 10 subgames, and Judge has 11 information sets I v, v = 0, 1,..., 10, where for each v 9, I v denotes that Plaintiff reveals v to Judge, and I 10 denotes the case that Plaintiff does not reveal the value. Plaintiff s strategy space is Judge s strategy space is S = {f f : T M} = {R, N} 10. Q = {(x 0, x 1,..., x 9, x 10 ): x i 0}, where x i is the action at the information set I i. Given any strategy s of Plaintiff, let s 1 (N) = {v : s(v) = N}, which denotes the set of Plaintiff s types at which the value is not revealed to Judge. Claim 1: Given any strategy s of Plaintiff, if s 1 (N), let n = s 1 (N). Then in a perfect Bayesian equilibrium, Judge s strategy should be q v (s) = 0, 1,..., 9,. n v s 1 (N) By backwards induction, Judge should choose v at the information set I v when v 9. At the information set I 10, which is on the equilibrium path, only the branches v, where v s 1 (N) can be reached. Thus, by Bayes rule, Judge believes that

MA4264 Game Theory 10/10 Solution to Tutorial 9 these branches are reached with equal probability, 1, where n = n s 1 (N). Thus, Judge s maximization problem is max 1 (x v) 2. x R + n v s 1 (N) It is easy to find the unique maximizer x (s) = 1 n v s 1 (N) v. Claim 2: In any subgame-perfect Nash equilibrium of this game, Plaintiff s strategy s should satisfy the following condition s 1 (N) = {0} or. Case 1: assume s 1 (N) = {v 0 }, where v 0 0. Given such a Plaintiff s strategy s, that is, s(v 0 ) = N, and s(v) = R for others v. By Claim 1, Judge s best response is q (s) = (0, 1, 2,..., 9, v 0 ). However, s is not a best response for Plaintiff given Judge s strategy q (s) = (0, 1, 2,..., 9, v 0 ): at the type 0, Plaintiff can be better off if he chooses Not Reveal rather then Reveal, since v 0 > 0. Case 2: assume s 1 (N) contains at least 2 elements. Let v 1 = min s 1 (N), and v 2 = max s 1 (N). Note that, v 1 < x (s) = 1 v < v 2. n By Claim 2, Judge s best response is v s 1 (N) q (s) = 0, 1, 2,..., 9, v s 1 (N) v. n ( However, s is not a best response for Plaintiff given Judges strategy q (s) = 0, 1, 2,..., 9, ) v s 1 (N) : at type t 2, Plaintiff can get a higher amount v 2 by v n revealing, since v 2 > v s 1 (N) Claim 3: v. n s(v) R, q = (0, 1, 2,..., 9, 0) with belief (1, 0,..., 0) on I 10 is a perfect Bayesian equilibrium: By Claims 1 and 2, this strategy profile is a subgame-perfect Nash equilibrium. Assume Judge s belief at the information set I 10 is (p 0, p 1,..., p 9 ), then Judge s maximization problem is max p 0 (x 0) 2 p 1 (x 1) 2 p 9 (x 9) 2. x R + Then the unique maximizer is x = p 0 0 + p 1 1 + + p 9 9. We know that x = 0, this implies p 0 = 1 and p 1 = p 2 = = p 9 = 0, that is, Judge believes that v = 0 with probability 1. Claim 4: { s(v) = R, if v > 0, N, if v = 0 q = (0, 1, 2,..., 9, 0) with belief (1, 0,..., 0) on I 10 is a perfect Bayesian equilibrium. (Exercise)