Notes I Classical Demand Theory: Review of Important Concepts

Similar documents
Utility Maximization Problem

Hicksian Demand and Expenditure Function Duality, Slutsky Equation

Consumer theory Topics in consumer theory. Microeconomics. Joana Pais. Fall Joana Pais

Structural Properties of Utility Functions Walrasian Demand

Revealed Preferences and Utility Functions

Utility Maximization Problem. Advanced Microeconomic Theory 2

Lecture 1. History of general equilibrium theory

Microeconomic Theory-I Washington State University Midterm Exam #1 - Answer key. Fall 2016

Consumer Theory. Ichiro Obara. October 8, 2012 UCLA. Obara (UCLA) Consumer Theory October 8, / 51

The Fundamental Welfare Theorems

Advanced Microeconomic Theory. Chapter 2: Demand Theory

Notes on Consumer Theory

Week 7: The Consumer (Malinvaud, Chapter 2 and 4) / Consumer November Theory 1, 2015 (Jehle and 1 / Reny, 32

Notes IV General Equilibrium and Welfare Properties

i) This is simply an application of Berge s Maximum Theorem, but it is actually not too difficult to prove the result directly.

GARP and Afriat s Theorem Production

Week 9: Topics in Consumer Theory (Jehle and Reny, Chapter 2)

DECISIONS AND GAMES. PART I

Last Revised: :19: (Fri, 12 Jan 2007)(Revision:

Advanced Microeconomics Preliminary Remarks

Microeconomics, Block I Part 1

Microeconomic Analysis

Recitation #2 (August 31st, 2018)

Generalized Convexity in Economics

CONSUMER DEMAND. Consumer Demand

Microeconomics II Lecture 4. Marshallian and Hicksian demands for goods with an endowment (Labour supply)

On the (Non-)Differentiability of the Optimal Value Function When the Optimal Solution Is Unique

ECON501 - Vector Di erentiation Simon Grant

PS4-Solution. Mehrdad Esfahani. Fall Arizona State University. Question 1 Question 2 Question 3 Question 4 Question 5

PhD Qualifier Examination

Properties of Walrasian Demand

Advanced Microeconomics Fall Lecture Note 1 Choice-Based Approach: Price e ects, Wealth e ects and the WARP

Preferences and Utility

Advanced Microeconomic Analysis Solutions to Midterm Exam

Microeconomics I Fall 2007 Prof. I. Hafalir

Week 6: Consumer Theory Part 1 (Jehle and Reny, Chapter 1)

[For Glaeser Midterm : Not helpful for Final or Generals] Matthew Basilico

Competitive Consumer Demand 1

Rice University. Answer Key to Mid-Semester Examination Fall ECON 501: Advanced Microeconomic Theory. Part A

CONSUMPTION. (Lectures 4, 5, and 6) Remark: (*) signals those exercises that I consider to be the most important

Technical Results on Regular Preferences and Demand

Final Exam - Math Camp August 27, 2014

Econ 5150: Applied Econometrics Empirical Demand Analysis. Sung Y. Park CUHK

Recitation 2-09/01/2017 (Solution)

Course Handouts ECON 4161/8001 MICROECONOMIC ANALYSIS. Jan Werner. University of Minnesota

EC487 Advanced Microeconomics, Part I: Lecture 2

Microeconomics. Joana Pais. Fall Joana Pais

Question 1. (p p) (x(p, w ) x(p, w)) 0. with strict inequality if x(p, w) x(p, w ).

In the Name of God. Sharif University of Technology. Microeconomics 1. Graduate School of Management and Economics. Dr. S.

Solution Homework 1 - EconS 501

The Utility Frontier

Mathematical models in economy. Short descriptions

Microeconomic Theory I Midterm

Advanced Microeconomics I: Consumers, Firms and Markets Chapters 1+2

EC /11. Math for Microeconomics September Course, Part II Lecture Notes. Course Outline

E 600 Chapter 4: Optimization

Economics th April 2011

Chapter 1 - Preference and choice

Midterm Exam, Econ 210A, Fall 2008

Lakehead University ECON 4117/5111 Mathematical Economics Fall 2002

Notes on General Equilibrium

CHAPTER 2: CONVEX SETS AND CONCAVE FUNCTIONS. W. Erwin Diewert January 31, 2008.

Introductory Microeconomics

Advanced Microeconomic Analysis, Lecture 6

1 General Equilibrium

Alfred Marshall s cardinal theory of value: the strong law of demand

Advanced Microeconomics

Ph.D. Preliminary Examination MICROECONOMIC THEORY Applied Economics Graduate Program May 2012

Midterm #1 EconS 527 Wednesday, February 21st, 2018

CHAPTER 4: HIGHER ORDER DERIVATIVES. Likewise, we may define the higher order derivatives. f(x, y, z) = xy 2 + e zx. y = 2xy.

Mathematical Economics: Lecture 16

Functions. Paul Schrimpf. October 9, UBC Economics 526. Functions. Paul Schrimpf. Definition and examples. Special types of functions

Advanced Microeconomics

September Math Course: First Order Derivative

Final Examination with Answers: Economics 210A

Economics 501B Final Exam Fall 2017 Solutions

Chapter 1 Consumer Theory Part II

General Equilibrium. General Equilibrium, Berardino. Cesi, MSc Tor Vergata

The Fundamental Welfare Theorems

Microeconomic Theory -1- Introduction

Demand Theory. Lecture IX and X Utility Maximization (Varian Ch. 7) Federico Trionfetti

Lecture 7: General Equilibrium - Existence, Uniqueness, Stability

Department of Agricultural Economics. PhD Qualifier Examination. May 2009

The Ohio State University Department of Economics. Homework Set Questions and Answers

Choice under Uncertainty

Duality. for The New Palgrave Dictionary of Economics, 2nd ed. Lawrence E. Blume

Solutions to selected exercises from Jehle and Reny (2001): Advanced Microeconomic Theory

x 1 1 and p 1 1 Two points if you just talk about monotonicity (u (c) > 0).

ECON 255 Introduction to Mathematical Economics

Microeconomics II. MOSEC, LUISS Guido Carli Problem Set n 3

Convergence of Non-Normalized Iterative

Advanced Microeconomic Theory. Chapter 6: Partial and General Equilibrium

Positive Theory of Equilibrium: Existence, Uniqueness, and Stability

Applications I: consumer theory

1 + x 1/2. b) For what values of k is g a quasi-concave function? For what values of k is g a concave function? Explain your answers.

EC487 Advanced Microeconomics, Part I: Lecture 5

Individual decision-making under certainty

1 Preference and choice

EC /11. Math for Microeconomics September Course, Part II Problem Set 1 with Solutions. a11 a 12. x 2

EconS 501 Final Exam - December 10th, 2018

Transcription:

Notes I Classical Demand Theory: Review of Important Concepts The notes for our course are based on: Mas-Colell, A., M.D. Whinston and J.R. Green (1995), Microeconomic Theory, New York and Oxford: Oxford University Press, which I will refer to as MWG. The notes review important concepts, however, in no way can the notes substitute for a thorough reading of MWG s text. 1 Notation Notice, we are working with scalars, vectors and matrices. At every step please make sure you are aware of the respective dimension of a variable (particularly, whether it is a scalar, a vector or a matrix). Basically, a vector in R N is a column vector! We denote the gradient vector of a function f(x) : R N R where x R N, N 1 at point x by f( x) R N. So, the nth row of f( x) equals f( x)/ x n, where x n is the nth element of vector x. The inner product of two vectors, x and y, is written as x y, i.e., x y = x T y, where x T is the transpose of x (i.e., a row vector). As a rule of thumb, an expression like x can always be read as x T. Consider a vector x R N. A statement like x 0 means that all elements of the vector are nonnegative: x i 0, i = 1,..., N. Similarly, x = 0 says: x i = 0, i = 1,..., N. Finally, x 0 says: x i > 0, i = 1,..., N, i.e., all elements of vector x are strictly positive: x 0 x R N ++, and x 0 x R N +. Let s consider two important matrices, the Jacobian and the Hessian. Suppose f is a vector valued function, i.e., f : R N R M. So there are m functions, each of which is defined on R N. The Jacobian matrix of f(x) is denoted by Df(x). Certainly, the Jacobian matrix of f(x) is a matrix of dimension M N whose mnth entry is f m / x n. Now suppose not all of the variables, over which the functions are defined, change. Specifically, consider f(x, y), where only the variables x R K change, but not so the variables y R L. Then, D x f(x, y) denotes the Jacobian matrix obtained by differentiating the M functions with respect to the Ronald Wendner I-1 v1.4

variables x i, i = 1,..., K only (and holding the variables y constant). The dimension of this Jacobian matrix, thus, is M K. Consider a function g : R N R (so we are just having a single function). The Hessian matrix of g(x), D( g(x)), is denoted by D 2 g(x), with mnth element [ g(x)/ x m ]/ x n. As x R N, the dimension of the Hessian matrix is N N. Query: What is the Jacobian matrix of a function g(z 1, z 2 ), i.e., when M = 1? Calculate the Hessian matrix of the function g(z 1, z 2 ). Summary of Differentiation in Matrix Notation. 1.) Consider a single function f : R N R. Then Df(x) is the Jacobian which, in this case, equals the transpose of the gradient: Df(x) = [ f(x)] T. Moreover, D 2 f(x) is the N N Hessian matrix whose mnth entry is 2 f(x)/( x m x n ). 2.) Now, consider a vector-valued function f : R N R M. Then Df(x) is the M N Jacobian whose mnth entry is f m (x)/ x n. 3.) Finally, consider f(g(x)), where f : R K R M, g : R N R K, and x R N. In words: there are K functions g k (x 1,..., x N ), and there are M functions f m (x) of g(x): f 1 (g 1 (x),..., g k (x)) f 2 (g 1 (x),..., g k (x))... f m (g 1 (x),..., g k (x)), or, shortly, f(g(x)). What is D x f(g(x))? Here comes the beauty of matrix notation. The derivative according to the product rule simply is: D x f(g(x)) = Df(g(x)) Dg(x). Just to make clear the dimensions: D x f(g(x)) [M N] = Df(g(x)) [M K] Dg(x) [K N]. 2 Setup We start our course with a review of important definitions (I assume you are familiar with these concepts from the Bakk-VWL courses). A market economy is (... an economy beware! notice we did not yet define what we mean by economy so we rather say) a setting where Ronald Wendner I-2 v1.4

goods and services are available for purchase at publicly known prices that consumers and firms take as unaffected by their own decisions (price taking assumption). Moreover, consumers trade in the marketplace to maximize well-being, and firms produce and trade to maximize profits. Consumption space: L commodities: l = 1,..., L; commodity bundle: x R L, where R L represents the commodity space. The consumption set, X, is a subset of the commodity space: X R L. Usually, we let X = R L + = {x R L : x l 0 for l = 1,..., L}, which also implies that the consumption set is convex. Budget Set: Let the price vector p R L be strictly positive: p R L ++, or, equivalently, p 0. Also, denote the consumer s wealth level (in euros or dollars, etc.) by w. Then, the Walrasian, or competitive budget set, is B p,w = {x R L + : p x w} Notice: B p,w X. Query: Consider any two points, x, x in the set B 0 = {x R L + : p x = w}. What does p (x x ) amount to? Interpret! Walrasian demand correspondence: 1 The consumer s Walrasian demand correspondence assigns to each price-wealth pair the set of optimal consumption bundles x from the budget set. I.e., x = x(p, w) = {x R L + : x x for all x B p,w }. Make sure you understand that x(p, w) represents a system of L functions (or correspondences) of (L + 1) variables i.e., a vector-valued function (correspondence) with M = L, N = L + 1. 3 Preference Relations and Utility: Basic Properties We denote a preference relation by a binary relation, on the consumption set X (=R L +). 2 Preferences are said to be rational if they are (i) complete: for all x, y X: x y or y x, or both, and 1 A correspondence is a kind of function. Suppose our domain is A R N. A (real valued) function f : A R is a rule that assigns to every x A a single value f(x) R (a singleton). In contrast, a (real valued) correspondence ϕ(x) : A R K is a rule that assigns to every x A a set ϕ(x) R K (which is not necessarily a singleton). Obviously, every function is a correspondence. But a correspondence is a function if and only if for every x A we have that ϕ(x) is a singleton. 2 A binary relation on a set X is a rule such that for each x and y in X, we can determine whether x y, y x, or neither, or both, where x y reads x is weakly preferred to y. Ronald Wendner I-3 v1.4

(ii) transitive: for all x, y, z X: x y and y z x z. A utility function u : X R assigns a numerical value to each element of X. It represents the preference relation if, for all x, y X, x y u(x) u(y). Notice that a utility function representing is not unique. Any strict increasing function g : R R, v(x) = g(u(x)), is a new utility function representing the same preferences. Also, a preference relation can be represented by a utility function only if (a) is rational, and (b) is continuous. Rationality, we already defined. Remains continuity... on X is continuous if it is preserved under limits. I.e., for any sequence of pairs {x n, y n } n=1 with x n y n for all n, and with x = lim n x n, and y = lim n y n we have: x y. Remark 1. By the definition of closedness of a set 3, continuity of implies that for all x X both the upper contour set, {x X : x x}, and the lower contour set, {x X : x x } are closed sets. 4 Remark 2. Lexicographic preferences are not continuous (hence, cannot be represented by a utility function). 5 A preference relation on X is locally nonsatiated if for every x X and every ɛ > 0, within the ɛ-ball about x, B ɛ (x) 6, there is an x B ɛ (x) such that x x. Notice that local nonsatiation rules out thick indifference curves. A stronger version of nonsatiation is monotonicity, where x x if x x. An even stronger version is strong monotonicity for which x x if x x. A preference relation on X is (strictly) convex if for every x X the upper contour set is convex. is convex if and only if u(x) is quasiconcave. Notice that if is strictly convex, then for any two consumption vectors x, y: x z and y z, we have for all α (0, 1): α x + (1 α) y z. 3 Consider all converging sequences {x n i } n=1 in A (i.e., every element of a sequence {x n i } n=1 belongs to the set A), and denote the respective limit point by x i. The set A R N is closed if for every converging sequence in A, x i A. 4 The upper and lower contour sets can be respectively described as no worse than-set and no better than-set. 5 Remember, lexicographic on R 2 are defined in the following way: x x if either x 1 > x 1 or (x 1 = x 1 and x 2 x 2). 6 Consider the consumption space X. An ɛ-ball about x X is defined to be B ɛ (x) {x X : x x < ɛ}. Ronald Wendner I-4 v1.4

4 Utility Maximization and Walrasian Demand The utility maximization problem (UMP) is defined as: max x 0 u(x) such that p x w. A solution to the UMP exists, if p 0, x 0 and are continuous. The solution of the UMP, x(p, w), is the Walrasian demand correspondence. Query: Interpret the Lagrangian multiplier of the UMP. Proposition 1 Properties of the Walrasian demand correspondence when preferences are continuous, and locally nonsatiated on the consumption set X: (1) Homogeneity of degree zero: x(p, w) = x(α p, α w), α > 0, (2) Walras law: p x = w for all x x(p, w), (3) Convexity/uniqueness: if preferences are convex (i.e., the utility function is quasiconcave), x(p, w) is a convex set. If preferences are strictly convex (i.e., the utility function is strictly quasiconcave), x(p, w) is a singleton (i.e., the Walrasian demand correspondence is in fact a Walrasian demand function. Given the Walrasian demand correspondence, we can define the indirect utility function as follows: v(p, w) u(x(p, w)). Proposition 2 If on X are continuous and locally nonsatiated, v(p, w) has the following properties: (1) v(p, w) = v(α p, α w), α > 0, (2) v w (p, w) > 0, and v pl (p, w) 0 for all l, 7 (3) v(p, w) is quasiconvex, i.e., the set {(p, w) : v(p, w) v} is convex for any v, (4) v(p, w) is continuous in p and w. 8 7 v w (p, w) v(p, w)/ w, and v pl (p, w) v(p, w)/ p l, etc. 8 Let Z R L+1 denote: Z = {(p, w) : p 0 & w = wealth}. Recall that v(p, w) : R L+1 R is continuous at ( p, w) if for every ɛ R ++, there exists a δ R ++ such that for all (p, w) B δ ( p, w) Z : v(p, w) v( p, w) < ɛ. v(p, w) is continuous on Z if v(p, w) is continuous at each (p, w) Z. Ronald Wendner I-5 v1.4

5 Expenditure Minimization and Hicksian Demand The expenditure minimization problem (EMP) is defined as: min x 0 p x such that u(x) u 0. The EMP is the dual problem to the UMP. The solution of the EMP, h(p, u 0 ), is the Hicksian demand correspondence. Query: Under which conditions is there a solution to the EMP? Query: Interpret the Lagrangian multiplier of the EMP. The Hicksian demand correspondence (or utility-compensated demand correspondence) represents the set of least-cost consumption bundles (at prices p) for which u(x) = u 0. Proposition 3 Suppose preferences are continuous, and locally nonsatiated on the consumption set X, and p 0. Then h(p, u 0 ) is: (1) Homogeneous of degree zero (HD 0 ) in p, (2) For any x h(p, u 0 ): u(x) = u 0, (3) Convexity/uniqueness: if are convex, h(p, u 0 ) is a convex set. If preferences are strictly convex, h(p, u 0 ) is a singleton. The value function, e(p, u 0 ), is called expenditure function. e(p, u 0 ) p h(p, u 0 ) represents the minimum expenditures necessary (at prices p) to purchase a commodity bundle that yields utility level u 0. Proposition 4 Suppose preferences are continuous, and locally nonsatiated on the consumption set X: Then e(p, u 0 ) is: (1) Homogeneous of degree one in p, (2) Strictly increasing in u 0 and nondecreasing in p l, (3) Concave in p, (4) Continuous in p and u 0. 6 True Facts (1) u(h(p, u 0 )) = u 0 (2) e(p, u 0 ) = p h(p, u 0 ) (3) v(p, e(p, u 0 )) = u 0 (4) e(p, v(p, w)) = w Ronald Wendner I-6 v1.4

(5) x(p, w) = h(p, v(p, w)) (6) h(p, u 0 ) = p e(p, u 0 ) (7) D p h(p, u 0 ) = D p x(p, w) + D w x(p, w) x(p, w) T (8) x l (p, w) = [ v(p, w)/ p l ]/[ v(p, w)/ w], for all l = 1,... L Relation (7) are the L 2 Slutsky equations. According to (7), the change in compensated demand of good l due to a change in p k is given by: h l (p, u 0 ) = x l(p, w) + x l(p, w) x k (p, w). p k p k w Finally, relationship (8) is called Roy s Identity. 7 Bonus Stuff Proposition 5 Suppose preferences are continuous, locally nonsatiated, and convex on the consumption set X, and h(., u 0 ) is continuously differentiable at (p, w). Denote its L L derivative matrix by D p h(p, u 0 ). Then: (1) D p h(p, u 0 ) = D 2 p e(p, u 0 ), (2) D p h(p, u 0 ) is a negative semidefinite matrix, (3) D p h(p, u 0 ) is a symmetric matrix, (4) D p h(p, u 0 ) p = 0. (1) follows directly from property (6) above and shows that D p h(p, u 0 ) is the Hessian matrix of e(p, u 0 ). (2) represents the fact that e(p, u 0 ) is a concave function. Moreover it implies non-positive own price effects. (3) is implied by Young s Theorem and implies symmetric compensated responses to price changes. (4) comes from the fact that h(p, u 0 ) is HD 0 in p. Ronald Wendner I-7 v1.4