Expected Utility. Tommaso Denti. February 7, 2015

Similar documents
Expected Scott-Suppes Utility Representation

Subjective Expected Utility

Chapter 2. Decision Making under Risk. 2.1 Consequences and Lotteries

Expected Utility Framework

Notes on Supermodularity and Increasing Differences. in Expected Utility

Choice Under Uncertainty

Von Neumann Morgenstern Expected Utility. I. Introduction, Definitions, and Applications. Decision Theory Spring 2014

Dominance and Admissibility without Priors

LECTURE 11: AXIOMATIC SET THEORY PART 3

Continuity and completeness of strongly independent preorders

CONSTRUCTION OF sequence of rational approximations to sets of rational approximating sequences, all with the same tail behaviour Definition 1.

A utility representation theorem with weaker continuity condition

Intransitive Indifference Under Uncertainty: Expected Scott-Suppes Utility Representation

When are Sums Closed?

A revealed preference test for weakly separable preferences

Recitation 7: Uncertainty. Xincheng Qiu

Lexicographic Refinements in the Context of Possibilistic Decision Theory

NOTES ON SOME EXERCISES OF LECTURE 5, MODULE 2

Preference for Commitment

Cautious Expected Utility and the Certainty Effect

Lecture 2: Period Three Implies Chaos

3 Intertemporal Risk Aversion

Division of the Humanities and Social Sciences. Sums of sets, etc.

Chapter 1 - Preference and choice

Theorem (4.11). Let M be a closed subspace of a Hilbert space H. For any x, y E, the parallelogram law applied to x/2 and y/2 gives.

Risk Aversion over Incomes and Risk Aversion over Commodities. By Juan E. Martinez-Legaz and John K.-H. Quah 1

Mathematical Social Sciences

A NICE PROOF OF FARKAS LEMMA

Game Theory. Lecture Notes By Y. Narahari. Department of Computer Science and Automation Indian Institute of Science Bangalore, India August 2012

Functional Analysis. Martin Brokate. 1 Normed Spaces 2. 2 Hilbert Spaces The Principle of Uniform Boundedness 32

Abstract Measure Theory

Demand Theory. Lecture IX and X Utility Maximization (Varian Ch. 7) Federico Trionfetti

Preferences and Utility

Lecture 4 Lebesgue spaces and inequalities

LECTURE 3 LECTURE OUTLINE

Second-Order Expected Utility

Lecture 4: September Reminder: convergence of sequences

Second Exam. Math , Spring March 2015

Coalitional Strategic Games

NOTES (1) FOR MATH 375, FALL 2012

Math 341: Convex Geometry. Xi Chen

David Hilbert was old and partly deaf in the nineteen thirties. Yet being a diligent

Optimization under Ordinal Scales: When is a Greedy Solution Optimal?

Technical Results on Regular Preferences and Demand

An Axiomatic Model of Reference Dependence under Uncertainty. Yosuke Hashidate

Algebraic Geometry Spring 2009

This corresponds to a within-subject experiment: see same subject make choices from different menus.

CLASSICAL PROBABILITY MODES OF CONVERGENCE AND INEQUALITIES

Sequence convergence, the weak T-axioms, and first countability

Topological properties

Convex Analysis and Economic Theory AY Elementary properties of convex functions

FINANCIAL OPTIMIZATION

Preference, Choice and Utility

Existence Postulate: The collection of all points forms a nonempty set. There is more than one point in that set.

September 2007, France

Lecture 4: Constructing the Integers, Rationals and Reals

Expected utility without full transitivity

Prof. M. Saha Professor of Mathematics The University of Burdwan West Bengal, India

Generating Functions

Anscombe & Aumann Expected Utility Betting and Insurance

Studying Rudin s Principles of Mathematical Analysis Through Questions. August 4, 2008

Chapter One. The Real Number System

Algebraic Geometry Spring 2009

Incomplete Preferences under Uncertainty: Indecisiveness in Beliefs vs. Tastes

MTH 505: Number Theory Spring 2017

CONSTRUCTION OF THE REAL NUMBERS.

Homework #6 (10/18/2017)

18.175: Lecture 2 Extension theorems, random variables, distributions

Supplement to Framing Contingencies

Now, the above series has all non-negative terms, and hence is an upper bound for any fixed term in the series. That is to say, for fixed n 0 N,

0.2 Vector spaces. J.A.Beachy 1

Random Variables. Andreas Klappenecker. Texas A&M University

Chapter 2 - Introduction to Vector Spaces

Linear Algebra Lecture Notes

1. INTRODUCTION 2. PRELIMINARIES

Completing the State Space with Subjective States 1

Week 6: Consumer Theory Part 1 (Jehle and Reny, Chapter 1)

This section will take the very naive point of view that a set is a collection of objects, the collection being regarded as a single object.

We are now going to go back to the concept of sequences, and look at some properties of sequences in R

1/37. Convexity theory. Victor Kitov

6.254 : Game Theory with Engineering Applications Lecture 7: Supermodular Games

3 The language of proof

CS 486: Applied Logic Lecture 7, February 11, Compactness. 7.1 Compactness why?

T i t l e o f t h e w o r k : L a M a r e a Y o k o h a m a. A r t i s t : M a r i a n o P e n s o t t i ( P l a y w r i g h t, D i r e c t o r )

Introduction to Arithmetic Geometry Fall 2013 Lecture #5 09/19/2013

DR.RUPNATHJI( DR.RUPAK NATH )

Graph Theory. Thomas Bloom. February 6, 2015

6.241 Dynamic Systems and Control

Math 267a - Propositional Proof Complexity. Lecture #1: 14 January 2002

Follow links for Class Use and other Permissions. For more information send to:

Incomplete version for students of easllc2012 only. 94 First-Order Logic. Incomplete version for students of easllc2012 only. 6.5 The Semantic Game 93

B ɛ (P ) B. n N } R. Q P

CHAPTER 5. Birkhoff Orthogonality and a Revisit to the Characterization of Best Approximations. 5.1 Introduction

2. The Concept of Convergence: Ultrafilters and Nets

Seminaar Abstrakte Wiskunde Seminar in Abstract Mathematics Lecture notes in progress (27 March 2010)

Lecture Note Set 4 4 UTILITY THEORY. IE675 Game Theory. Wayne F. Bialas 1 Thursday, March 6, Introduction

6.241 Dynamic Systems and Control

Convex Optimization Notes

Zero sum games Proving the vn theorem. Zero sum games. Roberto Lucchetti. Politecnico di Milano

Chapter 2: Linear Independence and Bases

Transcription:

Expected Utility Tommaso Denti February 7, 2015 In class some of you asked about the relation between the continuity axiom and the topology on the set of lotteries. The purpose of Herstein and Milnor (1953): An Axiomatic Approach to Measurable Utility was precisely to have a version of the Von Neumann-Morgenstern Theorem without imposing topological assumptions on the set of lotteries. Their idea was to use the convex structure of the set of alternatives to state the continuity axiom. Let X be a convex set of alternatives. Let Á be a binary relation on X, that is, a subset of X ˆX, reporting the preferences of the DM (Decision Maker). We say that a function U : X Ñ R represents Á if for all x, y P X x Á y ô Upxq ě Upyq. Moreover, we say that U is linear 1 if for all x, y P X and α P r0, 1s Upαx ` p1 αqyq αupxq ` p1 αqupyq. Herstein and Milnor consider the following set of axioms (I will refer to axioms as A1,...): Axiom 1 (Weak Order). Á is complete and transitive Remark 1 (Transitivity). No one will ever consider a preference relation which is not transitive. However: Let X r0, 8q be dollars. Assume that Á on X is transitive. Furthermore, assume that there is E ą 0 such that, whenever x y ď E, we have that x y. You can check that, no matter how small E is, the DM is indifferent between zero and one billion dollars. Remark 2 (Completeness). Incomplete preferences are much more interesting: if two alternatives are very different from each other, the DM may not be able to rank them. Aumann (1962): Utility Theory without the Completeness Axiom was the first to develop a theory of incomplete preferences. Dubra, Maccheroni and Ok (2004): Expected Utility Theory without the Completeness Axiom characterizes incomplete preferences represented by a set of utilities U Ă R X : 1 It would be more proper to say that U is affine. x Á y ô Upxq ě Upyq for all U P U. 1

Axiom 2 (Continuity). For all x, y, z P X, the sets tα P r0, 1s : αx ` p1 αqy Á zu and tβ P r0, 1s : z Á βx ` p1 βqyu are closed. This version of the continuity axiom uses the topology of the unit interval and the convex structure of X, instead of putting a topology on X. You can check that the continuity axiom we saw in class implies A2. 2 1 1 1 1 2 2 2 2 Axiom 3 (Independence). For all x, y, z P X, if x y, then x ` y x ` x. This version of the independence axiom is much weaker than the version we saw in class. Proving the representation theorem under A3 is indeed much harder: Theorem 1 (Herstein and Milnor (1953)). The following statements are equivalent: (i) Á on X satisfies A1, A2 and A3. (ii) There exists a linear U : X Ñ R which represents Á. 3 This is known as the Mixture Space Theorem. We obtain the expected utility criterion as a corollary. Let C be a finite set of consequences, and consider ΔpCq, the set of lotteries. It is clear that ΔpCq is a convex set. Corollary 1 (Expected Utility). The following statements are equivalent: (i) Á on ΔpCq satisfies A1, A2 and A3. (ii) There exists u : C Ñ R such that for all p, q P ΔpCq p Á q ô ppcqupcq ě qpcqupcq. Proof. To see that (ii) implies (i), define U : ΔpCq Ñ R such that for all p P ΔpCq Uppq ppcqupcq. It is clear that U is linear and represents Á. By the Mixture Space Theorem, Á satisfies A1, A2 and A3, which means that (i) holds. On the other hand, to show that (i) implies (ii), observe that by the Mixture Space Theorem there is U : ΔpCq Ñ R which is linear and represents Á. For every c P C, denote by δ c P ΔpCq ř the lottery putting probability one on c. Notice that any p P ΔpCq can be written as ppcqδ c. This means that since U is linear Uppq ppcqupδ c q. 2 Indeed, any meaningful topology on X has the property that: if α n Ñ α in r0, 1s, then α nx ` p1 α nqy Ñ αx ` p1 αqy in X. 3 Herstein and Milnor consider for the set of alternatives an abstract notion of convex set, which they call mixture set, hence the name of the theorem. 2

Define u : C Ñ R such that upcq Upδ c q for all c P C. Since U represents Á, for all p, q P ΔpCq p Á q ô ppcqupcq Uppq ě Upqq qpcqupcq, which means that (ii) holds, concluding the proof. We are gonna prove a much simpler version of the Mixture Space Theorem under the stronger version of the independence axiom we saw in class: Axiom 4. For all x, y, z P X and α P p0, 1q x Á y ô αx ` p1 αqz Á αy ` p1 αqz. You can verify the following immediate implications of A4: Lemma 1. Assume that Á on X satisfies A4. Then for all x, y, z P X and α P p0, 1q x ą y ô αx ` p1 αqz ą αy ` p1 αqz, x y ô αx ` p1 αqz αy ` p1 αqz. I will first prove one direction of the Mixture space Theorem under the assumption that there are extreme alternatives: Axiom 5. There are x, x P X such that x Á x Á x for all x P X. Axiom A5 makes life easier because it guarantees that X is a preference interval. For x, y P X, the preference interval is the set rx, ys : tz P X : x Á z Á yu. If Á satisfies A5, then X rx, x s. Notice that, if Á satisfies A4, then preference intervals are convex subset of X (why?). Proposition 1. Assume that Á on X satisfies A1, A2, A4 and A5. Then there exists a linear function U : X Ñ R which represents Á. Once we have Proposition 1, it is not hard to drop A5, and prove the Mixture Space Theorem with A4 instead of A3: Proposition 2. The following statements are equivalent: (i) Á on X satisfies A1, A2 and A4. (ii) There exists a linear U : X Ñ R which represents Á. 3

In the next two sections we are gonna see the proofs of these two propositions. The proof of Proposition 1 is what you need to remember (it is just a rephrasing of the proof for expected utility that you have in the lecture notes). Proposition 2, instead, it is only for your curiosity. In fact, as long as we are concern with X ΔpCq, lotteries with a finite set of consequences, it can be shown that A5 is implied by A1, A2 and A4: Exercise 1. Assume that Á on ΔpCq satisfies A1, A2 and A4. Then Á satisfies also A5. Proof of Proposition 1 Without loss of generality, assume that x ą x (if not, set Upxq 0 for all x P X). The idea of the proof is to measure the utility of alternative x relative to the utility of the extreme alternatives x and x using the convexity of X. If x αx ` p1 αqx for some α P r0, 1s, it is natural to assign utility α to x, and this would be a good idea to get linearity (why?). This idea, however, makes sense only if bigger weights on x are preferred by the DM. Thanks to independence axiom, this is the case: Lemma 2. Take α, β P r0, 1s such that α ą β. Then αx ` p1 αqx ą βx ` p1 βqx. Proof. If α 1 and β 0, there is nothing to do. Assume now that α 1 and β P p0, 1q. Since x ą x αx ` p1 αqx x βx ` p1 βqx ą βx ` p1 βqx, where the last inequality holds by A4. Assume now that β 0 and α P p0, 1q. Since x ą x αx ` p1 αqx ą αx ` p1 αqx x βx ` p1 βqx, where the first inequality holds by A4. We are left with the case α, β P p0, 1q. Notice that β{α P p0, 1q, and therefore we can write β β αx ` p1 αqx pαx ` p1 αqxq ` p1 qpαx ` p1 αqxq. α α We have shown above that αx ` p1 αqx ą x. So we can use A4 once again to get that β β β β pαx ` p1 αqxq ` p1 qpαx ` p1 αqxq ą pαx ` p1 αqxq ` p1 qx. α α α α Luckily β β pαx ` p1 αqxq ` p1 qx βx ` p1 βqx, α α which concludes the proof. We cannot hope to write any alternative x as convex combinations of x and x. However, since we have assumed that x Á x Á x (read A5), we can use the continuity axiom to show that x is indifferent to a convex combination of x and x. 4

Lemma 3. For any x P X, there is α x P r0, 1s such that x α x x ` p1 α x qx. Proof. Consider the set A tα P r0, 1s : αx ` p1 αqx Á xu and B tβ P r0, 1s : x Á βx ` p1 βqxu. Since Á is complete, A Y B r0, 1s. Furthermore by A5 x P A and x P B, and therefore both A and B are nonempty. Finally, by A2, A and B are closed. Since the interval r0, 1s is connected, a basic result from real analysis tells us that A X B. Therefore we can pick α x P A X B and be sure that x α x x ` p1 α x qx, as wanted. Thanks to Lemma 1 and 2, we can well define the function U : X Ñ R such that, for all x, 4 Upxq α x and be sure that it represents Á. The only remaining thing to prove is that U is linear. This is another consequence of the independence axiom: Lemma 4. The function U is linear. Proof. Take x, y P X and λ P p0, 1q. We wish to show that α λx`p1 λqy Upλx ` p1 λqyq λupxq ` p1 λqupyq λα x ` p1 λqα y. By Lemma 2, we know there can be at most one α P r0, 1s such that λx`p1 λqy αx`p1 αqx. Hence, to show that α λx`p1 λqy λα x ` p1 λqα y, it is enough to show that λx ` p1 λqy pλα x ` p1 λqα y qx ` p1 pλα x ` p1 λqα y qqx λpα x x ` p1 α x qxq ` p1 λqpα y x ` p1 α y qxq. Since x α x x ` p1 α x qx and y α y x ` p1 α y qx, by A4 and transitivity λx ` p1 λqy λpα x x ` p1 α x qxq ` p1 λqy λpα x x ` p1 α x qxq ` p1 λqpα y x ` p1 α y qxq, as wanted. Proof of Proposition 2 It is easy to see that (ii) implies (i). Therefore let s focus on the other direction: (ii) implies (i). Without loss of generality, assume that there are x, x P X such that x ą x (if not, just set Upxq 0 for all x P X). Take any pair x, y P X such that x Á x ą x Á y. Applying Proposition 1 to Á on ry, xs, we can find a linear function U x,y : ry, xs Ñ R which represents Á 4 To check that U is well defined, we need to verify that there exists a unique α x such that x α xx`p1 α xqx. Existence comes from Lemma 3, while uniqueness from Lemma 2. 5

5 on ry, xs. Furthermore, we can choose U xy such that U x,y pxq 0 and U x,y pxq 0 (why?). Now define U : X Ñ R such that Upzq U x,y pzq for x, y P X such that x, x, z P ry, xs. We need to prove that (i) U is well defined, (ii) U represents Á on X, and (iii) U is linear. Lemma 5. U is well defined. 1 1 1 1 Proof. Fix z P X. Take x, y, x, y P X such that x, x, z P ry, xs, ry, x s. We wish to show that U x,y pzq U x1,y1 pzq: if so, U is well defined. There are three cases to consider: z Á x, z P rx, x s and x Á z. We will only consider the case z Á x: the other two cases can be treated analogously. Assume therefore that x P rz, xs. Since U x,y represents Á on rz, xs, U x,y px q P pu x,y pxq, U x,y pzqs. This means that we can find α P p0, 1s such that U x,y px q αu x,y pzq ` p1 αqu x,y pxq. Since we have chosen U x,y pxq 1 and U x,y pxq 0, we obtain U x,y pzq 1{α. Furthermore, since U x,y is linear on rz, xs: U x,y px q αu x,y pzq ` p1 αqu x,y pxq U x,y pαz ` p1 αqxq. Hence, since U x,y represents Á on rz, xs, we get that x that U x 1,y 1 represents Á on rz, xs, and therefore U x 1,y 1 px q U x1,y1 pαz ` p1 αqxq. αz ` p1 αqx. But it is also true Since U x1,y 1 is linear on rz, xs and we have chosen U x 1,y 1 pxq 1 and U x 1,y 1 pxq 0, we easily get that also U x 1,y 1 pzq 1{α, and therefore U x,y pzq U x 1,y 1 pzq, as wanted. Lemma 6. U represents Á. 1 Proof. Take z, z P X. We can certainly find a preference interval ry, xs big enough so that x, x, z, z 1 P ry, xs. Then, using the fact that U x,y represents Á on ry, xs: 1 1 z Á z ô Upzq U x,y pzq ě U x,y pz 1 q Upz q, as wanted. Lemma 7. U is linear. 5 Note that Á on ry, xs satisfies also A5. 6

Proof. Take z, z 1 P X and α P r0, 1s. We can certainly find a preference interval ry, xs big enough so that x, x, z, z 1 P ry, xs. Since ry, xs is convex, αz ` p1 αqz 1 P ry, xs. Then, using the fact that U x,y is linear: Upαz ` p1 αqz 1 q U x,y pαz ` p1 αqz 1 q αu x,y pzq ` p1 αqu x,y pz 1 q αupzq ` p1 αqupz q, 1 as wanted. 7

MIT OpenCourseWare http://ocw.mit.edu 14.123 Microeconomic Theory III Spring 2015 For information about citing these materials or our Terms of Use, visit: http://ocw.mit.edu/terms.