SUBSPACES OF COMPUTABLE VECTOR SPACES

Similar documents
SUBSPACES OF COMPUTABLE VECTOR SPACES

IDEALS IN COMPUTABLE RINGS

IDEALS IN COMPUTABLE RINGS

INFINITE DIMENSIONAL PROPER SUBSPACES OF COMPUTABLE VECTOR SPACES

2 THE COMPUTABLY ENUMERABLE SUPERSETS OF AN R-MAXIMAL SET The structure of E has been the subject of much investigation over the past fty- ve years, s

ON THE ROLE OF THE COLLECTION PRINCIPLE FOR Σ 0 2-FORMULAS IN SECOND-ORDER REVERSE MATHEMATICS

THE STRENGTH OF SOME COMBINATORIAL PRINCIPLES RELATED TO RAMSEY S THEOREM FOR PAIRS

May 31, 2007 ON THE TRIPLE JUMP OF THE SET OF ATOMS OF A BOOLEAN ALGEBRA.

Coloring Problems and Reverse Mathematics. Jeff Hirst Appalachian State University October 16, 2008

ON THE ROLE OF THE COLLECTION PRINCIPLE FOR Σ 0 2-FORMULAS IN SECOND-ORDER REVERSE MATHEMATICS

2 M. M. Arslanov, S. Lempp, R. A. Shore Theorem 1.1. (Cooper [1971]) There is a properly d-r.e. degree, i.e. a Turing degree containing a d-r.e. but n

An uncountably categorical theory whose only computably presentable model is saturated

2 THE COMPLEXITY OF TORSION-FREENESS On the other hand, the nite presentation of a group G also does not allow us to determine almost any conceivable

ON THE COMPUTABILITY OF PERFECT SUBSETS OF SETS WITH POSITIVE MEASURE

Every set has a least jump enumeration

COMPUTABLY ENUMERABLE PARTIAL ORDERS

CUTS OF LINEAR ORDERS

2 RODNEY G. DOWNEY STEFFEN LEMPP Theorem. For any incomplete r.e. degree w, there is an incomplete r.e. degree a > w such that there is no r.e. degree

THE POLARIZED RAMSEY S THEOREM

New directions in reverse mathematics

Ramsey Theory and Reverse Mathematics

New directions in reverse mathematics

Reverse Mathematics, Artin-Wedderburn Theorem, and Rees Theorem

COUNTABLY COMPLEMENTABLE LINEAR ORDERINGS

DEFINABLE ENCODINGS IN THE COMPUTABLY ENUMERABLE SETS

Isomorphisms of Non-Standard Fields and Ash s Conjecture

Elementary 2-Group Character Codes. Abstract. In this correspondence we describe a class of codes over GF (q),

THE STRENGTH OF THE RAINBOW RAMSEY THEOREM. July 31, 2008

THE STRENGTH OF THE RAINBOW RAMSEY THEOREM. January 14, 2009

Ordered Groups: A Case Study In Reverse Mathematics

STABLE RAMSEY S THEOREM AND MEASURE

June 7, 2007 THE ISOMORPHISM PROBLEM FOR TORSION-FREE ABELIAN GROUPS IS ANALYTIC COMPLETE.

ANY FIP REAL COMPUTES A 1-GENERIC

Π 1 1 CA 0 and Order Types of Countable Ordered Groups

Linear Algebra (part 1) : Vector Spaces (by Evan Dummit, 2017, v. 1.07) 1.1 The Formal Denition of a Vector Space

Graphs, computability, and reverse mathematics

Reverse mathematics, countable and uncountable: a computational approach

IRREDUCIBLES AND PRIMES IN COMPUTABLE INTEGRAL DOMAINS

A Super Introduction to Reverse Mathematics

Reverse mathematics of some topics from algorithmic graph theory

Martin-Lof Random and PA-complete Sets. Frank Stephan. Universitat Heidelberg. November Abstract

PRINCIPLES WEAKER THAN RAMSEY S THEOREM FOR PAIRS

Computably Enumerable Algebras, Their Expansions, and Isomorphisms

ON A QUESTION OF SIERPIŃSKI

Reverse Mathematics of Topology

The Strength of the Grätzer-Schmidt Theorem

arxiv: v1 [math.lo] 24 May 2012

REALIZING LEVELS OF THE HYPERARITHMETIC HIERARCHY AS DEGREE SPECTRA OF RELATIONS ON COMPUTABLE STRUCTURES. 1. Introduction

König s Lemma and Kleene Tree

Medvedev Degrees, Muchnik Degrees, Subsystems of Z 2 and Reverse Mathematics

Reverse mathematics and marriage problems with unique solutions

INDEPENDENCE, RELATIVE RANDOMNESS, AND PA DEGREES

The enumeration degrees: Local and global structural interactions

Axioms for Set Theory

On Ramsey s Theorem for Pairs

THERE IS NO ORDERING ON THE CLASSES IN THE GENERALIZED HIGH/LOW HIERARCHIES.

Reverse Mathematics of the Nielsen-Schreier Theorem

Π 0 1-presentations of algebras

Embedding and Coding Below a 1-Generic Degree

ON THE STRENGTH OF RAMSEY S THEOREM FOR PAIRS

THE K-DEGREES, LOW FOR K DEGREES, AND WEAKLY LOW FOR K SETS

EQUIVARIANT COHOMOLOGY. p : E B such that there exist a countable open covering {U i } i I of B and homeomorphisms

Math 413/513 Chapter 6 (from Friedberg, Insel, & Spence)

RANDOM REALS, THE RAINBOW RAMSEY THEOREM, AND ARITHMETIC CONSERVATION

Splitting Theorems and the Jump Operator

Computable Structures: Presentations Matter

Representing Scott Sets in Algebraic Settings

Muchnik and Medvedev Degrees of Π 0 1

SPECTRA OF ATOMIC THEORIES

A theorem on summable families in normed groups. Dedicated to the professors of mathematics. L. Berg, W. Engel, G. Pazderski, and H.- W. Stolle.

Reverse mathematics and uniformity in proofs without excluded middle

Decision Problems Concerning. Prime Words and Languages of the

Combinatorial Principles Weaker than Ramsey s Theorem for Pairs

On an algebra related to orbit-counting. Peter J. Cameron. Queen Mary and Westeld College. London E1 4NS U.K. Abstract

RAMSEY S THEOREM AND CONE AVOIDANCE

STABILITY AND POSETS

Garrett: `Bernstein's analytic continuation of complex powers' 2 Let f be a polynomial in x 1 ; : : : ; x n with real coecients. For complex s, let f

Computability Theory

Chapter 1. Sets and Mappings

THE IMPORTANCE OF Π 0 1 CLASSES IN EFFECTIVE RANDOMNESS.

SOME RECENT RESEARCH DIRECTIONS IN THE COMPUTABLY ENUMERABLE SETS

2 G. D. DASKALOPOULOS AND R. A. WENTWORTH general, is not true. Thus, unlike the case of divisors, there are situations where k?1 0 and W k?1 = ;. r;d

So in the abstract setting dene the following: f n converges to f with respect to I i every subsequence ff n : n 2 Ag has a subsequence B A such that

GREGORY TREES, THE CONTINUUM, AND MARTIN S AXIOM

Jónsson posets and unary Jónsson algebras

Ordinal Analysis and the Infinite Ramsey Theorem

2 Garrett: `A Good Spectral Theorem' 1. von Neumann algebras, density theorem The commutant of a subring S of a ring R is S 0 = fr 2 R : rs = sr; 8s 2

HINDMAN S THEOREM AND IDEMPOTENT TYPES. 1. Introduction

COMPUTING AND DOMINATING THE RYLL-NARDZEWSKI FUNCTION

Mass Problems. Stephen G. Simpson. Pennsylvania State University NSF DMS , DMS

Finding paths through narrow and wide trees

The Erwin Schrodinger International Boltzmanngasse 9. Institute for Mathematical Physics A-1090 Wien, Austria

arxiv: v1 [math.lo] 14 Jan 2008

Boolean Algebra and Propositional Logic

Vector Space Basics. 1 Abstract Vector Spaces. 1. (commutativity of vector addition) u + v = v + u. 2. (associativity of vector addition)

Every Incomplete Computably Enumerable Truth-Table Degree Is Branching

Review of Linear Algebra

Contents. 2.1 Vectors in R n. Linear Algebra (part 2) : Vector Spaces (by Evan Dummit, 2017, v. 2.50) 2 Vector Spaces

Transcription:

SUBSPACES OF COMPUTABLE VECTOR SPACES RODNEY G. DOWNEY, DENIS R. HIRSCHFELDT, ASHER M. KACH, STEFFEN LEMPP, JOSEPH R. MILETI, AND ANTONIO MONTALB AN Abstract. We show that the existence of a nontrivial proper subspace of a vector space of dimension greater than one (over an innite eld) is equivalent to WKL 0 over RCA 0, and that the existence of a nite-dimensional nontrivial proper subspace of such a vector space is equivalent to ACA 0 over RCA 0. 1. Introduction This paper is a continuation of [3], which is a paper by three of the authors of the present paper. In [3], the eective content of the theory of ideals in commutative rings was studied; in particular, the following computability-theoretic results were established: Theorem 1.1. (1) There exists a computable integral domain R that is not a eld such that deg(i) 0 for all nontrivial proper ideals I of R. (2) There exists a computable integral domain R that is not a eld such that deg(i) = 0 0 for all nitely generated nontrivial proper ideals I of R. These results immediately gave the following proof-theoretic corollaries: Corollary 1.2. (1) Over RCA 0, WKL 0 is equivalent to the statement \Every (innite) commutative ring with identity that is not a eld has a nontrivial proper ideal." 1991 Mathematics Subject Classication. 03B30, 03C57, 03D45, 03F35. Key words and phrases. computable vector space, reverse mathematics, subspace. The rst author's research was partially supported by The Marsden Fund of New Zealand. The second author's research was partially supported by NSF grant DMS-0500590. The third author's research was partially supported by a VIGRE grant fellowship. The fourth author's research was partially supported by NSF grant DMS-0140120. The fth author's research was partially supported by NSF grant DMS-0502215. The sixth author's research was partially supported by NSF grant DMS-0600824. 1

2 DOWNEY, HIRSCHFELDT, KACH, LEMPP, MILETI, AND MONTALBAN (2) Over RCA 0, ACA 0 is equivalent to the statement \Every (innite) commutative ring with identity that is not a eld has a nitely generated nontrivial proper ideal." In the present paper, we complement these results with related results from linear algebra. (We refer to [3] for background, motivation, and denitions.) We start with the following Denition 1.3. (1) A computable eld is a computable subset F N equipped with two computable binary operations + and on F, together with two elements 0; 1 2 F such that (F; 0; 1; +; ) is a eld. (2) A computable vector space (over a computable eld F ) is a computable subset V N equipped with two computable operations + : V 2! V and : F V! V, together with an element 0 2 V such that (V; 0; +; ) is a vector space over F. This notion was rst studied by Dekker [2], then more systematically by Metakides and Nerode [5] and many others. As in [3] for nontrivial proper ideals in rings, one motivation in the results below is to understand the complexity of nontrivial proper subspaces of a vector space of dimension greater than one, and the prooftheoretic axioms needed to establish their existence. For example, consider the following elementary characterization of when a vector space has dimension greater than one. Proposition 1.4. A vector space V has dimension greater than one if and only if it has a nontrivial proper subspace. As in the case of ideals in [3], we will be able to show that this equivalence is not eective, and to pin down the exact proof-theoretic strength of the statement in two versions, for the existence of a nontrivial proper subspace and of a nite-dimensional nontrivial proper subspace: Theorem 1.5. (1) There exists a computable vector space V of dimension greater than one (over an innite computable eld) such that deg(w ) 0 for all nontrivial proper subspaces W of V. (2) There exists a computable vector space V of dimension greater than one (over an innite computable eld) such that deg(w ) 0 0 for all nite-dimensional nontrivial proper subspaces W of V. Again, after a brief analysis of the induction needed to establish Theorem 1.5, we obtain the following proof-theoretic corollaries:

SUBSPACES OF COMPUTABLE VECTOR SPACES 3 Corollary 1.6. (1) Over RCA 0, WKL 0 is equivalent to the statement \Every vector space of dimension greater than one (over an innite eld) has a nontrivial proper subspace." (2) Over RCA 0, ACA 0 is equivalent to the statement \Every vector space of dimension greater than one (over an innite eld) has a nite-dimensional nontrivial proper subspace." 2. The proof of Theorem 1.5 For the proof of part (1) of Theorem 1.5, we begin with a few easy lemmas: Lemma 2.1. Suppose that V is a vector space, that fv; wg is a linearly independent set of vectors in V, and that u 6= 0 is a vector in V. Then there exists at most one scalar such that u 2 hv wi. Proof. Suppose that u 2 hv 1 wi and that u 2 hv 2 wi. Fix 1 ; 2 such that u = 1 (v 1 w) and u = 2 (v 2 w). Notice that 1 ; 2 6= 0 because u 6= 0. We now have and hence 1 v 1 1 w = u = 2 v 2 2 w; ( 1 2 )v + ( 2 2 1 1 )w = 0: Since fv; wg is linearly independent, it follows that 1 2 = 0 and 2 2 1 1 = 0, hence 1 = 2 and 1 1 = 2 2. Since 1 = 2 6= 0, it follows from the second equation that 1 = 2. Lemma 2.2. Suppose that V is a vector space with basis B, which is linearly ordered by. Suppose that (1) v 2 V. (2) e 2 B. (3) is a scalar. (4) e max(supp(v)) (where supp(v) = supp B (v), the support of v, is the nite set of basis vectors in B needed to write v as a linear combination in this basis). Then B n feg is a basis for V over he vi, and, for all w 2 V, max(supp Bnfeg (w + he vi)) max(supp B (w)). Proof. Notice that e 2 h(b n feg) [ fe vgi because e =2 supp(v), so (B n feg) [ fe vg spans V. Suppose that e 1 ; e 2 ; : : : ; e n 2 B n feg are distinct and 1 ; 2 ; : : : ; n are scalars such that 1 e 1 + 2 e 2 + + n e n 2 he vi:

4 DOWNEY, HIRSCHFELDT, KACH, LEMPP, MILETI, AND MONTALBAN Fix such that 1 e 1 + 2 e 2 + + n e n = (e and notice that we must have = 0 (by looking at the coecient of e), hence each i = 0 because B is a basis. Therefore, B n feg is a basis for V over he vi. By hypothesis (4), the last line of the lemma now follows easily. Lemma 2.3. Suppose that V is a vector space with basis B, which is linearly ordered by. Suppose that (1) v 1 ; v 2 2 V. (2) e 1 ; e 2 2 B with e 1 6= e 2. (3) is a scalar. (4) e 1 max(supp(v 1 ) [ supp(v 2 )). (5) fv 1 ; e 1 g is linearly independent. (6) v 1 =2 he 2 v 2 i. v) Then fv 1 ; e 1 g is linearly independent over he 2 v 2 i. Proof. Suppose that 1 v 1 + 2 e 1 = 3 (e 2 v 2 ): We need to show that 1 = 2 = 0. Case 1: e 1 e 2. In this case, we must have 3 = 0 (by looking at the coecient of e 2 ). Thus, 1 v 1 + 2 e 1 = 0, and hence 1 = 2 = 0 since fv 1 ; e 1 g is linearly independent. Case 2: e 1 e 2. In this case, we must have 2 = 0 (by looking at the coecient of e 1 ). Thus, 1 v 1 = 3 (e 2 v 2 ). Since v 1 =2 he 2 v 2 i, this implies that 1 = 0. By applying the above three lemmas in the corresponding quotient, we obtain the following results. Lemma 2.4. Suppose that V is a vector space, that X V, that fv; wg is linearly independent over hxi, and that u =2 hxi. Then there exists at most one such that u 2 hx [ fv wgi. Lemma 2.5. Suppose that V is a vector space, that X V, and that B is a basis for V over hxi that is linearly ordered by. Suppose that (1) v 2 V. (2) e 2 B. (3) is a scalar. (4) e max(supp(v)). Then B n feg is a basis for V over hx [ fe vgi and, for all w 2 V, max(supp Bnfeg (w + hx [ fe vgi)) max(supp B (w)).

SUBSPACES OF COMPUTABLE VECTOR SPACES 5 Lemma 2.6. Suppose that V is a vector space, that X V, and that B is a basis for V over hxi that is linearly ordered by. Suppose that (1) v 1 ; v 2 2 V. (2) e 1 ; e 2 2 B with e 1 6= e 2. (3) is a scalar. (4) e 1 max(supp(v 1 ) [ supp(v 2 )). (5) fv 1 ; e 1 g is linearly independent over hxi. (6) v 1 =2 hx [ fe 2 v 2 gi. Then fv 1 ; e 1 g is linearly independent over hx [ fe 2 v 2 gi. Proof of Theorem 1.5. Fix two disjoint c.e. sets A and B such that deg(s) 0 for any set S satisfying A S and B \ S = ;. Let V 1 be the vector space over the innite computable eld F on the basis e 0 ; e 1 ; e 2 ; : : : (ordered by as listed) and list V 1 as v 0 ; v 1 ; v 2 ; : : : (viewed as being coded eectively by natural numbers). We may assume that v 0 is the zero vector of V 1. Fix a computable injective function g : N 3! N such that e g(i;j;n) max(supp(v i ) [ supp(v j )) for all i; j; n 2 N. We build a computable subspace U of V 1 with the plan of taking the quotient V = V 1 =U. We have the following requirements for all v i ; v j =2 U: R i;j;n : n =2 A [ B ) each of fv i ; e g(i;j;n) g and fv j ; e g(i;j;n) g are linearly independent over U; n 2 A ) e g(i;j;n) v i 2 U for some nonzero 2 F, and n 2 B ) e g(i;j;n) v j 2 U for some nonzero 2 F. We now eectively build a sequence U 2 ; U 3 ; U 4 ; : : : of nite subsets of V 1 such that U 2 U 3 U 4 : : :, and we set U = S n2 U n. We also dene a function h: N 4! f0; 1g for which h(i; j; n; s) = 1 if and only if we have acted for requirement R i;j;n at some stage s (as dened below). We ensure that for all k 2, we have v k 2 U if and only if v k 2 U k, which will make our set U computable. We begin by letting U 2 = fv 0 g and letting h(i; j; n; s) = 0 for all i; j; n; s with s 2. Suppose that s 2 and we have dened U s and h(i; j; n; s) for all i; j; n. Suppose also that we have for any i, j, n, and s such that v i ; v j =2 hu s i: (1) If h(i; j; n; s) = 0, then each of fv i ; e g(i;j;n) g and fv j ; e g(i;j;n) g is linearly independent over hu s i. (2) If h(i; j; n; s) = 1 and n 2 A s, then e g(i;j;n) v i 2 U s for some nonzero 2 F. (3) If h(i; j; n; s) = 1 and n 2 B s, then e g(i;j;n) v j 2 U s for some nonzero 2 F.

6 DOWNEY, HIRSCHFELDT, KACH, LEMPP, MILETI, AND MONTALBAN Check whether there exists a triple hi; j; ni < s (under some eective coding) such that (1) v i ; v j =2 hu s i. (2) n 2 A s [ B s. (3) h(i; j; n; s) = 0. Suppose rst that no such triple hi; j; ni exists. If v s+1 2 hu s i, then let U s+1 = U s [ fv s+1 g, otherwise let U s+1 = U s. Also, let h(i; j; n; s + 1) = h(i; j; n; s) for all i; j; n. Suppose then that such a triple hi; j; ni exists, and x the least such triple. If n 2 A s, then search for the least (under some eective coding) nonzero 2 F such that v k =2 hu s [ fe g(i;j;n) v i gi for all k s such that v k =2 U s. (Such must exist by Lemma 2.4 and the fact that F is innite.) Let U 0 s = U s [fe g(i;j;n) v i g and let h(i; j; n; s+1) = 1. If n 2 B s, then proceed likewise with v j replacing v i. Now, if v s+1 2 husi, 0 then let U s+1 = U 0 s [ fv s+1 g; otherwise let U s+1 = Us. 0 Also, let h(i; j; n; s + 1) = h(i; j; n; s) for all other i; j; n. Using Lemma 2.6, it follows that our inductive hypothesis is maintained, so we may continue. We can now view the quotient space V = V 1 =U as the set of < N - least representatives (which is a computable subset of V 1 ). Notice that V is not one-dimensional because fv 1 ; e g(1;2;n) g is linearly independent over U for any n =2 A [ B (since v 1 ; v 2 =2 U). Suppose that W is a nontrivial proper subspace of V, and x W 0 such that W = W 0 =U. Then W 0 is a W -computable subspace of V 1, and U W 0 V 1. Fix v i ; v j 2 V 1 n U such that v i 2 W 0 and v j =2 W 0. Let S = fn : e g(i;j;n) 2 W 0 g. We then have that S T W 0 T W, that A S, and that B \ S = ;. Thus deg(s) 0, establishing part (1) of Theorem 1.5. Part (2) of Theorem 1.5 now follows easily from part (1) and Arslanov's Completeness Criterion [1]: If W is a nite-dimensional nontrivial proper subspace of the above vector space V then W 0 is a c.e. set that computes a degree 0; thus deg(w ) must equal 0 0. 3. The proof of Corollary 1.6 As usual for these arguments, we only have to check that (i) WKL 0 (or ACA 0, respectively) suces to prove the existence of a (nite-dimensional) nontrivial proper subspace (establishing the left-to-right direction of Corollary 1.6); and (ii) the above computability-theoretic arguments can be carried out in RCA 0 (establishing the right-to-left direction of Corollary 1.6). Part (i) just requires a bit of coding. Using WKL 0, one can code membership in a nontrivial proper subspace W of a vector space V on a binary tree T where one arbitrarily xes two linearly independent

SUBSPACES OF COMPUTABLE VECTOR SPACES 7 vectors w; w 0 2 V such that w 2 W and w 0 =2 W is specied. A node 2 T W is now terminal if the subspace axioms for W are violated along using coecients with Godel number < jj, which can be checked eectively relative to the open diagram of the vector space. Using ACA 0, one can form the one-dimensional subspace generated by any nonzero vector in V. Part (ii) boils down to checking that 0 1-induction suces for the computability-theoretic arguments from Section 2. First of all, note that the denition of U and of the vector space operations on U can be carried out using 0 1-induction. WKL 0 is equivalent to showing 0 1- Separation, so x any sets A and B that are 0 1-denable in our model of arithmetic. Then their enumerations fa s g s2! and fb s g s2! exist in the model, and from them we can dene the subspace U, the quotient space V = V 1 =U, and the function mapping each vector v 2 V 1 to its < N -least representative modulo U, using only 0 1-induction. (The latter function only requires that in RCA 0, any innite 0 1-denable set can be enumerated in order.) The hypothesis now provides the nontrivial proper subspace W, and from it we can dene the separating set S by 0 1-induction. Proving the right-to-left direction of Corollary 1.6 (2) could be done using the concept of maximal pairs of c.e. sets as in our companion paper [3]. But for vector spaces, there is actually a much simpler proof: In the above construction, simply set A to be any 0 1-set and B = ;. Now V must be a vector space of dimension greater than one. Since any nitely generated nontrivial proper subspace can compute a onedimensional subspace, we may assume we are given a one-dimensional subspace W, spanned by v i, say. But then n 2 A iff fv i ; e g(i;1;n) g is linearly dependent in V iff e g(i;1;n) 2 W; and so W can compute A as desired. References [1] Arslanov, Marat M., Some generalizations of a xed-point theorem, Izv. Vyssh. Uchebn. Zaved. Mat. 25 (1981), no. 5, 9{16, translated in: Soviet Math. (Iz. VUZ) 25 (1981), no. 5, 1-10. [2] Dekker, Jacob C. E. Countable vector spaces with recursive operations. I, J. Symbolic Logic 34 (1969), 363{387. [3] Downey, Rodney G.; Lempp, Steen; and Mileti, Joseph R., Ideals in computable rings, to appear. [4] Jockusch, Carl G., Jr. and Soare, Robert I., 0 1 classes and degrees of theories, Trans. Amer. Math. Soc. 173 (1972), 33{56.

8 DOWNEY, HIRSCHFELDT, KACH, LEMPP, MILETI, AND MONTALBAN [5] Metakides, George and Nerode, Anil, Recursively enumerable vector spaces, Ann. Math. Logic 11 (1977), 147{171. [6] Odifreddi, Piergiorgio, Classical recursion theory, North-Holland, Amsterdam, 1989. [7] Odifreddi, Piergiorgio, Classical recursion theory, Vol. II, North-Holland, Amsterdam, 1999. [8] Simpson, Stephen G., Subsystems of Second Order Arithmetic, Springer- Verlag, Berlin, 1999. [9] Soare, Robert I., Recursively enumerable sets and degrees, Springer-Verlag, Berlin, New York, 1987. Department of Mathematics, Victoria University, P. O. Box 600, Wellington, NEW ZEALAND E-mail address: Rod.Downey@mcs.vuw.ac.nz (Hirschfeldt/Mileti/Montalban) Department of Mathematics, University of Chicago, Chicago, IL 60637-1514, USA E-mail address: drh@math.uchicago.edu E-mail address: mileti@math.uchicago.edu E-mail address: antonio@math.uchicago.edu (Kach/Lempp) Department of Mathematics, University of Wisconsin, Madison, WI 53706-1388, USA E-mail address: kach@math.wisc.edu E-mail address: lempp@math.wisc.edu