Quantum Mechanics: Stranger than we can imagine?

Similar documents
stranger than we can imagine Bell's theorem Limits on hidden variable accounts

How does it work? QM describes the microscopic world in a way analogous to how classical mechanics (CM) describes the macroscopic world.

Cosmology Lecture 2 Mr. Kiledjian

MITOCW watch?v=8osuq1yxcci

Bell s Theorem 1964 Local realism is in conflict with quantum mechanics

226 My God, He Plays Dice! Entanglement. Chapter This chapter on the web informationphilosopher.com/problems/entanglement

MITOCW Investigation 3, Part 1

Quantum Mechanics: Interpretation and Philosophy

T he Science of. What exactly is quantum physics? Until the end of the nineteenth century, scientists thought

Quantum Entanglement. Chapter Introduction. 8.2 Entangled Two-Particle States

3/10/11. Which interpreta/on sounds most reasonable to you? PH300 Modern Physics SP11

MITOCW ocw f99-lec30_300k

We can't solve problems by using the same kind of thinking we used when we created them.!

Topic 10: Bohm s Theory

What It Feels like to Be in a Superposition

Lecture 14, Thurs March 2: Nonlocal Games

Beginning Modern Quantum

MITOCW ocw f99-lec17_300k

Quantum Physics & Reality

Odd Things about Quantum Mechanics: Abandoning Determinism In Newtonian physics, Maxwell theory, Einstein's special or general relativity, if an initi

Note: Please use the actual date you accessed this material in your citation.

The Mysteries of Quantum Mechanics

Instructor (Brad Osgood)

MITOCW ocw f99-lec05_300k

The Philosophy of Quantum Mechanics (Handout Eight) between the microphysical and the macrophysical. The macrophysical world could be understood

The Curious World of the Very Very Small

MITOCW ocw f99-lec23_300k

Phil Notes #7: Time Travel

A Re-Evaluation of Schrodinger s Cat Paradox

Q8 Lecture. State of Quantum Mechanics EPR Paradox Bell s Thm. Physics 201: Lecture 1, Pg 1

value of the sum standard units

The Measurement Problem of Quantum Mechanics Click to edit Master title style. Wells Wulsin SASS 24 September 2008

37-6 Watching the electrons (matter waves)

The Foundations of Quantum Mechanics and The Limitations of Human Being

Evidence and Theory in Physics. Tim Maudlin, NYU Evidence in the Natural Sciences, May 30, 2014

4.1 Einstein-Podolsky-Rosen Paradox

MITOCW watch?v=dztkqqy2jn4

Dick's PhAQs II: Philosopher-Asked Questions

Physicists' Epistemologies of Quantum Mechanics

MITOCW watch?v=vjzv6wjttnc

The nature of Reality: Einstein-Podolsky-Rosen Argument in QM

Introduction to the strange world of Quantum Physics

ALBERT EINSTEIN AND THE FABRIC OF TIME by Gevin Giorbran

Singlet State Correlations

MITOCW 6. Standing Waves Part I

So What Does An Atom Look Like?

The Collapse of the Wave Function

Talk Science Professional Development

MITOCW watch?v=ko0vmalkgj8

Double slit questions

Bell s inequalities and their uses

What Does Quantum Mechanics Suggest About Our Perceptions of Reality?

228 My God - He Plays Dice! Schrödinger s Cat. Chapter 28. This chapter on the web informationphilosopher.com/problems/scrodingerscat

Uncertainty. Michael Peters December 27, 2013

Sniffing out new laws... Question

Chapter 2. Mathematical Reasoning. 2.1 Mathematical Models

It Was Probably Heisenberg

COPENHAGEN INTERPRETATION:

Einstein-Podolsky-Rosen paradox and Bell s inequalities

The Weird World of the Very Very Small

Superposition - World of Color and Hardness

MITOCW 5. Quantum Mechanics: Free Particle and Particle in 1D Box

Japan Disaster: 9.0 Earthquake

MITOCW ocw f99-lec09_300k

11/26/2018 Photons, Quasars and the Possibility of Free Will - Scientific American Blog Network. Observations

A trip to Quantum Physics

The Measurement Problem

The Relativistic Quantum World

Introductory Quantum Chemistry Prof. K. L. Sebastian Department of Inorganic and Physical Chemistry Indian Institute of Science, Bangalore

Introduction. Introductory Remarks

CHAPTER 1. Introduction

MITOCW watch?v=t6tqhnxy5wg

Hardy s Paradox. Chapter Introduction

Contingency Tables. Safety equipment in use Fatal Non-fatal Total. None 1, , ,128 Seat belt , ,878

We're in interested in Pr{three sixes when throwing a single dice 8 times}. => Y has a binomial distribution, or in official notation, Y ~ BIN(n,p).

ELEC4705 Fall Tom Smy. LECTURE 3 Fundamentals of Quantum Theory

ACTIVITY 5. Figure 5-1: Simulated electron interference pattern with your prediction for the next electron s position.

about Quantum Physics Bill Poirier MVJS Mini-Conference Lawrence Hall of Science July 9, 2015

6.041SC Probabilistic Systems Analysis and Applied Probability, Fall 2013 Transcript Tutorial:A Random Number of Coin Flips

Hypothesis testing I. - In particular, we are talking about statistical hypotheses. [get everyone s finger length!] n =

Gravity and Spacetime: Why do things fall?

Chapter 24: A Brief Introduction to Quantum Theory

Lecture 2 - Length Contraction

MITOCW ocw-18_02-f07-lec02_220k

What is Quantum Mechanics?

MITOCW ocw feb k

Note: Please use the actual date you accessed this material in your citation.

/60 (multiple choice) II /20 III /30 IV /10 V /60 (essay)

Fog Chamber Testing the Label: Photo of Fog. Joshua Gutwill 10/29/1999

MITOCW ocw f99-lec16_300k

MITOCW watch?v=ybcsmyk5xmg

( )( b + c) = ab + ac, but it can also be ( )( a) = ba + ca. Let s use the distributive property on a couple of

MITOCW watch?v=7q32wnm4dew

Master Projects (EPFL) Philosophical perspectives on the exact sciences and their history

MITOCW ocw f08-lec08_300k

Problems with/failures of QM

PROFESSOR: WELCOME BACK TO THE LAST LECTURE OF THE SEMESTER. PLANNING TO DO TODAY WAS FINISH THE BOOK. FINISH SECTION 6.5

Partner s Name: EXPERIMENT MOTION PLOTS & FREE FALL ACCELERATION

Wave-particle duality and the two-slit experiment: Analysis

MITOCW MITRES_18-007_Part1_lec2_300k.mp4

Transcription:

Quantum Mechanics: Stranger than we can imagine? 1900: Kelvin announced that physics was basically solved except for two little clouds on the horizon. One cloud led to relativity, the other to quantum mechanics. 1900: Max Planck, proposed that light behaved as if it arrived in lumps, not as continuous waves. 1905: Einstein proposed taking that lumpiness seriously 1912: Debye shows that sound is lumpy like light. 1913: Bohr proposes that similar lumpiness accounts for the structure of atoms. 1921: A. C. Lunn (U. Chicago) proposes a wave theory and solves it for the hydrogen atom. Rejected by Physical Review. 1923: DeBroglie wave picture of particles. (same as Lunn s) 1925: Schrödinger wave equation (same as Lunn s) Gradually, the old Newtonian physics of the microscopic world (atoms, molecules ) was entirely replaced by a new theory, quantum mechanics. Now ALL our understanding of materials properties (chemistry, conductivity, springiness, ) is based in QM. So this new physics is older than almost every one in this room. Maybe it s time to try to look at its implications. 1

Let s listen to a quantum process: a Geiger counter. Who hears the pattern in the clicks? Let s listen again. We can t predict exactly when the next click will come. Before we go on, let's be clear about something: QM does NOT say that "everything is uncertain." Here's a number from a standard table: Planck s constant (giving the ratio of energy lump size to wave frequency) is h= 6.6260755 ±.000004 x 10-34 J-s. So even if we find that some things are unpredictable, we re NOT saying that everything is too fuzzy to describe. 2

Are those clicks really occurring at purely random times? (or as Einstein asked: Does God play dice with the universe?) Or are there little causes, hidden away, as in many familiar random events? (e.g. See demo of balls bouncing through nails. They re only random if you can t see the exact details of each bounce quickly enough.) How can you test if there are hidden little causes or just purely random events? It sounds impossible, but in 1964John Bell figured out a way to test whether events have anything like causes. Let s start by applying Bell s test to something we can picture, not to little particle/waves. 3

A Science Fiction Story Say that you want to find out why people like pepperoni, mushrooms, and olives on pizza. You ask many people, and they give Yes/No answers when asked about each. (Say 50% yes for each.) But you don't notice any distinguishing properties of the people who say Y. Does that mean you can conclude that the answer is random, some sort of momentary glitch that occurs in a person's response? Of course not- you may just have missed the "hidden variables" needed to understand taste. There MAY be something in each person's mind ahead of time that determines their answer, or maybe not. 4

Try asking couples. You find that each couple gives the same answer to the one question you ask them, so you can be sure that there was already something in their heads that determined the answer. Otherwise how could they all get their stories straight? So there WAS some hidden variable determining the outcome. (There's a slight complication- all these folks seem to get confused after one question. If you ask each member of the couples a second question, the perfect correlation between them is lost. So you're only allowed to ask one of each person.) Now you try asking one person about pepperoni, and the other about mushrooms. You find that 85% of the time, they give the same answer (YY or NN). So you conclude that whatever makes people like mushrooms usually makes them like pepperoni. P N Y Y N Y N N Y N N Y N N N N Y Y N Y N M N Y Y N N N N Y N Y Y N N N Y Y Y N Y N You try the same thing asking about mushrooms and olives. Again 85% of the time, they give the same answer. (YY or NN) O N N Y N Y N N Y Y Y N Y N N Y N N Y Y Y M Y N Y N Y N N Y N Y N Y N N Y Y N Y Y Y 5

Now you ask about pepperoni and olives. What extent of agreement do you expect? The 15% of couples who had different opinions on M-P and the 15% with different opinions on M-O might be the same people. Then there would be 100% agreement on P-O. Or maybe they're all different people. Then there would be 100%-15%-15% = 70% agreement on P-O. Or it could come out anywhere in between 70% and 100%. What do you find? 6

They give the same answer 50% of the time! O Y N N Y N Y N Y N N Y Y Y Y Y N Y Y N M P Y N N N Y N Y N N Y N Y Y N N Y Y N N Try to fill that M row in with Y,N that s 85% the same as BOTH the O and P rows! Not possible. We claim that there really are answers to each question, because when we ask the same question of each person we get the SAME answer. Yet there s no way to fill in all three rows with answers that meet the % agreements that we find between rows. 7

What gives? Maybe there was a statistical fluke. You try the same thing again with 100,000 couples- and get the same result. Maybe the couples were secretly signaling each other, getting their stories coordinated (on some questions) AFTER the questions were asked. You ask the questions in sealed boxes. Same result. You ask the questions SIMULTANEOUSLY (in Earth frame). Same result. Maybe the couples were getting their stories straight only on the questions which they knew they would be asked. (Animal House?) The lists of answers only exist for those questions, not the ones that won t get asked. So you draw the questions out of hats, in the sealed boxes, simultaneously. And get the same result. Then if only TWO answers exist for any pair, there would have to be a conspiracy between the couples and whoever sets the randomly chosen pair of questions. 8

Conclusion: this story is obviously fiction. The identical results on any ONE question tell you that (whether or not you believe that people in general are spontaneous and random) on these particular issues there had to be some prior content in their heads determining the answers. But there is NO WAY of assigning answers to the 3 questions (M,O,P) which gives these results for the disagreement percentages: M 15% 15% O 50% P 9

Now we tell exactly the same story about particles of light, where "couples" are pairs emitted together in some decay process. "Like pepperoni?" -> polarized vertically "Like olives?" -> "polarized 45 degrees from vertical?" "Like mushrooms?" -> "polarized at 22.5 degrees " You don t have to know what those variables meanjust that each leads to clicks on a detector if the answer is yes. Experimentally the results are as we have described. Even though we always get agreement when we ask the same question of each partner, there CANNOT be lists of what those answers would be before we ask. You can t have two lists each almost the same as the third, but very different from each other! 10

Obviously when we concluded that this story must be science fiction we assumed something that's false. What did we assume about reality? Note that we assumed nothing whatever about QMwe didn't even mention it. It happens that QM precisely predicts the results, but we are now finding how the world differs from our assumptions, not how quantum theory differs from our assumptions. WE assumed Realism. The world may or may not be random, but those parts of it which can be perfectly predicted have some real cause. "If, without in any way disturbing a system, we can predict with certainty (i.e., probability equal to unity) the value of a physical quantity, then there exists an element of physical reality corresponding to this physical quantity." (Einstein, Podolsky, Rosen, 1935) Causes are local. You can t change the outcome here by doing something over there unless there s time for some signal to travel. No conspiracies. Nobody handed out instructions ahead of time to the little random particles and the little random, question choosers, telling them exactly what to do to mess with our heads. Which one are you willing to give up? (We vote.) 11

We can t tell you for sure what must go, but we do conclude that the universe has features that are not describable as results of pieces moving around in space and time. Somehow it knows the linkage between two distant results without knowing either of those results! (Here I m assuming no conspiracies.) So while you re getting used to that: What does the quantum picture say about where the randomness comes in? 12

The physical state of a system is described by a quantum state (in simple cases, a wave). Let s call it ψ, There s an equation (Schrödinger s ) that says how that state changes in time, just like Newton s laws say how a classical state changes in time. i dψ = Hψ dt There are only two things you need to know about that equation: 1. It s completely DETERMINISTIC. Give it the initial state ψ(0) and the rules of the game and it gives you exactly what the later states ψ(t) will be. So where s the randomness? 2. It s LINEAR. That means that if you have two different wave patterns that solve the equation, so does any combination of them. (That s called superposition) That s just like small water waves. (Demo: the waves from different sources travel through each other, unchanged.) 13

What would happen if the SEQ were to work exactly all the time, the way we used to think Newton s laws did? Say you follow Schrödinger s experimental idea: Quantum state ψ L triggers an apparatus to feed a cat (φ). ψ ϕ ψ ϕ L C L L Quantum state ψ D triggers an apparatus to kill a cat. ψ ϕ ψ ϕ D C D D Now prepare quantum state ψ L + ψ D. What happens? 1 1 2 2 ( ψ )( ) ( ) L + ψ D ϕc ψ LϕL + ψ DϕD The final quantum state contains BOTH live cat φ L and dead cat φ C because the SEQ is LINEARthe same as the water wave coming from two sources contains the parts from each source. 14

The result of the solution of the linear wave equation is that the cat is both alive and dead, in a superposition. This does not mean "in a coma" or "almost dead" but BOTH fully alive and purring or thoroughly dead and decomposing. How many times have you seen a live-dead cat? Let s include you (Y) in the equation- you re also made up of quantum parts. ψ ϕ Y ψ ϕ Y L C L L SL ψ ϕ Y or ψ ϕ Y D C D D SD 1 1 2 2 ( ψ )( ) ( ) L + ψ D ϕc Y ψ LϕLYL + ψ DϕDYD The solution of the linear wave equation now describes a superposition of a you who has seen the dead cat and a you who has seen the live cat! 15

Which of youse guys is for real? If the linear wave equation by itself describes the world of our experience, with no live-dead cats- it must describe many such worlds! With many different yous! That s hard to believe. This whole issue- how to go from a deterministic theory with superimposed possibilities to a random single experience is known as the measurement problem. There are a variety of ideas about how to deal with itall lousy. 16

Ideas to deal with the measurement problem: 1. "Hidden variables" were always around to determine the outcome of the experiments, so ψ doesn't have to collapse. We saw these variables can t be hidden anywhere in spacetime! (Einstein, DeBroglie, Bohm ) 2. (folk version) Somehow ψ collapses to one outcome, but don't ask how. 3. (formal Copenhagen) ψ wasn't ever real, so don't worry about how it collapses. It was just a calculating tool. 4. "macro-realism": ψ does too collapse, but that involves deviations from the linear wave equation. (Pearle, ) 5. mentalism: ψ does too collapse, due to "consciousness", which lies outside the realm of physics. (Wigner, ) 6. (Many Worlds). There's nothing but the linear equation, you just have to understand what it implies. ψ doesn't collapse, all those different branches occur but have no reason (until you understand the wave equation) to be aware of each other s existence. (Everett, Wheeler, ) 17

Let s say you re prepared to accept that crazy Many Worlds idea. I claim it s still not crazy enough. Let s do Schrödinger s experiment many times. Prepare initial states made 2/3 of ones that lead to live cats, 1/3 of ones that lead to dead cats. It turns out in reality that you will then usually see about 2/3 of the cats come out alive. But there are exactly equal numbers of worlds with mostly live and with mostly dead cats. Most versions of you see about the same number of live and dead cats. Why aren t all the versions of you equally real? 7. (Many Many Worlds). The linear equation predicts incorrect probabilities, so maybe you need non-linear terms to give the right probabilities. (only mbw) Some background reading: E. Squires, The Mystery of the Quantum World 18