On the Present Status of Quantum Mechanics

Similar documents
The Foundations of Quantum Mechanics and The Limitations of Human Being

Bohmian Mechanics as the Foundation of Quantum Mechanics

Cosmological quantum fluctuations from the

Time in Bohmian Mechanics

Bohmian Trajectories as the Foundation of Quantum Mechanics and Quantum Field Theory

The Measurement Problem of Quantum Mechanics Click to edit Master title style. Wells Wulsin SASS 24 September 2008

On Spontaneous Wave Function Collapse and Quantum Field Theory

What does Quantum Mechanics Tell us about Time?

Master Projects (EPFL) Philosophical perspectives on the exact sciences and their history

The Measurement Problem

ON THE NOTION OF PRIMITIVE ONTOLOGY. Andrea Oldofredi Université de Lausanne MCMP (LMU) 29 Oct. 2014

The Role of the Wave Function in the GRW Matter Density Theory

Bohmian Mechanics. Detlef Dürr, Sheldon Goldstein, Roderich Tumulka, and Nino Zanghì. December 31, 2004

Outline. What does Quantum Mechanics Tell us about Time? Classical Mechanics in a Nutshell. Classical Mechanics in a Nutshell

Cosmology Lecture 2 Mr. Kiledjian

Hiding a collapse mechanism inside the standard model

The nature of Reality: Einstein-Podolsky-Rosen Argument in QM

Quantum Theory: What is it about?

Evidence and Theory in Physics. Tim Maudlin, NYU Evidence in the Natural Sciences, May 30, 2014

Collapse or no collapse? What is the best ontology of quantum mechanics in the primitive ontology framework?

GRW Theory (Ghirardi, Rimini, Weber Model of Quantum Mechanics)

On the role of Decoherence in Bohmian Mechanics

Some remarks on the mentalistic reformulation of the measurement problem. A reply to S. Gao

The GRW flash theory: a relativistic quantum ontology of matter in space-time?

Introduction to Bell s theorem: the theory that solidified quantum mechanics

From Bohmian Mechanics to Bohmian Quantum Gravity. Antonio Vassallo Instytut Filozofii UW Section de Philosophie UNIL

Against the field ontology of quantum mechanics

A Re-Evaluation of Schrodinger s Cat Paradox

Bell s Theorem. Ben Dribus. June 8, Louisiana State University

MAKING BOHMIAN MECHANICS COMPATIBLE WITH RELATIVITY AND QUANTUM FIELD THEORY. Hrvoje Nikolić Rudjer Bošković Institute, Zagreb, Croatia

Wave function collapse

HSSP Philosophy of Quantum Mechanics 08/07/11 Lecture Notes

COPENHAGEN INTERPRETATION:

228 My God - He Plays Dice! Schrödinger s Cat. Chapter 28. This chapter on the web informationphilosopher.com/problems/scrodingerscat

Some Remarks on Wave Function Monism

Is quantum linear superposition exact on all energy scales? A unique case study with flavour oscillating systems

226 My God, He Plays Dice! Entanglement. Chapter This chapter on the web informationphilosopher.com/problems/entanglement

Decoherence and The Collapse of Quantum Mechanics. A Modern View

Einstein-Podolsky-Rosen paradox and Bell s inequalities

Where is quantum theory headed?

Bohmian Trajectories as the Foundation of Quantum Mechanics

Intermediate Philosophy of Physics: Philosophy of Quantum Mechanics Somerville College Dr Hilary Greaves

Primitive Ontology in a Nutshell

The Philosophy of Quantum Mechanics (Handout Eight) between the microphysical and the macrophysical. The macrophysical world could be understood

arxiv:physics/ v2 [physics.soc-ph] 10 Sep 2007

Quantum reality. Syksy Räsänen University of Helsinki, Department of Physics and Helsinki Institute of Physics

arxiv: v1 [quant-ph] 23 Jan 2019

For the seminar: Ausgewählte Probleme der Quantenmechanik Faculty of Physics, University of Vienna, WS 2011/2012 Christian Knobloch a

by Bradley Monton Department of Philosophy, University of Kentucky, Lexington KY USA phone: fax:

QFT. Unit 1: Relativistic Quantum Mechanics

Phil Notes #7: Time Travel

Curriculum vitae of Roderich Tumulka

Determinate Values for Quantum Observables

The Relativistic Quantum World

Primitive Ontology and the Classical World

Realism about the Wave Function

The physical construct of quantum mechanics

How to Make Sense of Quantum Mechanics (and More): Fundamental Physical Theories and Primitive Ontology

On the origin of probability in quantum mechanics

Measurement: still a problem in standard quantum theory

David Bohm s Hidden Variables

Quantum Mechanics: Interpretation and Philosophy

Has CHSH-inequality any relation to EPR-argument?

about Quantum Physics Bill Poirier MVJS Mini-Conference Lawrence Hall of Science July 9, 2015

Modern Physics notes Spring 2007 Paul Fendley Lecture 27

Probability in relativistic quantum mechanics and foliation of spacetime

Primitive ontology and quantum state in the GRW matter density theory

What does it feel like to be in a quantum superposition?

Quantum Mechanics: Stranger than we can imagine?

Quantum Entanglement. Chapter Introduction. 8.2 Entangled Two-Particle States

Coins and Counterfactuals

4. The twin paradox. HPS/Philosophy 2626 Philosophy of Physics Spring Part I: Space and Time

ON THE FAITHFUL INTERPRETATION OF PURE WAVE MECHANICS

A Crucial Mistake in the Free Will Debate

Quantum Mechanics: Philosophy & Interpretations

Walking on quantum foundations

Honors 225 Physics Study Guide/Chapter Summaries for Final Exam; Roots Chapters 15-18

The Preferred Basis Problem and the Quantum Mechanics of Everything

4. A Theory of Events and Their Direct/Projective Observation. von Neumann Measurements

Backward evolving quantum states

129 Lecture Notes Relativistic Quantum Mechanics

Gedankenexperimente werden Wirklichkeit The strange features of quantum mechanics in the light of modern experiments

How does it work? QM describes the microscopic world in a way analogous to how classical mechanics (CM) describes the macroscopic world.

Life and death in the tails of the GRW wave function

Hardy s Paradox. Chapter Introduction

Odd Things about Quantum Mechanics: Abandoning Determinism In Newtonian physics, Maxwell theory, Einstein's special or general relativity, if an initi

Is Bohm s interpretation of quantum mechanics consistent?

General Physical Chemistry II

Does the ψ-epistemic view really solve the measurement problem?

The hybrid-epistemic model of quantum mechanics and the solution to the measurement problem

1 Bell on Bohm. Sheldon Goldstein 1

arxiv:quant-ph/ v1 22 Apr 2004

Problems with/failures of QM

The Quantum to Classical Transition in Inflationary Cosmology

From No-signaling to Spontaneous Localization Theories: Remembering GianCarlo Ghirardi

Meaning of the wave function

Are All Particles Real?

Lectures 3 and 4: Historical Perspectives on Interpretation

Lecture 13B: Supplementary Notes on Advanced Topics. 1 Inner Products and Outer Products for Single Particle States

Consciousness and the Collapse of the Wave Function

Transcription:

Department of Mathematics UNAM, Mexico City, 24 September 2015

What does the cat example mean? It s often called a paradox, but that is too weak that sounds like get used to it. Basically, it s an argument: Cat + atom belong to a quantum system of 25 electrons, protons and neutrons, with a wave function ψ governed by the Schrödinger equation. Since the Schrödinger equation is linear, we have that, after 1 hour, the wave function is a superposition of the wave function of a dead cat and that of a live cat: ψ = ψ dead + ψ alive. However, in reality the cat must be either dead or alive. John S. Bell: The problem is: AND is not OR. Also known as the measurement problem of quantum mechanics.

Measurement problem Consider a quantum measurement of the observable A = n α n n n. n φ 0 t n φ n (φ 0 = ready state of apparatus, φ n = state displaying result α n ) n c n n φ 0 t n c n n φ n But one would believe that a measurement has an actual, random outcome n 0, so that one can ascribe the collapsed state n 0 to the system and the state φ n0 to the apparatus. Conclusion from this argument: Either ψ is not the complete description of the system, or the Schrödinger equation is not correct for N > 20 particles, or there are many worlds.

Foundations of QM: goals resolve the paradoxes of QM obtain an explanation of QM provide a theory about the foundations of QM that can be understood as clearly as classical mechanics a quantum theory without observers (K. Popper) use this theory as a clean mathematical basis to turn folklore knowledge into theorems make QM easier to learn fight mysticism about QM, unwarranted claims, and bad philosophy

Foundations of QM: goals obtain an explanation of QM Example. To be explained: outcome of double-slit experiment A possible explanation: Bohmian trajectories

quantum formalism: axioms about observations theory about foundations: axioms without observers

When do you need the foundations of QM? in principle practical

When do you need the foundations of QM? in principle: When you want to understand QM. practical: When you want to analyze measurements.

When do you need the foundations of QM? in principle: When you want to understand QM. Although a dose of practically-mindedness is helpful, in the end of the day we all set a high value on genuine understanding. practical: When you want to analyze measurements.

When do you need the foundations of QM? Example in principle: When you want to understand QM. practical: When you want to analyze measurements. You want to prove a superselection rule for a particular system (i.e., that a self-adjoint operator A will not be an observable unless it commutes with a certain operator S).

Morals of research in foundations of QM 1 Bohr s notion of complementarity was not helpful. 2 3 4 5 6 7 8

Morals of research in foundations of QM 1 Bohr s notion of complementarity was not helpful. 2 Insist on the highest standards of quality. 3 4 5 6 7 8

Morals of research in foundations of QM 1 Bohr s notion of complementarity was not helpful. 2 Insist on the highest standards of quality. Don t buy any theory that s weird. Don t accept that it s normal for quantum theories not to make sense. Quantum theories without observers can and should be as clearly understandable as classical mechanics.

Morals of research in foundations of QM 1 Bohr s notion of complementarity was not helpful. 2 Insist on the highest standards of quality. 3 The problem is not lack of existence, it s lack of uniqueness. 4 5 6 7 8

Morals of research in foundations of QM 1 Bohr s notion of complementarity was not helpful. 2 Insist on the highest standards of quality. 3 The problem is not lack of existence, it s lack of uniqueness. Bohr believed that no quantum-theories-without-observers exist. That s wrong. Several exist: Theories that work Bohmian mechanics spontaneous collapse many worlds (in Schrödinger s version, rather than Everett s) Research programs that may (one day) lead to theories that work quantum measure theory [R. Sorkin, F. Dowker] decoherent histories/consistent histories [M. Gell-Mann, J. Hartle, R. Omnès, R. Griffiths]

Bohmian mechanics takes the word particle literally: The k-th particle has position Q k (t) R 3 at time t. The complete description of a system is (Q 1,..., Q N, ψ). The equation of motion is the simplest possible: dq k dt = probability current probability density with current = ( /m k ) Im ψ k ψ and density = ψ 2. ψ evolves according to the Schrödinger eq. i ψ t = Hψ David Bohm (1917 1992) Like it or don t, it actually works: Inhabitants of a universe governed by Bohmian mechanics (with ψ 2 -distributed initial configuration) would observe exactly the probabilities predicted by the quantum formalism.

Bohmian mechanics Wave particle dualism in the literal sense: there is a wave, and there is a particle. The path of the particle depends on the wave. Shown: A double-slit and 80 possible paths of Bohm s particle. The wave passes through both slits, the particle through only one.

Spontaneous collapse e.g., the GRW flash theory (GRWf): Instead of Bohm s world lines, there are world points in space-time, called flashes. A macroscopic object consists of a galaxy of flashes.

Spontaneous collapse: GRW theory Key idea: The Schrödinger equation is only an approximation, valid for systems with few particles (N < 4 ) but not for macroscopic systems (N > 23 ). The true evolution law for the wave function is non-linear and stochastic (i.e., inherently random) and avoids superpositions (such as Schrödinger s cat) of macroscopically different contributions. Put differently, regard the collapse of ψ as a physical process governed by mathematical laws. GianCarlo Ghirardi (born 1935) Explicit equations by Ghirardi, Rimini, and Weber (1986) The predictions of the GRW theory deviate very very slightly from the quantum formalism. At present, no experimental test is possible.

GRW theories are empirically adequate Their predictions deviate very very slightly from the quantum formalism. 1 [s ] 4 0 4 8 12 16 20 24 28 32 36 12 ERR Adler GRW PUR 8 4 0 [m] [s ] 1 4 0 4 8 12 16 20 24 28 32 36 12 ERR Adler GRW PUR 8 4 0 [m] ] 1 [s 4 0 4 8 12 16 20 24 28 32 36 12 ERR PUR Adler GRW 8 4 0 [m] GRWf GRWm CSLm Parameter diagrams (log-log scale). ERR = empirically refuted region, PUR = philosophically unsatisfactory region. [Feldmann, Tumulka 2012]

GRW s stochastic evolution for ψ is designed for non-relativistic quantum mechanics of N particles meant to replace Schrödinger eq as a fundamental law of nature involves two new constants of nature: λ 15 sec 1, called collapse rate per particle. σ 7 m, called collapse width. Def: ψ evolves as if an observer outside the universe made, at random times with rate Nλ, quantum measurements of the position observable of a randomly selected particle with inaccuracy σ. rate Nλ means that prob(an event in the next dt seconds) = Nλ dt. more explicitly: Schrödinger evolution interrupted by jumps of the form ψ T + = e (q k q) 2 4σ 2 ψ T, i.e., multiplication by a Gauss function with random label k, center q and time T. A flash occurs at (T, q) for each collapse.

GRW s spontaneous collapse before the spontaneous collapse : and after:

Many worlds Schrödinger proposed this theory in 1925: Matter is distributed continuously in space with density m(q, t) = N k=1 R 3N δ 3 (q q k ) ψ t (q) 2 dq. ψ t evolves according to the Schrödinger eq. He soon abandoned this theory because he thought it made wrong predictions. But actually, it is a many-worlds theory making right predictions: it implies the quantum formalism. E. Schrödinger (1887 1961) For Schrödinger s cat, ψ = 1 2 ψ dead + 1 2 ψ alive, it follows that m = 1 2 m dead + 1 2 m alive. There is a dead cat and a live cat, but they are like ghosts to each other (they do not notice each other), as they do not interact. So to speak, they live in parallel worlds.

Many worlds Not knowing about Schrödinger s proposal, Everett advocated a many-worlds view in 1957, but with an unclear (or inadequate) ontology: His idea was that for wave functions such as Schrödinger s cat s, both cats are in the wave function, so both cats exist. Everett contributed substantially to the analysis of probabilities in a many-world framework. Hugh Everett (1930 1982) Both Schrödinger s and Everett s many-worlds theory have serious difficulty explaining why we see ψ 2 frequencies, and may therefore ultimately not be viable. [Kent 20, Allori et al. 2011]

The measurement problem is solved Conclusion from the quantum measurement problem: 1 Either ψ is not the complete description of the system, 2 or the Schrödinger equation is not correct for N > 20 particles, 3 or there are many worlds. 1 This is the case in Bohmian mechanics, as the complete description is (ψ, Q). 2 This is the case in collapse theories such as GRW. 3 Many worlds.

Morals of research in foundations of QM 1 Bohr s notion of complementarity was not helpful. 2 Insist on the highest standards of quality. 3 The problem is not lack of existence, it s lack of uniqueness. 4 The ultimate arbiter between quantum theories without observers will be quantum gravity. 5 6 7 8

Morals of research in foundations of QM 1 Bohr s notion of complementarity was not helpful. 2 Insist on the highest standards of quality. 3 The problem is not lack of existence, it s lack of uniqueness. 4 The ultimate arbiter between quantum theories without observers will be quantum gravity. 5 Get used to limitations to knowledge and control. 6 7 8

Morals of research in foundations of QM 5 Get used to limitations to knowledge and control. Limitation to knowledge means that there is a fact in the world but we can t find it out empirically, or a well-defined variable that we can t measure. Give up the idea that a scientific theory should involve only observable quantities. That s exaggerated positivism. John Bell (1987): To admit things not visible to the gross creatures that we are is, in my opinion, to show a decent humility, and not just a lamentable addiction to metaphysics. Example: The wave function is not an observable quantity. If you prepare a particle with wave function ψ, no experiment I can do will reveal to me what ψ is. Nature can keep a secret, and QM proves it.

Morals of research in foundations of QM 5 Get used to limitations to knowledge and control. Limitations to knowledge in quantum-theories-without-observers: Some people don t like Bohmian mechanics because you can t observe the entire trajectory without disturbing it. Not a good reason. Some people don t like many-worlds theories because you can t observe the other worlds. Not a good reason. Inhabitants of a hypothetical universe governed by the GRW collapse theory can t detect reliably (only with limited probability) how many collapses occurred in a given system in a given time interval. [Cowan and R.T. 2013]

Morals of research in foundations of QM 5 Get used to limitations to knowledge and control. Limitation to control means that there is a physical variable that we can t push to a desired value. In Bohmian mechanics, the configuration of a system is random with probability density ψ 2, and we can t choose it, i.e., we can t manipulate it to be a specific configuration without changing ψ.

Morals of research in foundations of QM 1 Bohr s notion of complementarity was not helpful. 2 Insist on the highest standards of quality. 3 The problem is not lack of existence, it s lack of uniqueness. 4 The ultimate arbiter between quantum theories without observers will be quantum gravity. 5 Get used to limitations to knowledge and control. 6 Ontology is an important concept. 7 8

Morals of research in foundations of QM 6 Ontology is an important concept. Ontology of a theory = what exists physically, according to that theory. Jeremy Bernstein (2011): Many of the papers I tried to read were written by philosophers and had words like ontology sprinkled over them like paprika. It was long thought that the key to clarity in QM was to avoid talking about ontology and stick to operational statements. That thought has not paid off.

Morals of research in foundations of QM 6 Ontology is an important concept. Be clear about what is real. ontology of Bohmian mechanics: particles and ψ ontology of GRWf: flashes and ψ ontology of Schrödinger s many-worlds: continuous distribution of matter with density m(q, t) and ψ

Morals of research in foundations of QM 1 Bohr s notion of complementarity was not helpful. 2 Insist on the highest standards of quality. 3 The problem is not lack of existence, it s lack of uniqueness. 4 The ultimate arbiter between quantum theories without observers will be quantum gravity. 5 Get used to limitations to knowledge and control. 6 Ontology is an important concept. 7 Don t take the word measurement literally. Literally, to measure means to reveal a quantity that was defined already before the experiment. Quantum experiments are usually not like that. To pretend they were (i.e., to adopt a naive realism about operators) leads to unnecessary weirdness and paradoxes. 8

Morals of research in foundations of QM 1 Bohr s notion of complementarity was not helpful. 2 Insist on the highest standards of quality. 3 The problem is not lack of existence, it s lack of uniqueness. 4 The ultimate arbiter between quantum theories without observers will be quantum gravity. 5 Get used to limitations to knowledge and control. 6 Ontology is an important concept. 7 Don t take the word measurement literally. 8 Not all observables are created equal: position is more important. All 3 quantum theories without observers (Bohmian mechanics, collapse à la GRW, many-worlds à la Schrödinger) give special status to position operators.

Quantum non-locality Bell s theorem (1964) Although it is not possible to send messages faster than light, sometimes events A, B occurring at spacelike separation (i.e., so that no light signal can travel from one to the other) must influence each other. We do not know whether A influences B or vice versa. Bell s theorem is often confused with Bell s lemma: If there were variables pre-determining the outcome of every experiment then they could be influenced faster than light. John S. Bell (1928-1990) Bell s lemma + EPR argument Bell s theorem All 3 quantum theories without observers (Bohmian mechanics, collapse à la GRW, many-worlds à la Schrödinger) are nonlocal.

Extensions to quantum field theory All 3 quantum theories without observers have been extended to non-relativistic quantum field theory: For Bohmian mechanics, there are two approaches: Field ontology (φ(q), Ψ[φ]), works only for bosonic fields [Bohm 1952; Struyve 20] t Particle ontology with particle creation and annihilation [Bell 1986; Dürr, R.T., et al. 2004] GRW theory [Pearle, Ghirardi et al. 1990; R.T. 2005] Schrödinger s many-worlds theory [Allori, R.T., et al. 2011] x

Extensions to relativity Challenge: Devise a theory that is nonlocal and relativistic Bohmian mechanics: If a preferred slicing of space-time into spacelike hypersurfaces ( time foliation ) is granted, then there is a simple, convincing analog of Bohmian mechanics. [Dürr et al. 1999] Also a GRW-style theory can be easily defined using a time foliation. But GRW can be made more relativistic without a time foliation This has been done for N non-interacting particles, including entanglement/nonlocality [R.T. 2006] Pearle s [1990] model includes interaction without a time foliation but is mathematically badly defined (divergent). Bedingham s [2011] model includes interaction and is well defined Schrödinger s many-worlds theory is easily made relativistic: m µν (x λ ) = ψ T µν (x λ ) ψ with T µν = energy-momentum operator.

Relativistic quantum field theory The main obstacle to devising an analog of Bohmian mechanics or GRWf theory for (say) full QED is that it is not clear which position operators to use. Equivalently, which probability density ρ in position representation. For a photon, the wave function ψ is mathematically equivalent to a classical Maxwell field (E, B). Landau and Peierls (1930) proposed ρ = Ẽ 2 + B 2 with ψ = F 1 ω(k) 1/2 F, but this rule is nonlocal in E and B ( superluminal signaling) and not Lorentz covariant. For an electron, ψ = (ψ 1,..., ψ 4 ) is a Dirac wave function and ρ = s ψ s 2. But electron-positron pair creation at location x would seem to lead to superluminal signaling over the distance given by the width of the positive-energy part of a Dirac δ function. Widespread view: There are no position operators. But we can detect photons. So what replaces the position operators? That is an open question for all interpretations of quantum theory.

Thank you for your attention