Chapter 1 - Preference and choice

Similar documents
Individual decision-making under certainty

Microeconomic Analysis

Last Revised: :19: (Fri, 12 Jan 2007)(Revision:

Solution Homework 1 - EconS 501

Preferences and Utility

Structural Properties of Utility Functions Walrasian Demand

Technical Results on Regular Preferences and Demand

MICROECONOMIC THEORY I PROBLEM SET 1

CONSUMER DEMAND. Consumer Demand

Definitions: A binary relation R on a set X is (a) reflexive if x X : xrx; (f) asymmetric if x, x X : [x Rx xr c x ]

Microeconomics, Block I Part 1

Advanced Microeconomics

Microeconomics II Lecture 4. Marshallian and Hicksian demands for goods with an endowment (Labour supply)

Lecture 3 - Axioms of Consumer Preference and the Theory of Choice

GARP and Afriat s Theorem Production

Solution Homework 1 - EconS 501

CHAPTER 4: HIGHER ORDER DERIVATIVES. Likewise, we may define the higher order derivatives. f(x, y, z) = xy 2 + e zx. y = 2xy.

Week 6: Consumer Theory Part 1 (Jehle and Reny, Chapter 1)

Economic Core, Fair Allocations, and Social Choice Theory

Microeconomics. Joana Pais. Fall Joana Pais

Problem Set 1 Welfare Economics

Notes on Consumer Theory

Positive Theory of Equilibrium: Existence, Uniqueness, and Stability

Preference and Utility

HW4 Solutions. 1. Problem 2.4 (Prove Proposition 2.5) 2. Prove Proposition 2.8. Kenjiro Asami. Microeconomics I

Midterm #1 EconS 527 Wednesday, February 21st, 2018

Revealed Preferences and Utility Functions

Pareto Efficiency (also called Pareto Optimality)

Microeconomic Theory I Midterm

Exercise 1.2. Suppose R, Q are two binary relations on X. Prove that, given our notation, the following are equivalent:

September Math Course: First Order Derivative

Mathematical Foundations -1- Convexity and quasi-convexity. Convex set Convex function Concave function Quasi-concave function Supporting hyperplane

Economics 101. Lecture 2 - The Walrasian Model and Consumer Choice

Notes I Classical Demand Theory: Review of Important Concepts

A metric space is a set S with a given distance (or metric) function d(x, y) which satisfies the conditions

Mathematical Foundations -1- Constrained Optimization. Constrained Optimization. An intuitive approach 2. First Order Conditions (FOC) 7

Static Decision Theory Under Certainty

ARE211, Fall 2005 CONTENTS. 5. Characteristics of Functions Surjective, Injective and Bijective functions. 5.2.

Convex Analysis and Economic Theory Winter 2018

2019 Spring MATH2060A Mathematical Analysis II 1

Axiomatic Decision Theory

Mathematical Preliminaries for Microeconomics: Exercises

A Comprehensive Approach to Revealed Preference Theory

Monotone comparative statics Finite Data and GARP

Expected Utility Framework

Problem 2: ii) Completeness of implies that for any x X we have x x and thus x x. Thus x I(x).

Preferences and Utility

Mathematical Methods in Economics (Part I) Lecture Note

Preferences for Randomization and Anticipation

Demand Theory. Lecture IX and X Utility Maximization (Varian Ch. 7) Federico Trionfetti

3/1/2016. Intermediate Microeconomics W3211. Lecture 3: Preferences and Choice. Today s Aims. The Story So Far. A Short Diversion: Proofs

EE290O / IEOR 290 Lecture 05

The general programming problem is the nonlinear programming problem where a given function is maximized subject to a set of inequality constraints.

3 Intertemporal Risk Aversion

Psychophysical Foundations of the Cobb-Douglas Utility Function

PS4-Solution. Mehrdad Esfahani. Fall Arizona State University. Question 1 Question 2 Question 3 Question 4 Question 5

Econ 121b: Intermediate Microeconomics

Lecture 8: Basic convex analysis

MATHEMATICAL ECONOMICS: OPTIMIZATION. Contents

where u is the decision-maker s payoff function over her actions and S is the set of her feasible actions.

Convex Functions and Optimization

Choice, Preferences and Utility

Microeconomics II. MOSEC, LUISS Guido Carli Problem Set n 3

x 1 1 and p 1 1 Two points if you just talk about monotonicity (u (c) > 0).

Beyond CES: Three Alternative Classes of Flexible Homothetic Demand Systems

Lexicographic Refinements in the Context of Possibilistic Decision Theory

Division of the Humanities and Social Sciences. Supergradients. KC Border Fall 2001 v ::15.45

Microeconomic Theory -1- Introduction

Beyond CES: Three Alternative Classes of Flexible Homothetic Demand Systems

Applications I: consumer theory

The Revealed Preference Implications of Reference Dependent Preferences

Competitive Market Mechanisms as Social Choice Procedures

Confronting Theory with Experimental Data and vice versa. Lecture I Choice under risk. The Norwegian School of Economics Nov 7-11, 2011

Market Equilibrium and the Core

DECISIONS AND GAMES. PART I

i) This is simply an application of Berge s Maximum Theorem, but it is actually not too difficult to prove the result directly.

Recitation #2 (August 31st, 2018)

Seminars on Mathematics for Economics and Finance Topic 5: Optimization Kuhn-Tucker conditions for problems with inequality constraints 1

Hicksian Demand and Expenditure Function Duality, Slutsky Equation

Advanced Microeconomics Fall Lecture Note 1 Choice-Based Approach: Price e ects, Wealth e ects and the WARP

Utility Representation of Lower Separable Preferences

Recitation 2-09/01/2017 (Solution)

Choice under Uncertainty

Whitney topology and spaces of preference relations. Abstract

1 General Equilibrium

Dynamic Macroeconomic Theory Notes. David L. Kelly. Department of Economics University of Miami Box Coral Gables, FL

ARE211, Fall2015. Contents. 2. Univariate and Multivariate Differentiation (cont) Taylor s Theorem (cont) 2

Properties of Walrasian Demand

Intro to Economic analysis

Choice, Preference, and Utility

Economics 501B Final Exam Fall 2017 Solutions

Note on social choice allocation in exchange economies with Cobb-Douglas preferences

Intertemporal Risk Aversion, Stationarity, and Discounting

Microeconomics MSc. preference relations. Todd R. Kaplan. October University of Haifa. Kaplan (Haifa) micro October / 43

Microeconomics I Fall 2007 Prof. I. Hafalir

Second Welfare Theorem

3. Neoclassical Demand Theory. 3.1 Preferences

Boundary Behavior of Excess Demand Functions without the Strong Monotonicity Assumption

Professor: Alan G. Isaac These notes are very rough. Suggestions welcome. Samuelson (1938, p.71) introduced revealed preference theory hoping

Revealed Reversals of Preferences

Transcription:

http://selod.ensae.net/m1 Paris School of Economics (selod@ens.fr) September 27, 2007

Notations Consider an individual (agent) facing a choice set X. Definition (Choice set, "Consumption set") X is a set of mutually exclusive choices. Ex.1 X = { APE M1, another M1, other studies, stop studying } Ex.2 Ex.3 Non-divisible goods { X = x = (x 1... x M ) R M +, Divisible goods X = } M x k = 1, x k {0, 1} k=1 { } R M +

Two approaches to model consumer behavior: A preference-based approach (dominant model) Assumes the decision maker has a preference relation over the set of possible choices that satisfies a rationality axiom. A choice-based approach Focuses directly on the choice behavior imposing consistency restrictions (parallels the rationality axiom of the preference-based approach).

The agent has a preference relation over X. We impose rationality axioms on these preferences. What consequences for the agent s choices? Definition (Preference relation) A preference relation (denoted ) is a binary relation on X which compares couples x, y X. x y reads "x is preferred over or equivalent to y". "x provides at least as much well-being as y". Two other relations: The strict-preference relation The indifference relation

Definition (Strict-preference relation) A strict-preference relation (denoted ) is defined as follows: x y x y but y x "x is (strictly) preferred over y". "x provides more well-being than y". Definition (Indifference relation) An indifference relation (denoted ) is defined as follows: x y x y and y x "x and y are indifferent ("the agent is"...)". "x and y provide the same well-being".

The theory (naturally) imposes a rationality axiom: Definition (Rational preference (rationality axiom)) A preference relation is rational if it is: (i) complete: (ii) transitive: x, y X, x y and / or y x x, y, z X, x y and y z x z Discussion No indecision nor changes in time. Precludes cyclical preferences (e.g. Condorcet paradox). "Framing" problem...

Proposition If a preference relation is rational (i.e. complete and transitive ), then: is irreflexive (x x is impossible) transitive (x y and y z x z) is reflexive (x x) transitive (x y and y z x z) symmetric (x y y x) x y z x z

Other properties and graphic representations of preferences Let s consider X = R M + (or X = R 2 + for graphs). Monotonicity Definition (Monotonicity) A preference relation is monotone: x, y X, x y x y A preference relation is strongly monotone: x, y X, x y and x y x y

Proposition Strongly monotone monotone. Definition (Indifference curve, upper and lower contour sets) An indifference curve is an equivalence class for the relation: I( x) = {x X : x x} Upper contour set: P + ( x) = {x X : x x} Lower contour set: P ( x) = {x X : x x} Example of monotone preferences (graph).

Local non-satiation Definition (Local non-satiation) is locally non-satiated x X, any neighborhood of x has a y such that y x x X, ε > 0, y X such that x y ε and y x Example of non-satiated preferences. Example of satiated preferences ("thick" indifference curve). Proposition Strongly monotone locally non-satiated.

Convexity (a very important concept) Definition (Convexity) A preference relation is convex If x z, and y z then λ [0, 1], λx + (1 λ)y z If x y, and y z then λ [0, 1], λx + (1 λ)y z P + (x) is a convex set (if y, z P + (x) then λ [0, 1], λy + (1 λ)z P + (x) ) Demonstration of equivalence: exercise. Example of non-convex and convex preferences (graphs). Definition (Strict convexity) A preference relation is strictly convex x, y, z X, x y, x z and y z λ ]0, 1[, λx + (1 λ)y z

Example of strictly convex preferences. Interpretation of convex preferences: love for diversity decreasing "marginal rate of substitution" (MRS). One needs an increasing quantity of a good in order to compensate for successive losses of another good.

Continuity (another important concept) Definition (Continuity) A preference relation is continuous x X, P + ( x) = {x X : x x} and P ( x) = {x X : x x} are closed (they include their boundaries). is preserved under limits: (i.e. for any sequence of pairs {(x n, y n )} n=1 with x n y n n, lim x n = x, and lim y n = y, then x y) Important results derive from the continuity property. Examples of non-continuous preferences ("jump" in the indifference curve).

Homotheticity Definition (Homotheticity) A preference relation is homothetic indifference curves are linked by a homothecy i.e. if x y then α 0, αx αy Graphic illustration.

Question: Agents have preferences. How do they choose? : choose an element of X that is "maximal" for. Definition (Maximal element) An element x X is maximal for y X such that y x. Existence? Unicity?

Proposition If X is compact and is continuous there exists at least one maximal element. Proposition If X is convex and compact and is strictly convex has a unique maximal element in X.

Utility functions are a fundamental concept. A utility function provides a numerical value to each choice and allows for comparisons. Definition (Utility function) Consider a function u : X R u represents the preference relation if x, y X: x y u(x) u(y)

Remarks: An infinity of utility functions can represent a given (proof: composition with a strictly-increasing function). The properties of utility functions which are preserved for any strictly increasing transformation are called ordinal. Cardinal properties are those not preserved under such transformations. The preference relation associated with a utility function is an ordinal property. The numerical values associated with elements of X and the difference in utility between two elements of X are cardinal properties.

Proposition (Representation theorem) If a rational preference relation (i.e. complete and transitive) is continuous there is a continuous utility function u(x) that represents. Remarks: The lexicographic preferences cannot be represented by a utility function. In the general case, utility functions need not be continuous.

Important properties of utility functions Concavity Definition (Concavity) u : X R is concave iff x, y X, x y, λ ]0, 1[, u(λ x + (1 λ) y) λ u(x) + (1 λ) u(y) Definition (Strict concavity) u : X R is strictly concave iff x, y X, x y, λ ]0, 1[, u(λ x + (1 λ) y) > λ u(x) + (1 λ) u(y)

Graphic examples with X = R (arcs below the graph). Strict concavity concavity. Concavity is a cardinal property. Other mathematical definitions to characterize concave functions (see Exercise class): Proposition A twice-differentiable function u : X R is concave the Hessian matrix is negative semi-definite. A twice-differentiable function u : X R is strictly concave the Hessian matrix is negative definite.

Quasi-concavity Definition (Quasi-concavity) u : X R is quasi-concave x, y X, x y, λ ]0, 1[, u(λ x + (1 λ) y) min{u(x), u(y)} {y X : u(y) u(x)} is convex x. Remark: // with definition of convex preferences (P + (x) convex).

Definition (Strict quasi-concavity) u : X R is strictly quasi-concave x, y X, x y, λ ]0, 1[, u(λ x + (1 λ) y) > min{u(x), u(y)} Graphic examples (indifference curves). Quasi-concavity is an ordinal property ( concavity which is cardinal).

Quasi-concavity is "weaker" than concavity: Proposition We have the following implications: Concave quasi-concave Strictly concave strictly quasi-concave Strictly quasi-concave quasi-concave But we do not need more! Proposition Consider represented by u is convex u is quasi-concave is strictly convex u is strictly quasi-concave

Another key concept: the Marginal Rate of Substitution Definition (Marginal Rate of Substitution (MRS)) Consider two goods, 1 and 2, and a consumption bundle x = (x 1, x 2 ). The "marginal rate of substitution of good 1 for good 2", denoted MRS 12 tells the amount of good 2 that the consumer must be given to compensate for a one-unit marginal reduction in his consumption of good 1 (i.e. in order to keep the same utility u(x) or, equivalently, to remain on the same indifference curve I(x)): MRS 12 (x) = u x 1 (x) = dx 2 (x) u dx x 1 2

Remarks In the general case, for any k and l goods, the MRS writes: MRS kl (x) = u x k (x) = dx l (x) u dx x k l It does not depend on the chosen utility function. It is a local concept which varies along the indifference curve. It is a subjective exchange rate. If, in a given situation, two individuals have different MRS, they will find it advantageous to trade products.

To sum up Proposition The following assertions are equivalent: Preferences are convex The utility function is quasi-concave MRS 12 decreases (in absolute value) with x 1

Coming back to the choice criterion Under some conditions, is represented by u Under some conditions,! maximal element of X for Choosing x X maximal for choosing x X which maximizes u (see Chapter 3: the classical demand theory) rational agents are "maximizers".

The choice-based approach to decision theory has an empirical flavor. The focus is directly on choices, trying to impose a consistent structure: the Weak Axiom of Revealed Preferences (WA). The WA parallels the rationality axiom in the preference-based approach)

Definition (Choice structure) Consider: A choice set X (e.g. X = {a, b, c}) A family F of non-empty subsets of X represents the situations an agent might be facing. (e.g. F = {{a, b}, {a, b, c}} A choice rule, defined on F, says which elements are chosen or can be chosen by the agent. (e.g. C({a, b}) = {a} or C({a, b, c}) = {a, b} (F, C) forms a choice structure. Question: What reasonable restrictions shall we impose for choices to be consistent? Answer: the Weak Axiom of Revealed Preferences.

Intuition of the WA: if a is chosen while b is available, then this choice reveals a preference for a over b. Thus, there must not exist another situation in which b is chosen while a is available but a is not also chosen. Definition (WA) A choice structure (F, C) satisfies the WA iff B F : B {a, b} and a C(B) { B F B {a; b} and b C(B ) a C(B ) } Does the previous example satisfy the WA?

The WA can be restated in terms of preference relations: Definition (The revealed preference relation) The revealed preference relation is defined on X by: a b B F : a, b B and a C(B) It reads "a is revealed at least as good as b" Definition (The revealed dominance relation) The revealed dominance relation is defined on X by a b B F : a, b B, a C(B) and b C(B) It reads "a is revealed preferred over b"

Definition (WA, second definition) A choice structure (F, C) satisfies the WA iff a b [b a] If a is revealed at least as good as b then b cannot be revealed preferred over a. Example.

How do the two approaches relate? From preferences choices Question: Consider an agent with a rational preference relation confronted to F. Can we derive from a choice structure that satisfies the WA? Answer: Yes. It suffices to consider the choice rule C (B, ) = {x B : y B, x y} which comes down to always choose the maximal element for. It always satisfies the WA. Proof.

How do the two approaches relate? From choices preferences Question: Consider a choice structure (F, C) that satisfies the WA. Can we define a rational preference relation that generates this choice structure (i.e. such that the selection of maximal elements for will coincide with the choice structure (F, C))? Answer: In some particular cases only. Example: a choice structure satisfying the WA but that cannot be rationalized.

How do the two approaches relate? A rational preference relation always "generates" a choice structure which satisfies the WA. However, it may not be possible to "rationalize" a choice structure which satisfies the WA. The standard consumer theory focuses on the preference-based approach.