AN EXTENSION OP THE NUCLEOLUS TO NON-ATOMIC SCALAR MEASURE GAMES. C. Bird. Research Report 72-23

Similar documents
Chapter 5. Nucleolus. Core(v) := {x R n x is an imputation such that e(x, S) 0 for all coalitions S}.

The -nucleolus for NTU games and Shapley procedure

Incentives to form the grand coalition versus no incentive to split off from the grand coalition

On 1-convexity and nucleolus of co-insurance games

Game Theory: Spring 2017

Convex Sets with Applications to Economics

Game Theory. Lecture Notes By Y. Narahari. Department of Computer Science and Automation Indian Institute of Science Bangalore, India November 2007

Maths 212: Homework Solutions

Defining the Integral

The Pre-nucleolus for Fuzzy Cooperative Games

THE RANGE OF A VECTOR-VALUED MEASURE

Math 361: Homework 1 Solutions

Existence and uniqueness: Picard s theorem

MORE ON CONTINUOUS FUNCTIONS AND SETS

Module 1. Probability

ORDERED VECTOR SPACES

ASYMPTOTIC VALUE OF MIXED GAMES*

Real Analysis Math 131AH Rudin, Chapter #1. Dominique Abdi

On the Impact of Independence of Irrelevant Alternatives

Cooperative Games. Stéphane Airiau. Institute for Logic, Language & Computations (ILLC) University of Amsterdam

08a. Operators on Hilbert spaces. 1. Boundedness, continuity, operator norms

Bases in Banach spaces

SANDWICH GAMES. July 9, 2014

Reduction of Ultrametric Minimum Cost Spanning Tree Games to Cost Allocation Games on Rooted Trees. Kazutoshi ANDO and Shinji KATO.

CHRISTENSEN ZERO SETS AND MEASURABLE CONVEX FUNCTIONS1 PAL FISCHER AND ZBIGNIEW SLODKOWSKI

Lax Solution Part 4. October 27, 2016

PRESERVING TRANSFORMATIONS

Abstract Measure Theory

Total Expected Discounted Reward MDPs: Existence of Optimal Policies

Aumann-Shapley Values on a Class of Cooperative Fuzzy Games

("-1/' .. f/ L) I LOCAL BOUNDEDNESS OF NONLINEAR, MONOTONE OPERA TORS. R. T. Rockafellar. MICHIGAN MATHEMATICAL vol. 16 (1969) pp.

MATH FINAL EXAM REVIEW HINTS

Lecture 4 The nucleolus

Homework 1 (revised) Solutions

Problem set 1, Real Analysis I, Spring, 2015.

Topological properties

Consistency, anonymity, and the core on the domain of convex games

NOTES ON VECTOR-VALUED INTEGRATION MATH 581, SPRING 2017

Matematicas Aplicadas. c1998 Universidad de Chile A CONVERGENT TRANSFER SCHEME TO THE. Av. Ejercito de Los Andes 950, 5700 San Luis, Argentina.

Analytic Solution for the Nucleolus of a Three-Player Cooperative Game

Convex Optimization Theory. Chapter 5 Exercises and Solutions: Extended Version

On Strongly Equivalent Nonrandomized Transition Probabilities

The SD-prenucleolus for TU games

Integral Jensen inequality

Nonnegative Solutions for a Class of Nonpositone Problems

Solutions Final Exam May. 14, 2014

Set, functions and Euclidean space. Seungjin Han

MATH 102 INTRODUCTION TO MATHEMATICAL ANALYSIS. 1. Some Fundamentals

5 Set Operations, Functions, and Counting

MATH31011/MATH41011/MATH61011: FOURIER ANALYSIS AND LEBESGUE INTEGRATION. Chapter 2: Countability and Cantor Sets

THE CANTOR GAME: WINNING STRATEGIES AND DETERMINACY. by arxiv: v1 [math.ca] 29 Jan 2017 MAGNUS D. LADUE

Coincidence of Cooperative Game Theoretic Solutions in the Appointment Problem. Youngsub Chun Nari Parky Duygu Yengin

Characterizations of Solution Sets of Fréchet Differentiable Problems with Quasiconvex Objective Function

1 Topology Definition of a topology Basis (Base) of a topology The subspace topology & the product topology on X Y 3

Theorems. Theorem 1.11: Greatest-Lower-Bound Property. Theorem 1.20: The Archimedean property of. Theorem 1.21: -th Root of Real Numbers

On Kusuoka Representation of Law Invariant Risk Measures

Math 4317 : Real Analysis I Mid-Term Exam 1 25 September 2012

Characterization Sets for the Nucleolus in Balanced Games

Boundary Behavior of Excess Demand Functions without the Strong Monotonicity Assumption

Unit 2, Section 3: Linear Combinations, Spanning, and Linear Independence Linear Combinations, Spanning, and Linear Independence

MATH41011/MATH61011: FOURIER SERIES AND LEBESGUE INTEGRATION. Extra Reading Material for Level 4 and Level 6

Call a distribution profile (for the surplus) the n-dimensional vector d N where d N i ^ 0, i ¼ 1, 2,..., n and P n

Problem Set 2: Solutions Math 201A: Fall 2016

GENERATING LARGE INDECOMPOSABLE CONTINUA

1 Lecture 4: Set topology on metric spaces, 8/17/2012

Applied Mathematics Letters

Math 117: Continuity of Functions

Course 212: Academic Year Section 1: Metric Spaces

Differential Games II. Marc Quincampoix Université de Bretagne Occidentale ( Brest-France) SADCO, London, September 2011

Characterisation of Accumulation Points. Convergence in Metric Spaces. Characterisation of Closed Sets. Characterisation of Closed Sets

Czechoslovak Mathematical Journal

CHAPTER 7. Connectedness

3 Integration and Expectation

Analytic Solution for the Nucleolus of a Three-Player Cooperative Game 1

SOME STABILITY RESULTS FOR THE SEMI-AFFINE VARIATIONAL INEQUALITY PROBLEM. 1. Introduction

A CHARACTERIZATION OF STRICT LOCAL MINIMIZERS OF ORDER ONE FOR STATIC MINMAX PROBLEMS IN THE PARAMETRIC CONSTRAINT CASE

The Lebesgue Integral

CHAPTER III THE PROOF OF INEQUALITIES

UNIFORM INTEGRABILITY AND THE POINTWTSE ERGODIC THEOREM

NATIONAL UNIVERSITY OF SINGAPORE. Department of Mathematics. MA4247 Complex Analysis II. Lecture Notes Part IV

) sm wl t. _.!!... e -pt sinh y t. Vo + mx" + cx' + kx = 0 (26) has a unique tions x(o) solution for t ;?; 0 satisfying given initial condi

On Semicontinuity of Convex-valued Multifunctions and Cesari s Property (Q)

CORES OF ALEXANDROFF SPACES

Monotonicity and weighted prenucleoli: A characterization without consistency

In N we can do addition, but in order to do subtraction we need to extend N to the integers

A Constructive Proof of the Nash Bargaining Solution

MATH 202B - Problem Set 5

A CONVEXITY CONDITION IN BANACH SPACES AND THE STRONG LAW OF LARGE NUMBERS1

Computing the Nucleolus of Matching, Cover and Clique Games

6 CARDINALITY OF SETS

Absolute value equations

Division of the Humanities and Social Sciences. Sums of sets, etc.

Seminaar Abstrakte Wiskunde Seminar in Abstract Mathematics Lecture notes in progress (27 March 2010)

Documentos de trabajo. A full characterization of representable preferences. J. Dubra & F. Echenique

Let us first solve the midterm problem 4 before we bring up the related issues.

Chapter 1 The Real Numbers

9. Banach algebras and C -algebras

Merging and splitting in cooperative games: some (im-)possibility results

MA651 Topology. Lecture 10. Metric Spaces.

EXISTENCE OF PURE EQUILIBRIA IN GAMES WITH NONATOMIC SPACE OF PLAYERS. Agnieszka Wiszniewska Matyszkiel. 1. Introduction

Transcription:

AN EXTENSION OP THE NUCLEOLUS TO NON-ATOMIC SCALAR MEASURE GAMES C. Bird Research Report 72-23 /nlc

AN EXTENSION OF THE NUCLEOLUS TO NON-ATOMIC SCALAR MEASURE GAMES C. Bird Introduction In [3] Schmiedler defined a solution concept for n-person characteristic function games called the nucleolus. He derived the nucleolus by considering a vector of coalition excesses for a particular imputation and then arranging the excesses in descending order. Then, by ordering these rearranged vectors lexicographically and taking the minimum under this ordering, the nucleolus, a unique imputation, was deduced. Because of its uniqueness and other desirable properties the nucleolus is an important bargaining concept in n-person game theory. function game. It is one plausible way to resolve a characteristic For these reasons it is of interest to try to extend the concept to infinite player games. The main difficulty is generalizing the lexicographical ordering to the case where there are an uncountable number of coalitions. However, in [2], Kohlberg proved an equivalent characterization of the nucleolus for finite player games. This characterization will be used to extend the nucleolus to a class of infinite player games, the non-atomic scalar measure games. The definition of the nucleolus can be easily extended to much larger classes of games. Non-atomic scalar measure games were treated by Aumann and Shapley in [1], although they were concerned primarily with the value. They form an important class of infinite player games

and allow us to take a first step in applying this bargaining concept to infinite player games. Extension of the Nucleolus This paper deals exclusively with non-atomic scalar measure games. By this we mean the characteristic function V is given by V(S) - f(fi(s)), where f(0) =0, ju is a non-atomic measure on X and SeB, the Borel field of X. For simplicity, we shall assume that X = [0,1], /i(x) = 1 and f(l) = 1. The imputations will be all positive non-atomic measures with v(x) = 1. Kohlberg 1 s characterization of the nucleolus for finite player games [2] will be used to extend the nucleolus to scalar measure games. Definition 1. For any non-atomic measure, V (X) = 1, the coalition array that belongs to (V,v) is the collection {b } n such that b = {S V(S) - v(s) = a}. Definition 2. A coalition array has property I if for every real a, for each non-atomic signed measure 77 defined on B, 77 (S) ;> 0 v S e U b ft and 77 (X) =0 implies 77 (S) =0 V S G U b Q. Definition 3. A non-atomic measure v is in the nucleolus of (X,B,V) if the coalition array that belongs to (V,v) has property I.

Theorem 1, Every non-atomic scalar measure game has a nonempty nucleolus. Proof, V(S) = f(/l(s)) where i is a non-atomic measure. We will show that the coalition array that belongs to (V,jLl) has property I. Partition the Borel field into an array ^Cy^Q<y<l where c y = ( s lm(s) = y}. Clearly, since V is a scalar measure game, for all a either b =0 or b =UC oc ex y for some values of y between 0 and 1. Now, suppose that the coalition array that belongs to (V,fi) does not have property I, Then 2 a a r) with?7(x) = 0 77 (S)^> 0 for all S U b R and 77 (S ) > 0 for Borne S e U b In particular this implies that 77 (S) 2, 0 for every SeC., c w 77 (X) = 0 and 77 (S ) > 0. This is a contradiction. To see this, consider the vector measure (MJM + V) If 1 > M(S Q ) > 0 then (/i + rj) (S Q ) > M(S Q ). Note that (1,1) and (0,0) are in the range of (/i,/lt + 77). Since this is a non-atomic vector measure its range is convex and compact. Thus there is an S 1 such that M(S! ) = 1 - M(S Q ) and (/i + 77) (S» ) > jlt(s! ). Therefore r?(s! ) > 0 and since /i(x-s! ) = fi(s ) then 77(X-S f ) ^> 0. As a result 77 (X) > 0 a contradiction. If instead /i(s ) = 0 or /LI(S ) = 1 then S eb since f(0) = 0 and f (1) = 1. Note that c 1 U C Q c b Q for this reason. So if 77(X) = 0, T?(S Q ) > 0 and 77(S) 2 V Seb Q then 77(X-S Q ) ^ 0 since /i(x-s ) = 0 or 1. But this implies that 77 (X) > 0 again a contradiction. Therefore it has been shown that the coalition array that

belongs to (V,/i) has property I and so \l is in the nucleolus of (X,B,V). In [3] Schmiedler proved the uniqueness of the nucleolus for finite games. Unfortunately in the extension to infinite games unicity is not preserved The following example points this out. Let V(S) = f (jlt(s)) where x = 0 f(x) = I 1/2 0 < x < 1 x = 1 and /i is a non-atomic measure. Clearly for any non-atomic measure v such that v(x) = JLt(X) and v is absolutely continuous with respect to [L, then V(S) - f(v(s)) also. Therefore by Theorem 1, both v and \i are in the nucleolus of (X,B,V). In the formulation of the problem we ruled out consideration of imputations which contained atomic measures. By allowing only non-atomic measures this encompasses the second condition in Kohlberg 1 s Property I, i.e. 77({X Q }) > 0 V X Q such that V({x Q }) = CK In this case, every x [0,1]. If instead we use Kohlberg 1 s original conditions for property I, some undesirable elements can appear in the nucleolus. Let x [0,1] be arbitrary then if x o S if x^s

is in the nucleolus of (X,B,V) for any non-atomic scalar measure game. Note that for any a, {s x /S f(jlt(s)) = a) c b Then for 7?(X) = 0, 77({y}) 2 0 V yex and?7(s) 2 V s U b ft. This implies that V S with x /S 7?(S) = 0 and because 7?((x }) ^ 0 then rj{x] = 0 since Tj(X) = 0. That this imputation should be allowed in the nucleolus is quite unreasonable as it is as far from a conciliatory solution as is possible. That this would otherwise be allowed can be attributed to the measure theoretic pathologies of the problem. The inapplicability of this condition to this type of game is due to the fact that it is possible in games with a continuum of players for each individual element to receive zero, but for an aggregate of elements to receive a positive quantity. Thus one should proceed with caution when attempting to extend these results to scalar measure games whose measures may have atoms. We now prove a lemma which will be useful in characterizing the nucleolus. Lemma. If /z,v are non-atomic measures such that /i(x) = v(x) and there is 0 < a < 1 there is an S with ju(s) = a v(s) > a then for every 0 < a < 1 there are s i^2 with H(S ± ) = M(S 2 ) = a, and v(s 1 ) > a > V (S 2 ). Conversely, if there is 0 < a < 1 such that for all S with /i(s) = a = v(s), then v = fx. Proof. Since /i,v are non-atomic then (v,/it) is a nonatomic vector measure hence its range is convex and compact.

If as with v(s) > ju(s) = a, 0 < a < 1 then because v(x) = ]U(X) by convexity for each p 1> P ^ a Sg with M(Sg) = P < v (Sg). Similarly (0,0) is in the range of (v,jlt) so that for any 5 < a 3- Se with ^(S*) = ^ < V ( S A) Also because v(s ) > jit(s ) - a then v(x-s ) < 1-a = M(X-S ). UL CX CX OL Applying the same argument yields If p 1 > p > 0 a SL with p) = P > v(s^). If on the other hand 2 a such that for all S with /i(s) = a v(s) = M(S), and v(x) = /Lt(X) then v = \x. To see this suppose there is an S /i(s ) ^ v(s ) then by the first part of this lemma there is S with jx(s ) = a ^ v(s ) a contradiction. Theorem 2. If f is continuous at 0,1 then the nucleolus of a scalar measure game is {/i} U {v v e int core of V} where int core of V = (v v core of V and if v(s) = V(S) then /i(s) or /i(x-s) = 0}. Proof. By Theorem 1 /i is in the nucleolus. If v e int core then b Q = {S M(S) = 0 or /i(x-s) = 0}. 0the2nvise if v(s) > 0 when /i(s) = 0 then v(x-s) < V(X-S) = V(X) = v(x) so that v is not in the core. Also b = 0 for a > 0, so b is the first non-empty element in the coalition array. To show that the coalition array that belongs to (V,v) has property I it is sufficient to show that for any e < 0 there is a y such that (s /i(s) = y } cz U b. If this property holds then 0 o e a property I follows from the previous lemma. Since V,JLI are non-atomic and v is absolutely

continuous with respect to /i, lim sup v(s) - 0. Therefore, x«+ 0 )Lt(S)=x given e < 0 there is a y, with sup v(s) < e/2 for all M(S)=x x < y,. Because f is continuous at 0 there is a y~ such that f(x) < e/2 for all x < y 2. Therefore there is an y with f (y ) - sup v(s) <. As a result {s )Lt(S) = y,j c U b. Now, to show (V,v) has property I. If 7] (S) ^> 0 a for all S e U b and r\ (X) =0 then 77 (S) ^0 for all S a with /i(s) = y. Therefore as in the proof of Theorem 1 77 (S) = 0 for all S with M(S) = y. By the previous lemma, M(S) = /Lt + 77(S) for all S with jlt(s) = y, therefore \k = \i + 77 and 77(S) =0 for all S including S U b. Since this holds for any e < 0 v is in the nucleolus. Now, to show that if v / \i is not in the int core of V then v is not in the nucleolus. If v is in the core but not in the int core then there is an S Q with 1 > ju(s o ) > 0 and v(s Q ) = f(/i(s Q )). Since )i/ v, by Lemma 1 there is an S 1 with jlt(s! ) = jil(s ) and v(s! ) < jll(s! ). Since v is in the core of V, then v(s Q ) = f(m(s Q )) - f(m(s f )) 1 v(s") < fi(s f ) so that M(S ) > v ts ). Consider the coalition array that belongs to (V,v), b = {s f(ju(s)) = v(s)}. Let 77 = M" v - Then for all Seb^ 77 (S) > 0 and 77 (X) = 0, but 77 (S ) > 0. Thus the coalition array cannot have property I so v is not in the nucleolus. If v j4 fj, is not in the core then sup V(S) - v(s) = A > 0. SeB It will be sufficient to show that

8 sup V(S) - v(s) > sup V(S) - v(s) = sup f(x)-x = D. SGB V(S)2M(S) xe[o,l] If D = O then trivially this inequality holds. If D > 0 then because f is continuous at 0,1, f(0) = 0 and f(l) = 1 then there is some e > 0 such that D = sup f(x)-x, and D > sup f(x)-x. XG [e, 1-e ]=Q xex-q By the lemma & S-^S- such that v(s 1 ) < e = M(S-,) and V ( S 2^ ^ l- -6. Because (v,/i) is a non-atomic vector measure, for each xeq there is an S with f-i(s) = x and v(s) < x-6. Now let {x.}. 1 x.eq be a sequence such that lim f(x.)-x. = D. 1 1 "* 1 x 1 x i -> GD For each x. there is a S. with v(s.) ^ fi(s.)- = x.~6 so that as i oo there will be some S. with f( Xi ) - v(s i ) = V(S i ) - v(s i ) 2 +1- Therefore A > D. To see that v cannot be in the nucleolus consider the coalition array that belongs to (V,v). Since A > D, for each S U b, jlt(s) > v(s) or /i-v > 0 and yet a /i-v(x) =0 so this coalition array cannot have property I. Examining the proof one can deduce even more. It is not necessary that f be continuous at 0 and 1, merely that sup f(x)-x does not occur there. With this in mind we xe [0,1] have the following corollary.

10 REFERENCES [1] Aumann, R. J. and L. S. Shapley, Values of Non-Atomic Games, Part je: The Axiomatic Approach, The RAND Corporation, RM-5468-PR, November 1968 [2] Kohlberg, E., "On the nucleolus of a characteristic function game", SIAM J. Applied Math,.20(1971), 62-66. [3] Schmeidler, D., "The nucleolus of a characteristic function game", SIAM J. Applied Math..17(1969), 1163-1170. /nlc 14 September 1972

Corollary 1, The nucleolus of a scalar measure game is unique if sup f(x)-x > lim sup f(x)-x. x[o,l] x-» 0,1 Proof. JLI is the nucleolus. There are no elements in the core of V otherwise sup f(x)-x = 0 which contradicts the hypothesis. By Theorem 2 if lim sup f(x)-x < sup f(x)-x x-> 0,1 XG [0,1] then by repeating the argument one can easily show that for v / JLI the coalition array that belongs to (V,v) does not have property I. Conclusions The conclusions of this paper are somewhat mixed. The main task has been accomplished; the nucleolus has been extended to infinite player games and its existence has been proven for scalar measure games. Furthermore it is suspected that with a few alterations of the definition, the nucleolus will exist for a much larger class of games including non-atomic vector measure games. Nevertheless, the nucleolus is of lesd value in the infinite case than the finite. It would appear to be most useful when there is no core at least in the case of scalar measure games. But the nucleolus is only slightly smaller than the core when the core exists and this tends to diminish its importance. It could be of use in further reducing the acceptable imputations on a game especially if it were used with another preference ordering bargaining concept.