Spring 2017 Ling 620 The Semantics of Control Infinitives: A First Introduction to De Se Attitudes

Similar documents
Spring 2017 Ling 620 Eliminating Res-Movement : An Introduction to Concept Generators

Semantics and Generative Grammar. An Introduction to Intensional Semantics 1

Spring 2018 Ling 620 Introduction to Semantics of Questions: Questions as Sets of Propositions (Hamblin 1973, Karttunen 1977)

Spring 2017 Ling 620. The Semantics of Modals, Part 3: The Ordering Source 1

Spring 2018 Ling 620 The Basics of Intensional Semantics, Part 1: The Motivation for Intensions and How to Formalize Them 1

Spring 2017 Ling 620. An Introduction to the Semantics of Tense 1

Introduction to Semantics. Pronouns and Variable Assignments. We ve seen that implicatures are crucially related to context.

Spring 2017 Ling 620. The Semantics of Modals, Part 2: The Modal Base 1

Semantics and Generative Grammar. Pronouns and Variable Assignments 1. We ve seen that implicatures are crucially related to context.

Introduction to Semantics. The Formalization of Meaning 1

Semantics and Generative Grammar. Quantificational DPs, Part 3: Covert Movement vs. Type Shifting 1

Proseminar on Semantic Theory Fall 2015 Ling 720 Adnominal Tenses Redux: Thomas (2014) Nominal Tense and Temporal Implicatures

INTRODUCTION TO LOGIC. Propositional Logic. Examples of syntactic claims

Intensionality. 1. Intensional Propositional Logic (IntPL).

Semantics and Generative Grammar. The Semantics of Adjectival Modification 1. (1) Our Current Assumptions Regarding Adjectives and Common Ns

A Review of the Essentials of Extensional Semantics 1

Spring 2018 Ling 620 The Semantics of Modals, Part 1: Basics of the Quantificational Analysis, and the Appearance of Ambiguity 1

Introduction to Semantics. Common Nouns and Adjectives in Predicate Position 1

Semantics and Generative Grammar. A Little Bit on Adverbs and Events

Semantics and Generative Grammar. Quantificational DPs, Part 2: Quantificational DPs in Non-Subject Position and Pronominal Binding 1

127: Lecture notes HT17. Week 8. (1) If Oswald didn t shoot Kennedy, someone else did. (2) If Oswald hadn t shot Kennedy, someone else would have.

Proseminar on Semantic Theory Fall 2010 Ling 720. Remko Scha (1981/1984): Distributive, Collective and Cumulative Quantification

The Semantics of Definite DPs 1. b. Argument Position: (i) [ A politician ] arrived from Washington. (ii) Joe likes [ the politician ].

Semantics and Generative Grammar. Expanding Our Formalism, Part 1 1

Spring 2017 Ling 620 Conditionals as Modal Modifiers Conditional Constructions: Some Basic Terminology, Questions, and Assumptions

Realism and Idealism External Realism

Kripke on Frege on Sense and Reference. David Chalmers

Modal Logics. Most applications of modal logic require a refined version of basic modal logic.

Proseminar on Semantic Theory Fall 2010 Ling 720 The Basics of Plurals: Part 1 1 The Meaning of Plural NPs and the Nature of Predication Over Plurals

Semantics 2 Part 1: Relative Clauses and Variables

Semantics Basics for Syntacticians

Propositional Logic: Semantics and an Example

The Semantics of Counterfactual wish*1)

Relations. Carl Pollard. October 11, Department of Linguistics Ohio State University

Generalized Quantifiers Logical and Linguistic Aspects

To every formula scheme there corresponds a property of R. This relationship helps one to understand the logic being studied.

Kaplan s Paradox and Epistemically Possible Worlds

Introduction to Metalogic

564 Lecture 25 Nov. 23, Continuing note on presuppositional vs. nonpresuppositional dets.

Mathematical Logic Prof. Arindama Singh Department of Mathematics Indian Institute of Technology, Madras. Lecture - 15 Propositional Calculus (PC)

Binding Theory Different types of NPs, constraints on their distribution

65,536 Definitions of Physicalism. David J. Chalmers

Proseminar on Semantic Theory Fall 2013 Ling 720 The Proper Treatment of Quantification in Ordinary English, Part 1: The Fragment of English

Presuppositions (introductory comments)

MODAL LOGIC WITH SUBJUNCTIVE MARKERS: A NEW PERSPECTIVE ON RIGID DESIGNATION

Proseminar on Semantic Theory Fall 2010 Ling 720. The Basics of Plurals: Part 2 Distributivity and Indefinite Plurals

Logic. Quantifiers. (real numbers understood). x [x is rotten in Denmark]. x<x+x 2 +1

Russell s logicism. Jeff Speaks. September 26, 2007

Sequence convergence, the weak T-axioms, and first countability

Discrete Mathematics for CS Fall 2003 Wagner Lecture 3. Strong induction

Notes on Quantum Logic

CHAPTER THREE: RELATIONS AND FUNCTIONS

Probability, Statistics, and Bayes Theorem Session 3

So, what are special sciences? ones that are particularly dear to the author? ( Oh dear. I am touched. Psychology is just, so, well, special!

PEANO AXIOMS FOR THE NATURAL NUMBERS AND PROOFS BY INDUCTION. The Peano axioms

Classical Menu of Pronouns

Uncertainty. Michael Peters December 27, 2013

1 Classical scalar implicature

Philosophy 244: #8 Counterfactuals, Neighborhood Semantics, Probability, Predicative Necessity, etc.

Logic. Introduction to Artificial Intelligence CS/ECE 348 Lecture 11 September 27, 2001

Truth-Functional Logic

Hamblin Semantics & Focus

Indicative conditionals

Intensional semantics: worlds, modals, conditionals

7. Propositional Logic. Wolfram Burgard and Bernhard Nebel

Logica e Linguaggio. Raffaella Bernardi. March 22, University of Trento

Discrete Structures Proofwriting Checklist

The Conditions are Right

Philosophy 244: Modal Logic Preliminaries

Modal and temporal logic

Solving Equations by Adding and Subtracting

09 Modal Logic II. CS 3234: Logic and Formal Systems. October 14, Martin Henz and Aquinas Hobor

Logic for Computer Science - Week 4 Natural Deduction

Examples: P: it is not the case that P. P Q: P or Q P Q: P implies Q (if P then Q) Typical formula:

Propositions. c D. Poole and A. Mackworth 2010 Artificial Intelligence, Lecture 5.1, Page 1

COMBINATORIAL GAMES AND SURREAL NUMBERS

Appendix A. Jargon. A.1 Strange technical terms

CAS LX 500 Topics in Linguistics: Questions Spring 2006 March 2, b: Prosody and Japanese wh-questions

Critical Notice: Bas van Fraassen, Scientific Representation: Paradoxes of Perspective Oxford University Press, 2008, xiv pages

Amount of Substance and Its Unit Mole- Connecting the Invisible Micro World to the Observable Macro World Part 2 (English, mp4)

(1) If Bush had not won the last election, then Nader would have won it.

MATH 22 FUNCTIONS: ORDER OF GROWTH. Lecture O: 10/21/2003. The old order changeth, yielding place to new. Tennyson, Idylls of the King

March 2, 2007 Menéndez-Benito. Quick Introduction to the Semantics of Modals 1

Quantification in the predicate calculus

In Defence of a Naïve Conditional Epistemology

Fitting a Straight Line to Data

Hedging Your Ifs and Vice Versa

Stabilizing Boolean Games by Sharing Information

KB Agents and Propositional Logic

a. Develop a fragment of English that contains quantificational NPs. b. Develop a translation base from that fragment to Politics+λ

Adding Some. Larry Moss. Nordic Logic School August 7-11, Indiana University 1/37

Fox/Menendez-Benito 11/14/06. Wrapping up discussion on Kratzer 2005 (inconclusively!)

Some Remarks on Alternating Temporal Epistemic Logic

Modal Calculus of Illocutionary Logic

Lewis 2 Definitions of T-terms

Some binding facts. Binding in HPSG. The three basic principles. Binding theory of Chomsky

Counterfactual Attitudes and Assignment-Sensitivity

The Philosophy of Physics. Is Space Absolute or Relational?

15-424/ Recitation 1 First-Order Logic, Syntax and Semantics, and Differential Equations Notes by: Brandon Bohrer

Extensions to the Logic of All x are y: Verbs, Relative Clauses, and Only

Transcription:

The Semantics of Control Infinitives: A First Introduction to De Se Attitudes 1. Non-Finite Control Complements and De Se Attitudes (1) Two Sentences that Seem Very Close in Meaning a. Dave expects he will win. b. Dave expects to win. Having developed a semantics for propositional attitude verbs like believes, we have the basic tools to develop an analysis of sentences like (1a). Can / Should we extend those tools to sentences like (1b), with non-finite complements? (2) Towards an Analysis of Sentence (1a) a. The Function Expectations : Just like belief -worlds, we could maybe introduce sets of expectation -worlds Expectations(x, w) = the set of worlds where x s expectations in w are realized = { w : x s expectations in w are realized in w } b. Lexical Semantics for Expects (based on [[believes]]): [[ expects ]] w = [ λp <st> : [ λx : For all w Expectations(x,w): p(w ) = T ] ] p is true in all the worlds where x s expectations are met c. Predicted Truth-Conditions for (1a): (i) Syntax: [ Dave 1 [ 1 [ t 1 [ expects [ he 1 will win ] ] ] (ii) Predicted Truth-Conditions: o For now, we ll fudge the presence of will in the complement clause... [[(1a)]] w = T iff For all w Expectations(Dave,w): Dave wins in w In every world where Dave s expectations in w are met, Dave wins. Easy peasy, right?... 1

Can we apply this to the case of the non-finite, Control sentence in (1b)?... (3) Towards an Analysis of Sentence (1b) a. Syntax of Non-Finite Control There is a great deal of converging syntactic evidence that Control sentences like (1b) have a structure with the following properties: (i) (ii) The non-finite clause contains a (phonologically empty) pronominal subject, PRO. This pronominal subject has to be bound. b. Possible Syntax of (1b): [ Dave 1 [ 1 [ t 1 [ expects [ PRO 1 to win ] ] ] c. Predicted Truth-Conditions: If we suppose that PRO is simply a bound pronoun, just like he in (2c), we ll end up predicting the exact same reading for (3b) [[(1b)]] w = T iff For all w Expectations(Dave,w): Dave wins in w So much winning!! But wait If it s this easy then why is there so much semantic literature on Control??... (4) Problem: Semantic Non-Equivalence of (1a) and (1b) Contrary to first impressions, sentences (1a) and (1b) do not mean exactly the same. In particular, their felicity differs in the following bizarre sorts of cases: a. Scenario: Dave is running for office, but he s pessimistic about his chances of winning. In his depression, he s getting drunk at a bar. On the TV, they play one of his political ads. He s so incredibly drunk, that he doesn t recognize himself or the ad on the TV. But, he s really impressed with the ad. He says to everyone else in the bar: See, that guy s gonna win this election! b. Judgments: (i) Sentence (1a) is sorta OK (meh?) (ii) Sentence (1b) is totally, definitely OUT! 2

(5) Some New Terminology: De Se Attitude 1 An agent x bears a de se attitude towards some content P only if: a. P is about x b. x figures into P in virtue of x thinking of themselves in a first personal way (Definition adapted from Pearson 2016) (6) De Se Attitudes More Informally a. In a de se attitude, like that expressed by (1b), the attitude holder is consciously self-ascribing a particular property (e.g., the property of going to win ) b. In a non-de se attitude, like that expressible by (1a), the attitude holder merely stands in a particular relation to a proposition involving themselves they needn t consciously recognize that they are themselves a component of that propositional content (7) Generalizations Invited by Facts like (4) a. Attitude sentences with Control infinitives can only express de se attitudes. Hence, the infelicity of (1b) in scenario (4a) b. Attitude sentences with finite complement need not express de se attitudes. Hence, the felicity of (1a) in scenario (4a) (8) The Obvious Task Now How can we augment our semantics to capture (7)? We need a theory of the truth-conditions of the de se reading for (1b). We need to concoct a story whereby (1b) can only get those truth-conditions, while (1a) doesn t (necessarily). 2. A Formal Theory of De Se Truth-Conditions (9) David Lewis s Insight About De Se Readings Lewis (1979) was the first to propose that de se readings involve the (conscious) selfascription of a property 99.999% of subsequent philosophical and semantic work builds on this key idea 1 The term de se is Latin for about oneself. 3

(10) Introducing Doxastic Alternatives a. Our Old Friend Beliefs, Restated: (i) Earlier Definition: Beliefs(x,w) = the worlds consistent with x s beliefs in w (ii) An Equivalent (But More Complicated) Formulation: Beliefs(x,w) = the worlds that x (in w) thinks they could be in b. A New Game Involving Beliefs To motivate Beliefs in (10a), we imagined playing a game, where we submit possible worlds to an entity x and ask Could this be the world you re in? We could also imagine another variant on this game o We submit to the entity x a pair consisting of a world w and an entity y from that world o We ask entity x, Given what you believe, could you be the entity y living in this world w? The set of pairs <y,w > to which the entity x answers Yes to are (obviously) those pairs <y,w > such that x (in w) thinks they could be y in w. c. Our New Friend, Doxastic Alternatives Dox-Alt(x,w) = the pairs <y,w > such that x (in w) thinks they could be y in w. Note that, just like Beliefs(x,w), Dox-Alt(x,w) can also be used to model the belief state of x in w. Note, moreover, that is provides even richer, more fine-grained information than Beliefs(x,w) o In addition to giving us the worlds that x thinks they re in o Dox-Alt also tells us the things in those worlds that x consciously identifies themselves as! 4

With all this in mind, the following seems like an attractive way of modeling the de se truthconditions of sentence (1b) (11) Dox-Alt and De Se Attitudes [[(1b)]] w = T iff For all <y,w > Dox-Alt(Dave,w): y wins in w These truth-conditions do not hold in scenario (4a) o After all, if we submitted to Dave a pair <y,w > such that y wins in w, Dave would (by assumption) say that he couldn t be entity y in world w But, these truth-conditions would definitely hold in a scenario where Dave thinks (optimistically) to himself I am going to win o Again, any pair <y,w > that Dave would say yes to in our game, must be one where y goes on to win! 3. Deriving the Desired Truth-Conditions So How can we set up things so that sentence (1b) receives the truth-conditions in (11)? Recalling the key insight in (9) that de se attitudes involve the (conscious) selfascription of a property Let s suppose that Control complements denote properties (type <s<et>>) (12) Lexical Semantics of Expect Control When it combines with a control complement, expect has the lexical semantics below: [[ expect ]] w = [ λp <s<e,t>> : [ λx : For all <y,w > Dox-Alt(x,w): P(w )(y) = T ] ] (13) Syntax of Control Complements As noted above in (3a), PRO has to be bound However, its not bound by the matrix subject, but rather by an operator in the leftperiphery of the control complement. 2 [ S1 Dave 1 [ VP expects [ CP 1 [ S2 PRO 1 to win ] ] ] ] 2 This general approach to the compositional semantics of Control is widely attributed to Chierchia (1990), Anaphora and Attitudes De Se. 5

(14) Derivation of the Desired Truth-Conditions a. [[(13)]] w,g = T iff (by FA, Lex.) b. [[VP]] w,g ( Dave ) = T iff (by IFA) c. [[expects]] w,g ( [λw : [[CP]] w,g ] )(Dave) = T iff (by PA) d. [[expects]] w,g ( [λw : λx: [[S]] w,g(1/x) ] )(Dave) = T iff (by FA, Lex., LC) e. [[expects]] w,g ( [λw : λx: x wins in w ] )(Dave) = T iff (by Lex.) f. [ λp <s<e,t>> : [ λx : For all <y,w > Dox-Alt(x,w): P(w )(y) = T ] ] ( [λw : λx: x wins in w ] )(Dave) = T iff (by LC) g. For all <y,w > Dox-Alt(Dave,w): [λw : λx: x wins in w ](w )(y) = T iff (by LC) h. For all <y,w > Dox-Alt(Dave,w): y wins in w A Potentially Problematic Quirk of This Treatment: Under this analysis, PRO is not directly bound by the subject Rather, it s bound by an operator in the left periphery of the subordinate clause The understood co-evaluation of PRO and the subject is due to the lexical semantics of the attitude verb (and the nature of what a Doxastic Alternative is) In recent work, Landau (2015) argues that this is in conflict with the syntactic evidence that the subject does directly bind PRO in control sentences like (1b) 3 o Landau proposes a synthesis of these two analyses, which allows us to retain the core of our semantic treatment above But what about sentence (1a)?... 3 Direct Variable Binding and Agreement in Obligatory Control. Available online at Lingbuzz: http://ling.auf.net/lingbuzz/002392 6

(15) Some Initial Thoughts on Finite Complements In a few more classes, we ll develop a more in-depth treatment of the reading sentences like (1a) get in scenarios like (4) (i.e., so-called de re readings) For now, though, it can be noted that our original semantics in (2c) actually does a pretty good job! o Note that (2c) says only that in all of Dave s belief worlds, Dave is the winner. o These truth-conditions are completely agnostics as to whether Dave consciously self-identifies as the winner or not. o Thus, these truth-conditions would seem to hold both in scenarios with conscious self-identification ( I m going to win ) and ones without it (4a). o Thus, at first glance, they d seem to do the right job They predict that (1a) will end up being construed as true in either such scenario But, we ll have much more to say about this later 7