Response to Kadri Vihvelin s counterfactuals and dispositions

Similar documents
The incompleteness of dispositional predicates

3. Nomic vs causal vs dispositional essentialism. 1. If quidditism is true, then properties could have swapped their nomic roles.

Handout 8: Bennett, Chapter 10

Tooley on backward causation

Assignment 3 Logic and Reasoning KEY

An Argument for the Extrinsic Grounding of Mass

The claim that composition is identity is an intuition in search of a formulation.

Philosophy 5340 Epistemology. Topic 3: Analysis, Analytically Basic Concepts, Direct Acquaintance, and Theoretical Terms. Part 2: Theoretical Terms

Gunk Mountains: A Puzzle

EASTERN DIVISION OF THE AMERICAN PHILOSOPHICAL ASSOCIATION 2009 GROUP MEETING: THE PHILOSOPHY OF TIME SOCIETY

Simply Possible. Theodore Sider Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 60 (2000):

CAUSATION CAUSATION. Chapter 10. Non-Humean Reductionism

Précis of Modality and Explanatory Reasoning

On Linking Dispositions and Conditionals David Manley and Ryan Wasserman

*a * * *b * * *c *d *

Cartwright: Do the Laws of Physics State the Facts?

Counterfactuals and comparative similarity

PROOF-THEORETIC REDUCTION AS A PHILOSOPHER S TOOL

The Ontology of Pure Dispositions

(1) If Bush had not won the last election, then Nader would have won it.

HPS 1653 / PHIL 1610 Introduction to the Philosophy of Science

Lecture 12: Arguments for the absolutist and relationist views of space

Indicative conditionals

Commentary. Regression toward the mean: a fresh look at an old story

Critical Notice: Bas van Fraassen, Scientific Representation: Paradoxes of Perspective Oxford University Press, 2008, xiv pages

Review of Gordon Belot, Geometric Possibility Oxford: Oxford UP, 2011

The Varieties of (Relative) Modality

Conceivability and Modal Knowledge

6.080 / Great Ideas in Theoretical Computer Science Spring 2008

Euler s Galilean Philosophy of Science

Baker. 1. Classical physics. 2. Determinism

In Newcomb s problem, an agent is faced with a choice between acts that

Throwing Darts, Time, and the Infinite

Objective probability-like things with and without objective indeterminism

Notes 11: OLS Theorems ECO 231W - Undergraduate Econometrics

Williamson s Modal Logic as Metaphysics

Ian Jarvie, Karl Milford and David Miller (eds.): Karl Popper - A Centenary Assessment. Volume III: Science. Ashgate Pub., Aldershot 2006,

CS 124 Math Review Section January 29, 2018

Math 31 Lesson Plan. Day 2: Sets; Binary Operations. Elizabeth Gillaspy. September 23, 2011

Causal Structuralism, Dispositional Actualism, and Counterfactual Conditionals

The Power of Possible Causation

Some Thoughts on Computation and Simulation in Cognitive Science

So, what are special sciences? ones that are particularly dear to the author? ( Oh dear. I am touched. Psychology is just, so, well, special!

Philosophy 240 Symbolic Logic. Russell Marcus Hamilton College Fall 2013

SIMILARITY IS A BAD GUIDE TO COUNTERFACTUAL TRUTH. The Lewis-Stalnaker logic systems [2] account for a wide range of intuitions about

HSSP Philosophy of Quantum Mechanics 08/07/11 Lecture Notes

Regularity analyses have failed; it is time to give up and try something else: a counterfactual analysis.

Minimal models with three-valued logic: The case of counterfactual conditionals

Yet Another Objection to Fading and Dancing Qualia (5th draft)

Must... stay... strong!

CH 59 SQUARE ROOTS. Every positive number has two square roots. Ch 59 Square Roots. Introduction

Wittgenstein on The Standard Metre

DISCUSSION CENSORED VISION. Bruce Le Catt

Physicalism

P (E) = P (A 1 )P (A 2 )... P (A n ).

Marc Lange -- IRIS. European Journal of Philosophy and Public Debate

Favoring, Likelihoodism, and Bayesianism

Paradoxes of special relativity

Sklar s Maneuver. Bradford Skow ABSTRACT

LECTURE FOUR MICHAELMAS 2017 Dr Maarten Steenhagen Causation

The Foundations of Mathematics. Frege s Logicism

Incompatibility Paradoxes

Lecture 14, Thurs March 2: Nonlocal Games

DIFFERENTIAL EQUATIONS

The paradox of knowability, the knower, and the believer

Universalism Entails Extensionalism

Predicates, Quantifiers and Nested Quantifiers

Math 38: Graph Theory Spring 2004 Dartmouth College. On Writing Proofs. 1 Introduction. 2 Finding A Solution

Weak and Global Supervenience Are Strong

4.3 Rational Inequalities and Applications

Lecture 18 Newton on Scientific Method

Appendix A Lewis s Counterfactuals

Introduction to Algebra: The First Week

Many philosophers accept a layered world view according to which the facts about

Of Miracles and Interventions

Does Frege have too many thoughts? A Cantorian problem revisited

Physics Fall Semester. Sections 1 5. Please find a seat. Keep all walkways free for safety reasons and to comply with the fire code.

Math 54 Homework 3 Solutions 9/

Introduction to Proofs

Sortals and Criteria of Identity

Popper s Measure of Corroboration and P h b

Computability Crib Sheet

Gödel s Argument for Cantor s Cardinals Matthew W. Parker Centre for Philosophy of Natural and Social Science

Comparative Bayesian Confirmation and the Quine Duhem Problem: A Rejoinder to Strevens Branden Fitelson and Andrew Waterman

PHIL12A Section answers, 14 February 2011

Discrete Structures Proofwriting Checklist

Complex Numbers: A Brief Introduction. By: Neal Dempsey. History of Mathematics. Prof. Jennifer McCarthy. July 16, 2010

Emergent Substances, Physical Properties, Action Explanations

TRACING THE ORIGIN OF LIFE

, (1) e i = ˆσ 1 h ii. c 2016, Jeffrey S. Simonoff 1

Solving with Absolute Value

Russell s logicism. Jeff Speaks. September 26, 2007

PHILOSOPHY OF PHYSICS (Spring 2002) 1 Substantivalism vs. relationism. Lecture 17: Substantivalism vs. relationism

The Pragmatics of Scientific Laws

GRAVITY SIMULATOR: Our Solar System

Relevant Logic. Daniel Bonevac. March 20, 2013

Breaking de Morgan s law in counterfactual antecedents

Clicker Ques,ons for NEXUS/Physics. Atomic Interactions & Chemical Energy

What is Crater Number Density?

We have seen that the symbols,,, and can guide the logical

Transcription:

University of Nebraska - Lincoln DigitalCommons@University of Nebraska - Lincoln Faculty Publications - Department of Philosophy Philosophy, Department of 2012 Response to Kadri Vihvelin s counterfactuals and dispositions Jennifer McKitrick University of Nebraska-Lincoln, jmckitrick2@unl.edu Follow this and additional works at: http://digitalcommons.unl.edu/philosfacpub McKitrick, Jennifer, "Response to Kadri Vihvelin s counterfactuals and dispositions " (2012). Faculty Publications - Department of Philosophy. 8. http://digitalcommons.unl.edu/philosfacpub/8 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Philosophy, Department of at DigitalCommons@University of Nebraska - Lincoln. It has been accepted for inclusion in Faculty Publications - Department of Philosophy by an authorized administrator of DigitalCommons@University of Nebraska - Lincoln.

Published in Philosophical Studies: An International Journal for Philosophy in the Analytic Tradition; doi: 10.1007/s11098-012-9898-3 Copyright 2012 Springer Science+Business Media B.V. Used by permission. Published online March 6, 2012 Response to Kadri Vihvelin s counterfactuals and dispositions Jennifer McKitrick University of Nebraska Lincoln, Lincoln, NE, USA Email jmckitrick2@unlnotes.unl.edu Keywords: Disposition, Counterfactual, Causal bases, Extrinsic diposition By incorporating David Lewis conditional analysis (LCA), Vihvelin s LCA-PROP inherits some of its problems. Recall: LCA x is disposed at time t to give response R to stimulus S iff, for some intrinsic property B that x has at t, for some time t after t, if x were to undergo stimulus S at time t and retain property B until time t, S and x s having of B would jointly be an x-complete cause of x s giving response R. Vihvelin amends this by adding for some suitable proportion of the test cases to deal with problematic masking cases, resulting in: LCA-PROP x is disposed at time t to give response R to stimulus S iff, for some intrinsic property B that x has at t, for some time t after t, and for some suitable proportion of test-cases, if x were in a test-case at t and retained property B until time t, S and x s having of B would be an x-complete cause of x s giving response R. I have three issues with LCA that apply equally to LCA-PROP. The first is perhaps a trivial issue regarding a lack of clarity of the analysis, though it may amount to something more significant, depending on the clarification. It concerns the phrase x-complete cause. According to the analysis: S and x s having of B would jointly be an x-complete cause of x s giving response R. Now, what is an xcomplete cause? Lewis tells us that an x-complete cause of R is a complete cause of R, in so far as the properties of x are concerned. Likewise, in a footnote, Vihvelin ex- 1

2 J. McKitrick in Philosophical Studies (2012) plains A Joe-complete cause is a cause, that is complete, so far as Joe s intrinsic properties are concerned, of Joe s walking. This might suggest that the x-complete cause is the contribution that x s properties make to the manifestation. But look at the wording of the analysis. It says that the stimulus S and the base property B would jointly be an x-complete cause of response R. That entails that the stimulus and the base property would jointly be a complete cause of the manifestation as far as the properties of x are concerned. But what does that mean? One way to read this is as saying that the stimulus and the causal basis are both properties of x. It s plausible, and is in fact stipulated by the analysis, that the base property B is a property of x, but what about the stimulus? Typical stimuli, such as striking, dropping, and submerging in water, don t seem like properties of x. They don t even seem like properties. Even if we focus on properties that are instantiated by the stimulus event, it s not clear that they would typically be properties of the disposed object. Often, a disposition s stimulus is extrinsic to the disposed object. The striking that stimulates the glass s fragility is extrinsic to the glass. The striking may have certain properties, such as happening at a certain time, in a certain place, with a certain force, and the hammer is hard, made of steel, etc. But these are not properties of the glass. Perhaps the glass has related relational properties, such as being in a certain proximity to a steel hammer moving at a certain velocity, and so on. But if stimulus S is supposed to refer to these relational properties of x, that is not made clear. Furthermore, Vihvelin s analysis claims that the Joe-complete cause consists of intrinsic properties of Joe. If the stimulus and the base properties are a Joe-complete cause, then the properties that trigger Joe s disposition must be intrinsic to Joe. In Vihvelin s example, it s something about Joe that stimulates his walking. But isn t it possible for Joe to be stimulated to walk by some event extrinsic to Joe, such as someone saying Hey Joe, could you come here for sec? Another way to read the expression complete as far as the properties of x are concerned is that nothing further is needed from x to cause the manifestation. But what does this add to simply saying that the stimulus and the causal basis would cause, or would be causally sufficient for the manifestation? Perhaps it is meant to rule out the possibility that some property of x other than B could also contribute to causing the manifestation. But it s not clear why anyone would want to rule that out. It means that a response can never be over-determined by multiple dispositions. Perhaps my conversing with people at the reception is over-determined by my being professionally ambitious and by my being sociable. The account would say that, in order for my sociability to count as a disposition, I must have some intrinsic property that serves as the causal basis of my sociability, such that it alone, and none of my other properties, would causally contribute to my engaging in conversation at the reception. If this is the proper way to understand x-complete cause, it rules out the possibility over-determining dispositions by definition. Lewis is not concerned to make room for over-determination in his theory of causation, and on this interpretation of LCA, he seems to go out of his way to rule out the possibility of overdetermination. But do we have any good reason to retain this feature of his view? I don t see any. Perhaps a more philosophically significant issue with LCA-PROP is its implication that every disposition must have a causal basis. Some philosophers argue that

R e s p o n s e to Kadri Vihvelin s counterfactuals and dispositions 3 dispositions do not necessarily have causal bases; there can be pure, ungrounded or bare dispositions. It s not a conceptual truth that dispositions have causal bases. If scientists found a certain particle that was disposed to behave in a certain way, and they could not identify any property of that particle to serve as the causal basis of that disposition, then they might conclude that there must be a basis there, and they just haven t found it yet. But if our best scientific research indicates that there is no hidden variable, then it seems reasonable to conclude that they found a disposition that has no causal basis. If such a scenario makes sense, the existence of a causal basis for every disposition is not a conceptual matter, but an empirical one. Furthermore, it seems that the answer to the empirical question does not favor ubiquitous causal bases. The natures of fundamental properties, such as mass and charge, seem to be exhausted by their dispositionality, and further study reveals no deeper structure to serve as the intrinsic properties to ground these dispositions. LCA-PROP would seem, therefore, to be inapplicable to the most fundamental properties of the physical world. One might argue that, if there are such cases where something has a disposition but has no other property that grounds the disposition, that is compatible with the analysis. The analysis states that when x has a disposition, there is some intrinsic property B that x has at t. It doesn t stipulate that B must be a distinct property. It s compatible with that claim that the intrinsic property is the disposition itself. A disposition that has no distinct causal basis could be its own causal basis. I have some sympathy with this response. However, notice that it might fail as an analysis, since reference to the disposition would appear on the analysans side of the bi-conditional. Furthermore, if the disposition itself could be property B in the analysis, that is, if a disposition could causally contribute to its own manifestation, then the motivation to introduce an additional property into the analysis becomes unclear, and the suggestion that only the causal basis and not the disposition itself can be causally relevant becomes more doubtful. The third issue I have with this analysis is its insistence that the causal basis of the disposition must be intrinsic to the disposed object. Dispositions are not necessarily intrinsic to the objects that have them, and when they are not, it s plausible that those dispositions have extrinsic causal bases. Contrary to Lewis, perfect duplicates could differ with respect to having certain dispositions; a thing can lose or acquire dispositions without changing intrinsically. Weight, for example, may be dispositional, but it s not intrinsic. The weight of an object is relative to the object s gravitational field. So, the causal basis of an object s weight is not limited to the intrinsic properties of the object, but must also include some of its extrinsic properties, such as the object s spatial relations to massive bodies. One might object that being subject to a certain gravitational field is part of the circumstances of manifestation of having a certain weight, or not part of the testcase for attributing that weight to something. However, this is not in accord with the meaning of weight, if ordinary usage is any guide. A visit to the Your Weight on Other Worlds website amply demonstrates this. The site asks Ever wonder what you might weigh on Mars or the Moon? Here s your chance to find out. If the test case for your weight included being in the Earth s gravitational field, there would be no cause to wonder what you weigh on the moon.

4 J. McKitrick in Philosophical Studies (2012) One might argue that the real disposition here is mass, and that is intrinsic. I m not sure if such an objection means to deny that weight is a disposition, too. If it does, on what grounds does it do so? Perhaps the thought is that an object s weight is derived from its mass, and that mass is more fundamental. But if that s the reason why weight is being dismissed as a real disposition, then Joe s dispositions to walk and do math will be in trouble, for it is doubtful that they are fundamental in a way that weight is not. (I m not saying Joe s dispositions to walk and do math are extrinsically based, just that they are dispositions, and that the purported reason for thinking that weight is not a real disposition proves too much.) Furthermore, it can be argued that mass is extrinsically grounded as well. Theoretically, a particle has the mass that it does because of relations to other things in the universe, such as, perhaps, the Higgs field. If that s right, then the causal basis of an object s mass is not intrinsic to the object itself. But we need not delve into theoretical physics to find extrinsic dispositions. Vulnerability, marketability, visibility, humorousness, decipherability, and recognizability are all dispositions a thing could gain or loose without intrinsic change. That suggests that these are extrinsic dispositions, and if these dispositions have causal bases, they must be at least partially extrinsic to the disposed object. To summarize, I have three objections to LCA-PROP: 1. As far as I can understand what an x-complete cause is, the analysis is mistaken in claiming that a disposition s stimulus and its causal basis would jointly be an x-complete cause of its manifestation. 2. The analysis is mistaken if it assumes that dispositions necessarily have distinct causal bases. 3. The analysis is mistaken in assuming that the causal basis of a disposition must be an intrinsic property of the disposed object.