Regularity analyses have failed; it is time to give up and try something else: a counterfactual analysis.

Similar documents
David Lewis. Causation

LECTURE FOUR MICHAELMAS 2017 Dr Maarten Steenhagen Causation

The Power of Possible Causation

Lewis Counterfactual Theory of Causation

DISCUSSION CENSORED VISION. Bruce Le Catt

Faculty of Philosophy, University of Cambridge Michaelmas Term Part IA: Metaphysics Causation

Of Miracles and Interventions

Lecture 34 Woodward on Manipulation and Causation

As you scroll through this review, you move your hand; this causes the

Why Care About Counterfactual Support? The Cognitive Uses of Causal Order Lecture 2

Philosophy 4310: Conditionals Spring 2017

Tooley on backward causation

Indicative conditionals

Appendix A Lewis s Counterfactuals

In Newcomb s problem, an agent is faced with a choice between acts that

(1) If Bush had not won the last election, then Nader would have won it.

The incompleteness of dispositional predicates

David Lewis. Void and Object

March 2, 2007 Menéndez-Benito. Quick Introduction to the Semantics of Modals 1

Topic 4: Causation and conditionals

CAUSATION. Chapter 5. Humean Reductionism - Counterfactual Approaches

OXFORD PHILOSOPHICAL SOCIETY MEMBERS WEEKEND, AUGUST 2018 SCRIPT FOR THE PRESENTATION

Module 03 Lecture 14 Inferential Statistics ANOVA and TOI

CS1800: Strong Induction. Professor Kevin Gold

Response to Kadri Vihvelin s counterfactuals and dispositions

Conditionals. Ray Briggs Stanford University

SIMILARITY IS A BAD GUIDE TO COUNTERFACTUAL TRUTH. The Lewis-Stalnaker logic systems [2] account for a wide range of intuitions about

The problem of disjunctive causal factors. Following Hitchcock: fix K and do everything within a single cell K (which we don t mention).

Kripke on Frege on Sense and Reference. David Chalmers

Précis of Modality and Explanatory Reasoning

COUNTERFACTUALS, CAUSATION, AND PREEMPTION

Philosophy 240 Symbolic Logic. Russell Marcus Hamilton College Fall 2013

Brit. J. Phil. Sci. 46 (1995), Redundant Causation. Michael McDermott

Introduction to Aerospace Propulsion. Prof. Bhaskar Roy. Prof. A. M. Pradeep. Department of Aerospace Engineering

The State Explosion Problem

V. SCALING. A. Length scale - correlation length. h f 1 L a. (50)

1 Multiple Choice. PHIL110 Philosophy of Science. Exam May 10, Basic Concepts. 1.2 Inductivism. Name:

Metaphysics of Modality

Searle: Proper Names and Intentionality

HPS 1653 / PHIL 1610 Introduction to the Philosophy of Science

Probabilistic Causation, Preemption and Counterfactuals

Baker. 1. Classical physics. 2. Determinism

Break the Weakest Rules

Causal Reasoning. Note. Being g is necessary for being f iff being f is sufficient for being g

Michael Franke Fritz Hamm. January 26, 2011

TECHNISCHE UNIVERSITEIT EINDHOVEN Faculteit Wiskunde en Informatica. Final exam Logic & Set Theory (2IT61) (correction model)

Biostatistics: Correlations

Essay Review: Cause and Chance: Causation in an Indeterministic World, Phil Dowe and Paul Noordhof, eds., Routledge, 2004

Pig organ transplants within 5 years

The Eco Pyramid By Michael Stahl

Computability Crib Sheet

Breaking de Morgan s law in counterfactual antecedents

Kaplan s Paradox and Epistemically Possible Worlds

Discrete Mathematics and Probability Theory Fall 2013 Vazirani Note 1

So, what are special sciences? ones that are particularly dear to the author? ( Oh dear. I am touched. Psychology is just, so, well, special!

Hedging Your Ifs and Vice Versa

Truth Table Definitions of Logical Connectives

Identity in Physics and Elsewhere

The SI unit for Energy is the joule, usually abbreviated J. One joule is equal to one kilogram meter squared per second squared:

CAUSALITY: FROM HUME, VIA SCHLICK TO LEWIS* Christian Damböck Institute Vienna Circle University of Vienna

65,536 Definitions of Physicalism. David J. Chalmers

A Probabilistic Analysis of Causation

REALISM VERSUS QUANTUM MECHANICS: IMPLICATIONS OF SOME RECENT EXPERIMENTS

Antecedents of counterfactuals violate de Morgan s law

Formal Logic. Critical Thinking

Philosophy 5340 Epistemology. Topic 3: Analysis, Analytically Basic Concepts, Direct Acquaintance, and Theoretical Terms. Part 2: Theoretical Terms

EASTERN DIVISION OF THE AMERICAN PHILOSOPHICAL ASSOCIATION 2009 GROUP MEETING: THE PHILOSOPHY OF TIME SOCIETY

Revealed Preference 2011

A Remark About the Geodesic Principle in General Relativity

A Little Deductive Logic

Space, Time and Causality: Causa4on, II. David Lewis s Counterfactual Account

From Causality, Second edition, Contents

Hypothesis Testing. ) the hypothesis that suggests no change from previous experience

CS 453 Operating Systems. Lecture 7 : Deadlock

Lecture 31 Woodward on Actual Causes

Section 2.7 Solving Linear Inequalities

Commentary. Regression toward the mean: a fresh look at an old story

Philosophy 244: Modal Logic Preliminaries

Finite Automata Part One

A Little Deductive Logic

Finite Automata Part One

The claim that composition is identity is an intuition in search of a formulation.

CH 24 IDENTITIES. [Each product is 35] Ch 24 Identities. Introduction

Relations. Carl Pollard. October 11, Department of Linguistics Ohio State University

Week 2: Probability: Counting, Sets, and Bayes

Weighted Majority and the Online Learning Approach

Vocabulary atom atomos Dalton's atomic theory law of constant composition law of definite proportions law of multiple proportions matter.

First Order Logic (1A) Young W. Lim 11/5/13

For Philosophy and Phenomenolgical Research

6. Which of the following is not a basic need of all animals a. food b. friends c. water d. protection from predators

MITOCW watch?v=t6tqhnxy5wg

Some problems in giving an adequate model-theoretic account of CAUSE *

Math 300: Foundations of Higher Mathematics Northwestern University, Lecture Notes


Causal Modeling and Transitivity

A FLOW DIAGRAM FOR CALCULATING LIMITS OF FUNCTIONS (OF SEVERAL VARIABLES).

Basic methods to solve equations

Replay argument. Abstract. Tanasije Gjorgoski Posted on on 03 April 2006

Fundamentals of Mathematics I

PHILOSOPHY OF PHYSICS (Spring 2002) 1 Substantivalism vs. relationism. Lecture 17: Substantivalism vs. relationism

Transcription:

David Lewis Causation, in: Papers II p. 160: Causation is not the only causal relation. Regularity analyses have failed; it is time to give up and try something else: a counterfactual analysis. p. 161: Lewis only analyzes token causation. p. 162: Worse still, Only C-events cause E-events ought to mean (d) For every c, if there is some e in E such that c causes e, then c is in C. if only has its usual meaning. But no; it unambiguously means (b) instead! where (b) is For every e in E, there is some c in C such that c causes e. - How can Lewis say that a sentence ought to mean something but means something else? By what standard? Compare: Only humans laugh = for every animal a, if a laughs, then a is human. This is parallel to: Only C s cause E s = for every event a, if a causes an E, then a is a C. And this is (d). There is no reason whatsoever to parse it as (b). p. 163: The vagueness of similarity does infect causation, and no correct analysis can deny it. p. 164: The B s depend counterfactually on the A s iff for all B s b, b holds at all the closest worlds at which an A holds. p. 166: roughly, an event A depends causally an event B iff the propositions that B

occurs / that B does not occur (under any true description) are counterfactually dependent on the proposition that A occurs / that A does not occur (under any description). Then e depends causally on c iff the family O(e), ~O(e) depends counterfactually on the family O(c), ~O(c). Causal dependence is not yet causation. p. 167: Causal dependence among actual events implies causation. If c and e are two actual events such that e would not have occurred without c, then c is a cause of e. But I reject the converse. Causation must always be transitive; causal dependence may not be; so there can be causation without causal dependence. p. 167: A causes B iff there is a causal chain that leads from A to B. A causal chain is causal dependence extended to a transitive relation in the usual way. p. 170: one problem is that if c causes e, c would not have occurred if e had not. Lewis solution is to flatly deny the counterfactuals that cause the trouble ; that is, to deny that c would not have occurred had e not occurred. That is: Drinking a bottle of arsenic caused the death of A. Had A not died, it could also not have been true that A had consumed a bottle of arsenic. Lewis denies the latter. Compare the three scenarios: (1) A drinks a bottle of arsenic and dies (2) A drinks a bottle of arsenic and does not die. (3) A does not drink a bottle of arsenic and does not die. Lewis says that (2) is more similar to (1) than (3); which it is not. p. 171: Under determinism any divergence, soon or late, req[u]ires some violation of

the actual laws. Causation, Postscript p. 172: Lewis account works only if the relation of dependence is assumed to hold between distinct events. p. 173: the farther we depart from actuality, the more we lose control over our counterfactuals. p. 174: problem is that (a) my action of raising the flag causes the rising of the flag (b) the rising and my raising are the same event. Lewis deals with this by distinguishing between events being parts of other events, events being names in terms of other events. He says: My action of raising the flag does not include its rising, it is only characterized in terms of its causal consequence, which it does not include. p. 179: if I change the course of events so that an event gets less likely, I might still cause it by doing so. p. 186: Lewis distinguishes between sensitive and insensitive causation; which is a matter of degree. Causation is sensitive to the extent to which the effect of the cause in question also depends on other things. If the effect of a cause does not depend on many other things, the causation is not very sensitive. This is supposed to explain the difference between - killing / causing to die - making / causing to come to be - breaking / causing to be in pieces etc.

... the causing to die in killing must be of a comparatively insensitive kind. p. 196: an event is more fragile if its identity depends on more variables. We have names for robust events, and such robust events are internally causally structured such that the causation that structures them is sufficiently insensitive. But note that insensitivity concerns types, and fragility concerns token events. An event is fragile to the degree that it would not survive changes in the circumstantial setting. p. 203: late preemption (where the occurrence of an effect of cause A deactivates cause B, which would have cause to the same effect) is a real problem to Lewis analysis. For here the effect would have ensued even if the actual cause would not have gone through (p. 200). According to a counterfactual analysis, A is not a cause, then. p. 206: Lewis introduces a notion of quasi-dependence: e quasi-depends on c if e is a later part of a process P of which c is an earlier part; where P follows a generally specifiable pattern. And he says that c is a cause of e if there is a chain of such dependences from c to e. Lewis claims that such a construal would avoid cases of late preemption. p. 211: It is fair to discover the appropriate standards of similarity form the counterfactuals they make true, rather than vice versa. See also Counterfactual Dependence and Time s Arrow. Events, in Papers II p. 243-4: If an event occurs in a space-time region, - it does not occur in any proper part of this region, - it is occurring in all of its proper parts, and - it occurs within every region that includes the region in which it occurs.

p. 244-5: Lewis first says that for each event there is a corresponding property that belongs to all and only those spatiotemporal regions in which this event occurs. Then he claims that events are these properties. He thus needs an independent way of identifying the respective properties. To say that an event is the property that consists in its occurring in a certain space-time region would not help much. (I guess Lewis wants to say that events are what populates space-time regions such as to fill them with content; just as properties populate property-bearers and give them their shape. Then he should say that events are denizens of space-time regions.) p. 250: events are fragile if it is hard to change them without destroying them. p. 256: Saying Hello and saying Hello loudly are different events, since their causes and effects differ, but they are not distinct events. Causation as Influence (2000) p. 186: Besides whether-whether dependence, there is also when-whether dependence and more; that is whether B occurs depends counterfactually on whether A occurs when B occurs depends counterfactually on whether A occcurs when... when... where... whether... how... whether... how... when... etc. If we draw these distinctions, we do not need an elaborate theory about fragile events. We do not need to put times, places, manners etc. into the essence of an event, but can put them in the description of the causal relation.

p. 190: Where C and E are distinct actual events, let us say that C influences E if and only if there is a substantial range C1, C2... of different not-too-distant alterations of C (including the actual alteration of C) and there is a range E1, E2... of alterations of E, at least some of which differ, such that if C1 had occurred, El would have occurred, and if C2 had occurred, E2 would have occurred, and so on. Thus we have a pattern of dependence of how, when, and whether upon how, when, and whether. That is, very roughly, C is a cause of E if differences in C make a difference for E. p. 196: The problem with absences is that there are too many of them. But this is not really a problem, because in any case it is true that all these absences cause what they make possible. In most cases, it is just not worth mentioning. Also, absences are a special case because here we cannot influence the time, place, or manner in which they occur. They do not occur.