Lecture 3 - Axioms of Consumer Preference and the Theory of Choice

Similar documents
Lecture 6: Contraction mapping, inverse and implicit function theorems

Advanced Microeconomics

Lecture 8: Basic convex analysis

Adv. Micro Theory, ECON

Partial Solutions to Homework 2

Recitation 2-09/01/2017 (Solution)

Preferences and Utility

Part 2A. 3. Indifference Curves

Intro to Economic analysis

Chapter 1 - Preference and choice

Microeconomics, Block I Part 1

1 Uncertainty. These notes correspond to chapter 2 of Jehle and Reny.

x 1 1 and p 1 1 Two points if you just talk about monotonicity (u (c) > 0).

Recitation #2 (August 31st, 2018)

1 Objective. 2 Constrained optimization. 2.1 Utility maximization. Dieter Balkenborg Department of Economics

Preferences and Utility

個體經濟學一. Total utility of consuming (x, y), denoted as u(x, y), is the total level of total satisfaction of consuming(x, y).

Microeconomic Theory-I Washington State University Midterm Exam #1 - Answer key. Fall 2016

The Consumer, the Firm, and an Economy

BEEM103 UNIVERSITY OF EXETER. BUSINESS School. January 2009 Mock Exam, Part A. OPTIMIZATION TECHNIQUES FOR ECONOMISTS solutions

3/1/2016. Intermediate Microeconomics W3211. Lecture 3: Preferences and Choice. Today s Aims. The Story So Far. A Short Diversion: Proofs

Microeconomic Analysis

GS/ECON 5010 section B Answers to Assignment 1 September Q1. Are the preferences described below transitive? Strictly monotonic? Convex?

Econ Review Set 2 - Answers

Lecture Notes for Chapter 12

Advanced Microeconomics Fall Lecture Note 1 Choice-Based Approach: Price e ects, Wealth e ects and the WARP

Economics 501B Final Exam Fall 2017 Solutions

ECON2285: Mathematical Economics

Monotone comparative statics Finite Data and GARP

Lecture # 1 - Introduction

Existence, Computation, and Applications of Equilibrium

Almost Transferable Utility, Changes in Production Possibilities, and the Nash Bargaining and the Kalai-Smorodinsky Solutions

Microeconomics MSc. preference relations. Todd R. Kaplan. October University of Haifa. Kaplan (Haifa) micro October / 39

Week 6: Consumer Theory Part 1 (Jehle and Reny, Chapter 1)

It is convenient to introduce some notation for this type of problems. I will write this as. max u (x 1 ; x 2 ) subj. to. p 1 x 1 + p 2 x 2 m ;

Microeconomic Theory: Lecture 2 Choice Theory and Consumer Demand

ECON0702: Mathematical Methods in Economics

Midterm #1 EconS 527 Wednesday, February 21st, 2018

Economics 201b Spring 2010 Solutions to Problem Set 1 John Zhu

Microeconomic Theory -1- Introduction

Universidad Carlos III de Madrid June Microeconomics Grade

Revealed Preferences and Utility Functions

September Math Course: First Order Derivative

Definitions: A binary relation R on a set X is (a) reflexive if x X : xrx; (f) asymmetric if x, x X : [x Rx xr c x ]

Nonlinear Programming (NLP)

Econ Spring Review Set 1 - Answers ELEMENTS OF LOGIC. NECESSARY AND SUFFICIENT. SET THE-

Applications I: consumer theory

Partial Differentiation

Universidad Carlos III de Madrid May Microeconomics Grade

Sometimes the domains X and Z will be the same, so this might be written:

EconS 501 Final Exam - December 10th, 2018

; p. p y p y p y. Production Set: We have 2 constraints on production - demand for each factor of production must be less than its endowment

Advanced Microeconomics I: Consumers, Firms and Markets Chapters 1+2

CONSUMER DEMAND. Consumer Demand

Microeconomics MSc. preference relations. Todd R. Kaplan. October University of Haifa. Kaplan (Haifa) micro October / 42

ECON 304 MIDTERM EXAM ANSWERS

1 Uncertainty and Insurance

The Fundamental Welfare Theorems

z = f (x; y) f (x ; y ) f (x; y) f (x; y )

Economics 101. Lecture 2 - The Walrasian Model and Consumer Choice

Fall Final Examination Solutions Thursday 10 January 2012

Chapter 5: Preferences

Notes on Consumer Theory

1.5 The Derivative (2.7, 2.8 & 2.9)

Last Revised: :19: (Fri, 12 Jan 2007)(Revision:

Introduction to Economic Analysis Fall 2009 Problems on Chapter 1: Rationality

CHAPTER 4: HIGHER ORDER DERIVATIVES. Likewise, we may define the higher order derivatives. f(x, y, z) = xy 2 + e zx. y = 2xy.

Microeconomics. Joana Pais. Fall Joana Pais

Constrained optimization.

Lecture Notes October 18, Reading assignment for this lecture: Syllabus, section I.

Introduction to General Equilibrium

EconS Advanced Microeconomics II Handout on Mechanism Design

Structural Properties of Utility Functions Walrasian Demand

Final Examination with Answers: Economics 210A

Rules of Differentiation

Demand Theory. Lecture IX and X Utility Maximization (Varian Ch. 7) Federico Trionfetti

Econ 110: Introduction to Economic Theory. 8th Class 2/7/11

0 Aims of this course

The Kuhn-Tucker Problem

Tutorial 3: Optimisation

ECON501 - Vector Di erentiation Simon Grant

Lecture 7: General Equilibrium - Existence, Uniqueness, Stability

Microeconomics, Block I Part 2

GARP and Afriat s Theorem Production

Preference and Utility

Choice Theory. Matthieu de Lapparent

Differentiable Welfare Theorems Existence of a Competitive Equilibrium: Preliminaries

a = (a 1; :::a i )

Gi en Demand for Several Goods

c 2007 Je rey A. Miron

3. Neoclassical Demand Theory. 3.1 Preferences

Answer Key for M. A. Economics Entrance Examination 2017 (Main version)

Solow Growth Model. Michael Bar. February 28, Introduction Some facts about modern growth Questions... 4

Mathematical Foundations -1- Constrained Optimization. Constrained Optimization. An intuitive approach 2. First Order Conditions (FOC) 7

Tangent Plane. Nobuyuki TOSE. October 02, Nobuyuki TOSE. Tangent Plane

EE290O / IEOR 290 Lecture 05

Some Notes on Adverse Selection

Indian Institute of Technology Bombay

In economics, the amount of a good x demanded is a function of the price of that good. In other words,

BEE1024 Mathematics for Economists

Transcription:

Lecture 3 - Axioms of Consumer Preference and the Theory of Choice David Autor 14.03 Fall 2004 Agenda: 1. Consumer preference theory (a) Notion of utility function (b) Axioms of consumer preference (c) Monotone transformations 2. Theory of choice (a) Solving the consumer s problem Ingredients Characteristics of the solution Interior vs corner solutions (b) Constrained maximization for consumer (c) Interpretation of the Lagrange multiplier Road map: Theory 1. Consumer preference theory 2. Theory of choice 3. Individual demand functions 4. Market demand Applications 1

1. Dead weight loss of Christmas 2. Food stamps and other taxes and transfers 3. Gi en goods: Theory and evidence 1 Consumer Preference Theory A consumer s utility from consumption of a given bundle A is determined by a personal utility function. 1.1 Cardinal and ordinal utility Cardinal Utility Function According to this approach U(A) is a cardinal number, that is: U : consumption bundle! R 1 measured in utils Ordinal Utility Function More general than cardinal utility function U provides a ranking or preference ordering over bundles. Used in demand/consumer theory Cardinal vs Ordinal Utility Functions 8 < A P B U : (A; B)! B P A : A I B The problem with cardinal utility functions comes from the di culty in nding the appropriate measurement index (metric). Example: Is 1 util for person 1 equivalent to 1 util for person 2? Or if we increase a person s utility from 1 to 2, is she twice as happy? By being unit-free ordinal utility functions avoid these problems. What s important about utility functions is that it allows us to model how people make personal choices, that is, how they choose among competing alternatives. We do not t need to know how many utils people experience from each choice to answer this question; we just need to know how they rank choices. Note: It s much harder to model interpersonal comparisons of utility 2

1.2 Axioms of Consumer Preference Theory Created for purposes of: 1. Using mathematical representation of utility functions 2. Portraying rational behavior (rational in this case means optimizing ) 3. Deriving well-behaved demand curves 1.2.1 Axiom 1: Preferences are Complete ( Completeness ) For any two bundles A and B, a consumer can establish a preference ordering. That is, for any comparison of bundles, she will choose one and only one of the following: 1. A P B 2. B P A 3. A I B Without this property, preferences are unde ned. 1.2.2 Axiom 2: Preferences are Transitive ( Transitivity ) For any consumer if A P B and B P C then it must be that A P C: Consumers are consistent in their preferences. 1.2.3 Axiom 3: Preferences are Continuous ( Continuity ) If A P B and C lies within an " radius of B then A P C. We need continuity to derive well-behaved demand curves. Given Axioms 1-3 are obeyed we can always de ne a utility function. Any utility function that satis es Axioms 1-3 cannot have indi erence curves that cross. Indi erence Curves De ne a level of utility say U(x) = U then the indi erence curve for U, IC(U) is the locus of consumption bundles that generate utility level U for utility function U(x). An Indi erence Curve Map is a sequence of indi erence curves de ned over every possible bundle and every utility level: fic(0); IC("); IC(2"); :::g with " = epsilon 3

Utils Utility function (3D) Graph 25 Good x IC (2D) Good y Graph 26 Indi erence curves are level sets of this utility function. y IC 3 IC 2 IC 1 IC 3! Utility level U 3 IC 2! Utility level U 2 IC 1! Utility level U 1 9 = ; U 3 > U 2 > U 1 x This is called an Indi erence Curve Map Properties: Every consumption bundle lies on some indi erence curve (by the completeness axiom) INDIFFERENCE CURVES CANNOT INTERSECT (by the transitivity axiom) Proof: say two indi erence curves intersect: 4

Graph 27 Good y D C A B Good x According to these indi erence curves: A P B B I C C P D D I A By the above mentioned axioms: A P D and A I D which is a contradiction. Axioms 4. and 5. are introduced to re ect observed behavior. They simplify problems greatly, but they are not necessary for a theory of rational choice. 1.2.4 Axiom 4: Non-Satiation (Never Get Enough) Given two bundles, A and B, composed of two goods, X and Y. X A = amount of X in A, similarly X B Y A = amount of Y in A, similarly Y B If X A = X B and Y A > Y B (assuming utility is increasing in both arguments) then A P B (regardless of the levels of X A ; X B ; Y A ; Y B ) This implies that: 1. The consumer always places positive value on more consumption 2. Indi erence curve map stretches out endlessly (there is no upper limit to utility) 1.2.5 Axiom 5: Diminishing Marginal Rate of Substitution In order to de ne this axiom we need to introduce the concept of Marginal Rate of Substitution and some further preliminary explanations. 5

De nition: MRS measures willingness to trade one bundle for another. Example: Bundle A = (6 hours of sleep, 50 points on the problem set) Bundle B = (5 hours of sleep, 60 points on the problem set) A and B lie on the same indi erence curve A student is willing to give up 1 more hour of sleep for 10 more points on the problem set. Her willingness to substitute sleep for grade points at the margin (i.e. for 1 fewer hours of sleep) is: 10 1 = 10 MRS (sleep for points) = j 10j = 10 MRS is measured along an indi erence curve and it may vary along the same indi erence curve. If so, we must de ne the MRS relative to some bundle (starting point). du = 0 along an indi erence curve Therefore: 0 = @U @U dx + @x @y dy 0 = MU x dx + MU y dy dy dx = MU x = MRS of x for y MU y MRS must always be evaluated at some particular point (consumption bundle) on the indi erence curve. So one should really write MRS(x; y) where(x; y) is a particular consumption bundle. We are ready to explain what is meant by Diminishing Marginal Rate of Substitution. Graph 28 y (sleep) A y 2 10 1 B 10 C 0 x (problem set points) 6

MRS of x for y decreases as we go down on the indi erence curve. This indi erence curve exhibits diminishing MRS: the rate at which (at the margin) a consumer is willing to trade x for y diminishes as the level of x consumed goes up. That is the slope of the indi erence curve between points B and C is less than the slope of the curve between points A and B. Diminishing MRS is a consequence of Diminishing Marginal Utility. A utility function exhibits diminishing marginal utility for good x when MU x decreases as consumption of x increases. A bow-shaped-to-origin (convex) indi erence curve is one in which utility function has diminishing MU for Graph 29 both goods. y Diminishing MRS y for x Diminishing MRS x for y This implies that consumer prefers diversity in consumption. An alternative de nition of diminishing MRS can be given through the mathematical notion of convexity. De nition: a function U(x; y) is convex if: U(x 1 + (1 )x 2 ; y 1 + (1 )y 2 ) U(x 1 ; y 1 ) + (1 )U(x 2 ; y 2 ) x Suppose the two bundles, (x 1 ; y 1 ) and (x 2 ; y 2 ) are on the same indi erence curve. This property states that the convex combination of this two bundles is on higher indi erence curve than the two initial ones. 7

y Graph 30 y 2 y* y 1 x 2 x* x 1 x where x = x 1 + (1 )x 2 and y = y 1 + (1 )y 2. This is veri ed for every 2 (0; 1). The following is an example of a non-convex curve: y Graph 31 y 2 y 1 x 2 x 1 x In this graph not every point on the line connecting two points above the curve is also above the curve, therefore the curve is not convex. 8

Q: Suppose co ee and sushi have the same quality: the more you consume, the more you want. How do we draw this? For a given budget, should you diversify if you have this kind of preferences? No, because preferences are not convex. Graph 32 sushi U 1 U 2 U 0 coffee 1.3 Cardinal vs Ordinal Utility A utility function of the form U(x; y) = f(x; y) is cardinal in the sense that it reads o utils as a function of consumption. Obviously we don t know what utils are or how to measure them. Nor do we assume that 10 utils is twice as good as 5 utils. That is a cardinal assumption. What we really care about is the ranking (or ordering) that a utility function gives over bundles of goods. Therefore we prefer to use ordinal utility functions. We want to know if A P B but not by how much. However we do care that the MRS along an indi erence curve is well de ned, i.e. we do want to know precisely how people trade o among goods in indi erent (equally preferred) bundles. Q: How can we preserve properties of utility that we care about and believe in (1.ordering is unique and 2. MRS exists) without imposing cardinal properties? A: We state that utility functions are only de ned up to a monotonic transformation. De nition: Monotonic Transformation Let I be an interval on the real line (R 1 ) then: g : I! R 1 is a monotonic transformation if g is a strictly increasing function on I. If g(x) is di erentiable then g 0 (x) > 0 8x 9

Informally: A monotone transformation of a variable is a rank-preserving transformation. [Note: not all rank-preserving transformations are di erentiable.] Examples: Which are monotone functions Let y be de ned on R 1 : 1. x = y + 1 [yes] 2. x = 2y [yes] 3. x = exp(y) [yes] 4. x = abs(y) [no] 5. x = y 2 if y 0 [yes] 6. x = ln(y) if y > 0 [yes] 7. x = y 3 if y 0 [yes] 8. x = 1 y [yes but unde ned if y = 0] 9. x = max(y 2 ; y 3 ) if y 0 [yes] 10. x = 2y y 2 [no] Property: If U 2 (:) is a monotone transformation of U 1 (:), i.e. U 2 (:) = f(u 1 (:)) where f(:) is monotone in U 1 as de ned earlier, then: U 1 and U 2 exhibit identical preference rankings MRS of U 1 (U) and U 2 (U) =) U 1 and U 2 are equivalent for consumer theory Example: U(x; y) = x y (Cobb-Douglas) 10

Graph 33 y U 2 U 0 U 1 x What is the MRS along an indi erence curve U 0? U 0 = x 0 y 0 du 0 = x 1 0 y 0 dx + x 0 y 1 0 dy dy dx = U=U0 Consider now a monotonic transformation of U: x 1 0 y 0 x 0 y 1 0 = y 0 = @U=@x x 0 @U=@y U 1 (x; y) = x y U 2 (x; y) = ln(u 1 (x; y)) U 2 = ln x + ln y What is the MRS of U 2 along an indi erence curve such that U 2 = ln U 0? dy dx U 2 0 = ln U 0 = ln x 0 + ln y 0 du 2 0 = x 0 dx + y 0 dy = 0 U 2 =U 2 0 which is the same as we derived for U 1. = y 0 = @U=@x x 0 @U=@y How do we know that monotonic transformations always preserve the MRS of a utility function? 11

Let U = f(x; y) be a utility function Let g(u) be a monotonic transformation of U = f(x; y) The MRS of g(u) along an indi erence curve where U 0 = f(x 0 ; y 0 ) and g(u 0 ) = g(f(x 0 ; y 0 )) By totally di erentiating this equality we can obtain the MRS. dy dx dg(u 0 ) = g 0 (f(x 0 ; y 0 ))f x (x 0 ; y 0 )dx + g 0 (f(x 0 ; y 0 ))f y (x 0 ; y 0 )dy = g0 (f(x 0 ; y 0 ))f x (x 0 ; y 0 ) g 0 (f(x 0 ; y 0 ))f y (x 0 ; y 0 ) = f x(x 0 ; y 0 ) f y (x 0 ; y 0 ) = @U=@x @U=@y g(u)=g(u0) which is the MRS of the original function U(x; y). 12