Dominance and Admissibility without Priors

Similar documents
Choice Theory when Agents can Randomize

Continuity and completeness of strongly independent preorders

An Axiomatic Model of Reference Dependence under Uncertainty. Yosuke Hashidate

Mathematical Social Sciences

September 2007, France

Lecture Notes 1: Decisions and Data. In these notes, I describe some basic ideas in decision theory. theory is constructed from

Notes on Supermodularity and Increasing Differences. in Expected Utility

Axiomatic Decision Theory

Action-Independent Subjective Expected Utility without States of the World

Subjective multi-prior probability: a representation of a partial l

Great Expectations. Part I: On the Customizability of Generalized Expected Utility*

New Perspectives on Statistical Decisions under Ambiguity

Two-Stage-Partitional Representation and Dynamic Consistency 1

Reverse Bayesianism: A Generalization

Bayesian consistent prior selection

Rationalization of Collective Choice Functions by Games with Perfect Information. Yongsheng Xu

Conditional and Dynamic Preferences

Weak* Axiom of Independence and the Non-Expected Utility Theory

Lexicographic Expected Utility with a Subjective State Space

An additively separable representation in the Savage framework

How Restrictive Are Information Partitions?

Expected utility without full transitivity

Preference, Choice and Utility

Coherent Choice Functions Under Uncertainty* OUTLINE

Rationality and Uncertainty

Maxmin expected utility as resulting from information on others preferences

Second-Order Expected Utility

Rationality and solutions to nonconvex bargaining problems: rationalizability and Nash solutions 1

Columbia University. Department of Economics Discussion Paper Series. The Knob of the Discord. Massimiliano Amarante Fabio Maccheroni

Recitation 7: Uncertainty. Xincheng Qiu

Harsanyi s aggregation theorem with incomplete preferences

Utility Representation of Lower Separable Preferences

1 Axiomatic Bargaining Theory

Axiomatic Foundations of Expected Utility. and Subjective Probability

Probabilistic Subjective Expected Utility. Pavlo R. Blavatskyy

Incomplete Preferences under Uncertainty: Indecisiveness in Beliefs vs. Tastes

Decision Making under Uncertainty and Subjective. Probabilities

Recursive Ambiguity and Machina s Examples

Completing the State Space with Subjective States 1

Anscombe & Aumann Expected Utility Betting and Insurance

Familiarity Breeds Completeness

Regret aversion and opportunity dependence

AN ORDINAL SOLUTION TO BARGAINING PROBLEMS WITH MANY PLAYERS

The Interdisciplinary Center, Herzliya School of Economics Advanced Microeconomics Fall Bargaining The Axiomatic Approach

Chapter 1 - Preference and choice

Introductory notes on stochastic rationality. 1 Stochastic choice and stochastic rationality

3 Intertemporal Risk Aversion

Uncertainty and Robustness of Surplus Extraction

13 Social choice B = 2 X X. is the collection of all binary relations on X. R = { X X : is complete and transitive}

Follow links for Class Use and other Permissions. For more information send to:

Tijmen Daniëls Universiteit van Amsterdam. Abstract

Nash Equilibria of Games When Players Preferences Are Quasi-Transitive

This corresponds to a within-subject experiment: see same subject make choices from different menus.

Department of Economics

Expected utility without full transitivity

Single-plateaued choice

Monotone Preferences over Information. Juan Dubra and Federico Echenique. March 2001

Stagnation proofness and individually monotonic bargaining solutions. Jaume García-Segarra Miguel Ginés-Vilar 2013 / 04

Bayesian consistent prior selection

Preferences for Randomization and Anticipation

Extensions of Expected Utility Theory and some Limitations of Pairwise Comparisons

A Subjective Model of Temporal Preferences

Lexicographic Choice under Variable Capacity Constraints

The Rational Core of Preference Relations

A MODEL OF PROCEDURAL DECISION MAKING IN THE PRESENCE OF RISK 1. INTRODUCTION

Weak Robust (Virtual) Implementation

Journal of Mathematical Economics

A Behavioral Characterization of Plausible Priors

Comment on The Veil of Public Ignorance

Coalitional Strategic Games

Endogenizing Prospect Theory s Reference Point. by Ulrich Schmidt and Horst Zank

Suzumura-consistent relations: an overview

Decision-making with belief functions

Cooperative bargaining: independence and monotonicity imply disagreement

The core of voting games: a partition approach

Homework #6 (10/18/2017)

No-envy in Queueing Problems

Engineering Decisions

Revisiting independence and stochastic dominance for compound lotteries

WEAKLY DOMINATED STRATEGIES: A MYSTERY CRACKED

Confidence Models of Incomplete Preferences

Expected Utility. Tommaso Denti. February 7, 2015

Are Probabilities Used in Markets? 1

Arrow s General (Im)Possibility Theorem

Cautious Expected Utility and the Certainty Effect

A Behavioral Characterization of Plausible Priors

1 Uncertainty. These notes correspond to chapter 2 of Jehle and Reny.

Rational Choice with Categories

Coalitional Structure of the Muller-Satterthwaite Theorem

Supplement to Framing Contingencies

Bayesian Updating for General Maxmin Expected Utility Preferences

Chapter 1. Preliminaries

Lecture Notes on Bargaining

Individual Rationality in Collective Choice

Riskiness for sets of gambles

Choosing the two finalists

Is it Possible to Define Subjective Probabilities in Purely Behavioral Terms? A Comment on Epstein-Zhang (2001)

Agreeing to disagree: The non-probabilistic case

Indifference or indecisiveness? Choice-theoretic foundations of incomplete preferences

Relative Benefit Equilibrating Bargaining Solution and the Ordinal Interpretation of Gauthier s Arbitration Scheme

Transcription:

Dominance and Admissibility without Priors Jörg Stoye Cornell University September 14, 2011 Abstract This note axiomatizes the incomplete preference ordering that reflects statewise dominance with respect to expected utility, as well as the according choice correspondence. The main motivation is to clarify how admissibility as understood by statisticians relates to existing axiomatizations. The answer is that it is characterized by Anscombe and Aumann s (1963) axioms, plus symmetry (Arrow and Hurwicz (1972)), less completeness. Characterizing the according choice correspondence requires relaxing the weak axiom of revealed preference. Keywords: admissibility, incompleteness, ambiguity, statistical decision theory. JEL codes: C44, D81. 1 Introduction This note provides an axiomatic characterization of the incomplete preference ordering described by Z Z % ( ) ( ) ( ) ( ) S (1) as well as the corresponding choice rule ( ) ={ : Â for no } (2) Here, Â is the asymmetric component of %, and are lottery-acts inducing objective probability distributions ( ) and ( ) over outcomes in state of the world S, is a utility function, and a menu is a set of acts. In words, is preferred over if it statewise dominates in terms of expected utility. The motivation for this investigation is that % corresponds to dominance of risk functions and membership in to admissibility of a decision rule in the sense that these words are used in statistics. 1 Address: Jörg Stoye, Department of Economics, Cornell University, Uris Hall, Ithaca, NY 14853, stoye@cornell.edu. 1 See Ferguson (1967) for a classic textbook account. 1

At the same time, different subsets of the axioms used are known to characterize numerous complete preferences, notably expected utility, maximin utility, and minimax regret. These axioms cannot jointly be fulfilled by a complete preference, yet they characterize % upon dropping completeness. Thinking of completeness as a pragmatic requirement rather than a substantive condition of rationality, one could, therefore, say that admissibility exhausts the overlap between many reasonable decision rules in a precise axiomatic sense. 2 Extending the characterization to requires additional work because does not fulfil the weak axiom of revealed preference (WARP, defined precisely below) and it is not true that % iff is chosen from { }. The next section presents and discusses the main result for %, and section 3 extends the characterization to. Relations to the literature are explained along the way. 2 Main Result Consider a set X of ultimate outcomes, theset X of finite lotteries over such outcomes, and a state space S with typical element and sigma-algebra Σ. Acts F are finite, Σ-measurable functions from S into X that map states onto lotteries ( ) X. An act is constant if ( ) does not depend on. The only restriction on S is that it must contain three distinct states. With the usual abuse of notation, X will be embedded in F by identifying constant acts with the corresponding lotteries. Mixtures between acts are defined as statewise probabilistic mixtures: ( +(1 ) )( ) = ( ) +(1 ) ( ). Attention will initially be on a preference relation % on F Fand on the following axioms. P.1: Transitivity % % = % P.2: Completeness on Constant Acts % or % for all constant acts X. P.3: Monotonicity If ( ) % ( ) for all S, then %. P.4: Independence % +(1 ) % +(1 ) 2 Indeed, this paper was spawned by the observation that column 1 in table 1 of Stoye (2011b) is not provided in the literature. See the same survey for more background, interpretation, and references. 2

for all acts and scalars (0 1). P.5: Continuity There are no acts s.t. +(1 )  for all [0 1) but or vice versa. P.6: Nontriviality  for some acts. P.7: Symmetry For any acts and disjoint, nonempty events Σ s.t. both and are constant on as well as, % 0 % 0 where 0 is defined by 0 ( ) = ( )k ( )k ( ) otherwise and 0 is defined analogously. P.1-6 are Anscombe and Aumann s (1963) axioms with two modifications: Completeness is only imposed on constant acts, and continuity is weakened along the lines of Aumann (1962). One could strengthen P.5 to mixture continuity, i.e. closedness of weak upper contour sets, without affecting the result. The improvement reported here will be important in the next section, however. Moreover, without completeness, mixture continuity is not equivalent to openness of strict upper contour sets. The latter will actually be failed, as will the usual Archimedean axiom (   +(1 )   +(1 ) for some (0 1)). Symmetry (Arrow and Hurwicz (1972)) is designed to prevent any imposition of prior weighting among states. It is plausible if, and only if, no prior information about differential plausibility etc. of states is available. The firstmainresultisasfollows: Theorem 1 A preference % fulfils axioms P.1-7 iff it can be expressed as in (1), where : X R is unique up to positive affine transformation. Proof. I only show only if. First, the restriction of % to constant acts X is von Neumann- Morgenstern expected utility by Herstein and Milnor (1953), thus there exists with claimed properties s.t. % R ( ) ( ) R ( ) ( ). 3 Next, define the mapping ( utility act ) : S R by ( ) = R ( ) ( ). Then ( ) ( ) for all implies % by monotonicity. Also 3 Mixture continuity, used by Herstein and Milnor (1953), can be derived from solvability, completeness, and independence. But in their first use (their theorem 1), P.5 will obviously do, and the second use (their theorem 2) is redundant given the stronger independence axiom used here. 3

using transitivity, = implies as well as % % for all ; thus, utility acts define equivalence classes among acts. I will henceforth equate acts with utility acts. Nontriviality now implies that the range of is not a singleton, thus it can be normalized to contain { 1 1}. Every Σ-measurable step function : S [ 1 1] then corresponds to an existing (utility) act. Let 0 be the constant act with zero utility. Independence, used with 0 as mixing act, implies that % % for every (0 1). If the range of is bounded, this suggests an obvious (namely the homothetic) extension of % to the set of Σ-measurable functions : S R, and the remainder of this proof can be carried out on the extension first. I will henceforth presume that the range of is unbounded. Define ª by ( ª )( ) = ( ) ( ), then repeated uses of independence (using and 0 as mixture acts) yield % ª % 0. Consider any nonconstant act, define [ ] asthe constant act with utility value min S ( ) [max S ( )], let [ ] betheeventonwhichthis utility is achieved, and write for the act that agrees with on event and with otherwise. Then % % by monotonicity. Yet also % 0 % 0 % 0 by symmetry. Also using independence, monotonicity, and transitivity, it follows that there exist numbers 0 s.t. min S ( )+ max S ( ) 0 implies  0 and min S ( )+ max S ( ) 0 implies that not % 0. Suppose by contradiction that 0. Let the constant acts ( ) have utility values (1 + 3 2) and let { } partition S into nonempty events (existence of three distinct states ensures feasibility of this), then it would follow that  0,  0, but not 1 2 + 1 2 % 0. This is a contradiction because  0 1 2 + 1 2  1 2 0 + 1 2 and  0 1 2 0 + 1 2  0 by independence, thus 1 2 + 1 2  0 by transitivity. Thus =0, hence min S ( ) 0 is necessary for % 0 ;itissufficient by monotonicity. This model can be contrasted with a multiple prior version whereby % iff R ( ) R ( ) for all priors in a convex set Γ, as recently axiomatized by Gilboa et al. (2010). The present, prior-less version corresponds to the case where Γ collects all distributions on (S Σ). Gilboa et al. s (2010) axioms imply P.1-P.5, thus theorem 1 establishes that adding symmetry to them enforces the maximal set of priors. However, the above proof is brief, self-contained, elementary, and weakens continuity. In earlier work, Bewley (2002) uses a finite state space and takes strict preference as primitive, leading to some differences in axioms and results. In particular, must be strictly better than under all priors to be strictly preferred to, andallpriors Π must have full support; thus, this paper s model is not embedded. Stoye (2011a) axiomatizes a ranking that resembles % in not using priors but resembles Bewley s in that strict preference requires everywhere strict dominance. In addition, the ranking is complete; loosely speaking, noncomparabilities are replaced with indifferences, and this is axiomatized by relaxing transitivity. 4

3 Extension to Choice Correspondences A revealed preference perspective suggests choices as primitive objects of analysis because they are directly observable. Thus, consider a choice correspondence that maps finite menus F onto nonempty choice sets ( ) and consider imposing axioms on rather than %. Well known consistency conditions for are: WARP (Arrow (1959) 4 ) ( ) { ( ) } for all menus. Property α (Chernoff (1954), Sen (1969)) ( ) ( ) for all menus. Imposing WARP would lead to an immediate dualism between choice and preference (Arrow (1959)): Define the preference revealed by as D if ({ }) and the choice correspondence induced by a preference relation D as D ( ) ={ : D }, thenwarp implies that D is transitive and that D =. This all fails here: The in (2) fulfils property (which is listed for subsequent use) but fails WARP, D is intransitive, and %6=D %. To characterize anyway, one needs the following axioms. C.1: Admissibility If and ({ ( ) ( )}) for all, then ( ) ( ). C.2: Strict Admissibility If, ({ ( ) ( )}) for all, and ({ ( ) ( )}) ={ ( )} for some, then ( ). C.3: Weak Axiom of Revealed Non-Inferiority (WARNI; Bandhyopadhay and Sengupta (1993), Eliaz and Ok (2006)) Say that globally blocks if ( ) for all. Then for all, ( ) implies that some ( ) globally blocks. C.4: Independence ( +(1 ) ) = ( )+(1 ) for all menus, acts, and scalars (0 1), where +(1 ) = { F : = +(1 ) } C.5: Continuity If ({ }) ={ } and ({ }) ={ }, thenthereexists (0 1) with ({ +(1 ) }) = { +(1 ) }. 4 I avoid Arrow s label ( Independence of Irrelevant Alternatives ) for terminological consistency with WARNI and to avoid confusion with social choice theory. 5

C.6: Nontriviality There exists s.t. ( ) 6=. C.7: Symmetry Fix any menu and disjoint, nonempty events Σ s.t. any is constant on as well as.define 0 as before. Then ( ) 0 ({ 0 : }) Axioms C.4-7 much resemble P.4-7. Weakening continuity in analogy to axiom P.5 is now crucial because is not upper hemicontinuous, and D fails all standard continuity axioms. Axioms C.1-3 are less similar to P.1-3 because it is intricate to choice theoretically distinguish indifference from noncomparability. For example, D conflates the two, rendering it complete yet intransitive. Indeed, the strengthening of monotonicity in axiom C.2 compensates for an inability to directly impose transitivity; it is this axiom (and not transitivity as before) that eliminates the prior-less version of Bewley s (2002) model. Note also that (as shown in the proof) axioms C.1 and C.3 jointly imply WARP for constant acts and that WARNI is easily verified to imply property. This section s technical result is as follows. 5 Theorem 2 fulfils axioms C.1-6 iff it can be written as in (2), with % as in theorem 1. Proof. Initially restrict attention to menus of constant acts X. Then WARP is implied: For any X, ( ) ( ) by the property implication of WARNI. If ( ) { ( ) }, then there exist ( ) and ( ) ( ). Property applied to ( ) yields ({ }) ={ }, contradicting axiom C.1 applied to. Combining Arrow (1959) and Herstein and Milnor (1953), it now follows that is rationalized by expected utility maximization. On the general domain, let  if ({ }) ={ }. Then rationalizes in the sense of (2). To see this, fix any menu and act. If ( ), thensome ( ) globally blocks. The definition of global blocking then implies Â. If ( ), then  for no because any such would block globally and, therefore, in. Next,  is transitive: Let ({ }) ={ } and ({ }) ={ }, then ({ }) ={ } by WARNI (both and are globally blocked), thus globally blocks, thus ({ }) ={ }. The following claims are then easily shown by mimicking the preceding proof (whose notation is freely used): Utility acts constitute equivalence classes; one 5 Taking revealed preference really seriously, one might remark that in many applications including statistical decision theory, agents can randomize, thus one cannot observe choice from finite menus but only from the corresponding mixture sets, which here coincide with their convex hulls. The directly revealed preference might then be even more incomplete than true preference, namely if % yet choice from the convex hull { } is a proper mixture of the two. In general, this leads to substantial complications (Stoye (2011b) and references therein). These do not arise here because if +(1 ) ( { }), then +(1 ) ( { +(1 ) }) by the property implication of WARNI, thus ( { }) by independence. 6

can proceed as if the range of were unbounded; and  ª  0. Consider now any act that takes at least three different utility values, then   by strict admissibility. Transitivity then yields  0  0 and  0  0, while symmetry yields  0  0  0. Hence, attention can be restricted to acts of form as before. The last part of the previous proof can then be mimicked to show that min S ( ) 0 is necessary for  0 ; on the other hand, min S ( ) 0 and 6= 0 is sufficient by axiom C.2. References [1] Anscombe, F.J., Aumann, R.J., 1963. A definition of subjective probability, Annals of Mathematical Statistics, 34, 199-205. [2] Arrow, K.J., 1959. Rational choice functions and orderings, Economica, 26, 121-127. [3] Arrow, K.J., Hurwicz, L., 1972. An optimality criterion for decision-making under ignorance, in Carter, C.F., Ford, J.L. (eds.), Uncertainty and Expectations in Economics: Essays in Honour of G.L.S. Shackle. Oxford: Basil Blackwell. [4] Aumann, R.J., 1962. Utility theory without the completeness axiom, Econometrica, 30, 445-462. [5] Bandyhopadhay, T., Sengupta, K., 2003. Characterization of generalized weak orders and revealed preference, Economic Theory, 3, 571-576. [6] Bewley, T.F., 2002. Knightian decision theory. Part I, Decisions in Economics and Finance, 25, 79-110. [7] Chernoff, H., 1954. Rational selection of decision functions, Econometrica, 22, 422-443. [8] Eliaz, K., Ok, E.A., 2006. Indifference or indecisiveness? Choice-theoretic foundations of incomplete preferences, Games and Economic Behavior, 56, 61-86. [9] Ferguson, T.S., 1967. Mathematical statistics: A decision theoretic approach. New York: Wiley. [10] Gilboa, I., Maccheroni, F., Marinacchi, M., Schmeidler, D., 2010. Objective and subjective rationality in a multiple prior model, Econometrica, 78, 755 770. [11] Herstein, I.N., Milnor, J., 1953. An axiomatic approach to measurable utility, Econometrica, 21, 291-297. [12] Sen, A.K., 1969. Quasi-transitivity, rational choice and collective decisions, Review of Economic Studies, 36, 381-393. [13] Stoye, J., 2011a. Statistical decisions under ambiguity. Theory and Decision, 70, 129-148. [14], 2011b. New perspectives on statistical decisions under ambiguity. Discussion paper, Cornell University. 7