Gleason s Theorem for non-separable Hilbert spaces: Extended abstract

Similar documents
REU 2007 Transfinite Combinatorics Lecture 9

MATH 3300 Test 1. Name: Student Id:

The Measure Problem. Louis de Branges Department of Mathematics Purdue University West Lafayette, IN , USA

Classical Theory of Cardinal Characteristics

Trees and generic absoluteness

Exercises for Unit VI (Infinite constructions in set theory)

Lecture 5: Peak sets for operator algebras and quantum cardinals. David Blecher. December 2016

Measurability Problems for Boolean Algebras

Basic set-theoretic techniques in logic Part III, Transfinite recursion and induction

Measure and Integration: Concepts, Examples and Exercises. INDER K. RANA Indian Institute of Technology Bombay India

Cantor and sets: La diagonale du fou

VARIATIONS FOR SEPARATING CLUB GUESSING PRINCIPLES

SHELAH S SINGULAR COMPACTNESS THEOREM

ON A QUESTION OF SIERPIŃSKI

Jónsson posets and unary Jónsson algebras

On the Length of Borel Hierarchies

On the Length of Borel Hierarchies

Unsolvable problems, the Continuum Hypothesis, and the nature of infinity

DO FIVE OUT OF SIX ON EACH SET PROBLEM SET

Topology Proceedings. COPYRIGHT c by Topology Proceedings. All rights reserved.

INCOMPLETENESS I by Harvey M. Friedman Distinguished University Professor Mathematics, Philosophy, Computer Science Ohio State University Invitation

INSEPARABLE SEQUENCES AND FORCING

Quantum measure theory, quantum cardinals, and noncommutative Hardy spaces. David Blecher. December 2016

20 Ordinals. Definition A set α is an ordinal iff: (i) α is transitive; and. (ii) α is linearly ordered by. Example 20.2.

Set Theory and the Foundation of Mathematics. June 19, 2018

Chapter 4. Measure Theory. 1. Measure Spaces

INTRODUCTION TO CARDINAL NUMBERS

A version of for which ZFC can not predict a single bit Robert M. Solovay May 16, Introduction In [2], Chaitin introd

Ultrafilters with property (s)

Extremely large cardinals in the absence of Choice

The cardinal comparison of sets

Part II. Logic and Set Theory. Year

Foundations of non-commutative probability theory

Two sets X, Y have the same cardinality (cardinal number, cardinal),

The Continuum Hypothesis, Part II

ON THE EXISTENCE OF PRIME IDEALS IN BOOLEAN ALGEBRAS

Chapter 8. General Countably Additive Set Functions. 8.1 Hahn Decomposition Theorem

arxiv: v1 [math.lo] 7 Dec 2017

MATHEMATICS: CONCEPTS, AND FOUNDATIONS Vol. II - Model Theory - H. Jerome Keisler

Section 7.5: Cardinality

Generalizing Gödel s Constructible Universe:

SPACES WHOSE PSEUDOCOMPACT SUBSPACES ARE CLOSED SUBSETS. Alan Dow, Jack R. Porter, R.M. Stephenson, Jr., and R. Grant Woods

TEST GROUPS FOR WHITEHEAD GROUPS

A Note on Singular Cardinals in Set Theory without Choice

MATH & MATH FUNCTIONS OF A REAL VARIABLE EXERCISES FALL 2015 & SPRING Scientia Imperii Decus et Tutamen 1

AN EXTENSION OF THE PROBABILITY LOGIC LP P 2. Tatjana Stojanović 1, Ana Kaplarević-Mališić 1 and Zoran Ognjanović 2

3 COUNTABILITY AND CONNECTEDNESS AXIOMS

Functions and cardinality (solutions) sections A and F TA: Clive Newstead 6 th May 2014

The Countable Henkin Principle

The modal logic of forcing

Formal Epistemology: Lecture Notes. Horacio Arló-Costa Carnegie Mellon University

FORCING WITH SEQUENCES OF MODELS OF TWO TYPES

Measurable Envelopes, Hausdorff Measures and Sierpiński Sets

The axiom of choice and two-point sets in the plane

Basic Measure and Integration Theory. Michael L. Carroll

A CONVERSATION BETWEEN MODEL THEORY AND GRAPH THEORY

The Axiom of Choice and Zorn s Lemma

Chain Conditions of Horn and Tarski

SOME TRANSFINITE INDUCTION DEDUCTIONS

WHY ISN T THE CONTINUUM PROBLEM ON THE MILLENNIUM ($1,000,000) PRIZE LIST?

Lusin sequences under CH and under Martin s Axiom

S. Mrówka introduced a topological space ψ whose underlying set is the. natural numbers together with an infinite maximal almost disjoint family(madf)

1 Introduction. Math Sci Net numbers(msc2000) Primary = 06-02; Secondary = 06A05, 28A12, 54F05 draft of

Non-Elementary Classes 2007

Tallness and Level by Level Equivalence and Inequivalence

PROBLEMS FROM THE GALWAY TOPOLOGY COLLOQUIUM

Non-conglomerability for countably additive measures that are not -additive* Mark Schervish, Teddy Seidenfeld, and Joseph Kadane CMU

1.1. MEASURES AND INTEGRALS

From Constructibility and Absoluteness to Computability and Domain Independence

INDEPENDENCE OF THE CONTINUUM HYPOTHESIS

AMS regional meeting Bloomington, IN April 1, 2017

Absolutely ordinal definable sets

This is logically equivalent to the conjunction of the positive assertion Minimal Arithmetic and Representability

Open access to the SEP is made possible by a world-wide funding initiative. Please Read How You Can Help Keep the Encyclopedia Free

Chapter 1 : The language of mathematics.

Topological Test Spaces 1 Alexander Wilce Department of Mathematical Sciences, Susquehanna University Selinsgrove, Pa

FINITE BOREL MEASURES ON SPACES OF CARDINALITY LESS THAN c

3. (a) What is a simple function? What is an integrable function? How is f dµ defined? Define it first

The Ultrapower Axiom implies GCH above a supercompact cardinal

Math 396. Bijectivity vs. isomorphism

Discrete Mathematics. W. Ethan Duckworth. Fall 2017, Loyola University Maryland

Forcing Axioms and Inner Models of Set Theory

Axioms of separation

1.4 Outer measures 10 CHAPTER 1. MEASURE

Combinatorial dichotomies and cardinal invariants

INFINITY: CARDINAL NUMBERS

Non- conglomerability for countably additive measures that are not κ- additive* T.Seidenfeld, M.J.Schervish, and J.B.Kadane

The constructible universe

Lebesgue measure on R is just one of many important measures in mathematics. In these notes we introduce the general framework for measures.

THE CLOSED-POINT ZARISKI TOPOLOGY FOR IRREDUCIBLE REPRESENTATIONS. K. R. Goodearl and E. S. Letzter

Description of the book Set Theory

Huan Long Shanghai Jiao Tong University

SETS AND FUNCTIONS JOSHUA BALLEW

Maximal perpendicularity in certain Abelian groups

Finite Quantum Measure Spaces

Lebesgue-Radon-Nikodym Theorem

CITS2211 Discrete Structures (2017) Cardinality and Countability

The Two Faces of Infinity Dr. Bob Gardner Great Ideas in Science (BIOL 3018)

SELF-DUAL UNIFORM MATROIDS ON INFINITE SETS

Stat 451: Solutions to Assignment #1

Transcription:

Gleason s Theorem for non-separable Hilbert spaces: Extended abstract R. M. Solovay May 2, 2009 1 Introduction: Statement of Results The probelm of generalizing Gleason s theorem to the non separable case arose in correspondence with Paul Chernoff. I am very grateful to him for suggesting this charming problem to me. Let H be a Hilbert space. The coefficient field K of H can be either the reals or the complexes. We let P(H) denote the collection of all closed subspaces of H. A Gleason measure on H is a map µ : P(H) [0, 1] satisfying the following conditions: µ({0}) = 0; µ(h) = 1. Let M i i ω be a pairwise orthogonal sequence of subspaces of H with sum M. Then µ(m) = µ(m i ) We follow the general convention that if M [possibly decorated with subscripts or superscripts] is a closed subspace of H then P [with the same decoration] is the corresponding projection. One way to get such a Gleason measure is as follows. Let A be a positive self-adjoint trace class operator whose trace is 1. Set i=0 µ(m) = trace(ap) (1) Then µ is easily checked to be a Gleason measure. In [2] the following remarkable theorem is proved: 1

Theorem 1.1 (Gleason). Let H be separable and of dimension unequal to 2. Then every Gleason measure arises from precisely one positive self-adjoint operator, A, of trace 1 in the manner just described. As Gleason remarks in [2], the restrictions to dimensions other than 2 is essential to the validity of the theorem. In this paper, we completely analyze the generalization of Gleason s theorem to non-separable Hilbert spaces. We find that the naive generalization is false, but that a more refined generalization is valid. Before stating our precise results we need some preliminary definitions. Let X be a set. Then a measure on X is a map ν from the power set of X, P(X), to the interval [0, 1] such that: ν( ) = 0; ν(x) = 1. if A i i ω is a pairwise disjoint sequence of subsets of X with union A, then ν(a) = ν(a i ) The reader should note the analogy with our definition of a Gleasom measure. Note also, that contrary to the usual definitions in analysis, we require that our measure be defined on every subset of X. A measure ν is continuous if it vanishes on one point sets. It is a consequence of Gödel s theorem that one cannot prove from the usual axioms of set-theory that there are continuous measures. Whether or not a set X carries a continuous measure clearly depends only on the cardinality of X. A cardinal κ is real-valued measurable if there is a continuous measure ν defined on all the subsets of κ which is κ-additive in the sense that the union of fewer than κ sets of ν-measure zero again has ν-measure zero. It is a standard and easy fact that the existence of a real-valued measurable cardinal is equivalent to the existence of a continuous measure. Moreover the least cardinal to support a continuous measure is a real-valued measurable cardinal. Definition 1.2. A Gleason measure is exotic if it does not arise from a positive trace class operator of trace 1 (in the manner described above). Theorem 1.3. Let H be a non-separable Hilbert space of dimension λ. Then the following are equivalent: 2 i=0

There is a real-valued measurable cardinal κ with κ λ. There is an exotic Gleason measure on H. Hence the following are equivalent: There is a real-valued measurable cardinal. There is an exotic Gleason measure. Remark: This theorem is independently due to Dvurecenskij [1]. 1.1 Our main theorem describes how to construct all the Gleason measures on a non-separable Hilbert space. (The analogous result for separable Hilbert spaces of dimension unequal to 2 follows from Theorem 1.1.) We also have a result which gives a complete system of invariants for a Gleason measure which we formulate in section 1.5. Let H be a non-separable Hilbert space and let Y be an orthonormal basis of H. Let µ be a measure on Y. To the data Y and µ we shall associate a Gleason measure ν on H as follows. Let M be a closed subspace of H, and let P be the projection associated to M. Then ν(m) = (Py, y) dµ(y) (2) Y Theorem 1.4 (Main Theorem). Let H be a non-separable Hilbert space and let ν be a Gleason measure on H. Then there is an orthonormal basis Y of H, and a measure µ on Y such that ν is defined from this data as in equation 2. The proof of the main theorem involves a substantial amount of set theory. We do wish to emphasize that all our results are provable in ZFC and that they do not require any extra large cardinal hypotheses. Here is a very brief outline of how the proof of our main theorem proceeds. We are given a Gleason measure ν on a non-separable Hilbert space H. From ν we shall define [in a non-canonical fashion] an ordinary measure µ 0 [defined on the subsets of X 0 say] with a technical property called purity. Let B be the measure algebra of the measure µ 0. In the Boolean valued universe, V B, we define a Gleason measure, ν 1, on the Hilbert space l 2. In V B all the theorems of ZFC are available. In particular we can apply the usual version of Gleason s theorem to ν 1 getting a positive trace class operator of trace 1 in V B, A 1. 3

We now apply the machinery of Boolean valued ultraproducts. A 1 determines a map from X 0 to the trace class operators on l 2 back in V. With a little massaging, this gives a map from X 0 to the trace class operators on H. Let this final map be noted x A x. For M a closed subspace of H let P be the corresponding projection. It will turn out that we have the integral representation: ν(m) = trace(pa x ) dµ 0 (x) (3) X 0 However the proof of the validity of this representation requires a delicate argument. 1.2 Exotic Gleason measures In this section, we briefly list some consequences of Theorem 1.3. 1.2.1 First some applications of Gödel s theorems: 1. If ZFC is consistent, then ZFC does not prove the existence of an exotic Gleason measure. 2. If ZFC is arithmetically sound [i.e. ZFC proves no false arithmetic statement] then ZFC does not prove the assertion: If ZFC is consistent, then so is the theory ZFC + There is an exotic Gleason measure. 1.2.2 To get the consistency of the existence of an exotic Gleason measure we need a strong large cardinal consistency assertion. Suppose then that the theory ZFC + There is a measurable cardinal is consistent. Then the following assertions are consistent with ZFC: 1. There is an exotic Gleason measure on a Hilbert space of dimension c = 2 ℵ 0. 2. The continuum hypothesis holds but there is an exotic Gleason measure on a Hilbert space of strongly inaccessible dimension. 1.3 Finally, the following results say that the dimension of a Hilbert space that carries an exotic Gleason measure must be very large. We shall need the notation of the ℶ α s: 4

1. ℶ 0 = ℵ 0 ; 2. ℶ α+1 = 2 ℶα ; 3. For λ a limit ordinal ℶ λ = sup{ℶ α α < λ}. Then we have the following results: 1. If there is an exotic Gleason measure on a Hilbert space of dimension at most c then there is a weakly inaccessible cardinal less than c. In particular c is greater than the least κ such that κ = ℵ κ. 2. Suppose that there is no exotic Gleason measure on any space of dimension at most c. [By the preceding remark, this holds if the continuum hypothesis is true, or even if c is at most the least κ such that κ = ℵ κ.] Then if a Hilbert space H supports an exotic Gleason measure, its dimension is at least as large as the first strongly inaccessible cardinal. In particular, it is larger than the least κ such that κ = ℶ κ. 1.4 Purity If f is a function and A is a subset of its domain then we let f[a] denote the direct image: f[a] = {f(x) x A} Let µ be a measure on the set X. A partial equivalence f for µ is a function such that: 1. f has domain a subset A of X. 2. f has range a subset B of X. 3. f is a bijection. 4. Let A be any subset of A and let B = f[a ]. Then µ(a ) = 0 iff µ(b ) = 0. A partial equivalence f is trivial if for almost all x in its domain f(x) = x. The measure µ is pure if every partial equivalence f for µ is trivial. 5

1.5 Uniqueness The purpose of this section is to give a different integral representation of a Gleason measure for which we will be able to provide a canonical choice. Let H be a Hilbert space whose dimension is uncountable. Let T be the set of positive trace class operators on H of trace 1. Suppose now that µ is a measure on T. Then we associate to µ a Gleason measure on H by the following prescription: ν(m) = trace(pa) dµ(a) (4) T Theorem 1.5. Every Gleason measure on H arises from a measure on T in this way. If A T, then the support of A is the orthogonal complement of the nullspace of A. The support of A is a subspace of H of at most countable dimension. If µ is a measure on T we say that µ is separated if there is a set Y of µ measure 1 such that if A 1 and A 2 are distinct members of Y then the supports of A 1 and A 2 are orthogonal. Theorem 1.6 (Uniqueness). If ν is a Gleason measure on H, then ν arises from precisely one pure separated measure on T by the prescription of 4. 1.6 Comments 1. The theorems announced in this abstract have been in my desk drawer for some time. For example, I talked about these results at U. C. L. A. in May 1992. 2. This abstract has been extracted (at the request of Paul Chernoff) from an incomplete draft of a manuscript which will eventually present complete proofs of the results referred to. References [1] A. Dvurecenskij. Gleason s Theorem and Its Applications. Kluwer Academic Publishers, 1993. 6

[2] A. M. Gleason. Measures on the closed subspaces of a Hilbert space. Journal of Mathematics and Mechanics, 6:885 893, 1957. [3] Robert M. Solovay. Real-valued measurable cardinals. In Dana S. Scott, editor, Axiomatic Set Theory, volume XIII, Part I of Proceedings of Symposia In Pure Mathematics, pages 397 428, Providence, Rhode Island, 1971. American Mathematical Society. [4] S. Ulam. Zur masstheorie in der allgemeinen mengenlehre. Fund. Math., 16:140 150, 1930. 7