Almost Transferable Utility, Changes in Production Possibilities, and the Nash Bargaining and the Kalai-Smorodinsky Solutions

Similar documents
SHARE THE GAIN, SHARE THE PAIN? ALMOST TRANSFERABLE UTILITY, CHANGES IN PRODUCTION POSSIBILITIES, AND BARGAINING SOLUTIONS *

Share the Gain, Share the Pain? Almost Transferable Utility, Changes in Production Possibilities and Bargaining Solutions

Game Theory. Bargaining Theory. ordi Massó. International Doctorate in Economic Analysis (IDEA) Universitat Autònoma de Barcelona (UAB)

Axiomatic bargaining. theory

Adding an Apple to an Orange: A General Equilibrium Approach to Aggregation of Beliefs

Nash Bargaining Theory with Non-Convexity and Unique Solution

Lecture Notes on Bargaining

ECONOMICS SERIES SWP 2009/16. Weakest Collective Rationality and the Nash Bargaining Solution. Nejat Anbarci and Ching-jen Sun

econstor Make Your Publications Visible.

Stagnation proofness and individually monotonic bargaining solutions. Jaume García-Segarra Miguel Ginés-Vilar 2013 / 04

The B.E. Journal of Theoretical Economics

Banks, depositors and liquidity shocks: long term vs short term interest rates in a model of adverse selection

Background notes on bargaining

Unique Nash Implementation for a Class of Bargaining Solutions

Can everyone benefit from innovation?

1 Uncertainty. These notes correspond to chapter 2 of Jehle and Reny.

Lecture 3 - Axioms of Consumer Preference and the Theory of Choice

Advanced Microeconomics I: Consumers, Firms and Markets Chapters 1+2

Ph.D. Preliminary Examination MICROECONOMIC THEORY Applied Economics Graduate Program June 2016

The Interdisciplinary Center, Herzliya School of Economics Advanced Microeconomics Fall Bargaining The Axiomatic Approach

Bargaining Efficiency and the Repeated Prisoners Dilemma. Bhaskar Chakravorti* and John Conley**

Endogenous timing in a mixed duopoly

Equity in Production Economies with Dedicated Factors. Laurence Kranich Department of Economics University at Albany

Lecture 8: Basic convex analysis

Risk Aversion over Incomes and Risk Aversion over Commodities. By Juan E. Martinez-Legaz and John K.-H. Quah 1

Learning and Risk Aversion

Second Welfare Theorem

Implementing the Nash Extension Bargaining Solution for Non-convex Problems. John P. Conley* and Simon Wilkie**

Achieving Efficiency with Manipulative Bargainers

Nash Bargaining Theory with Non-Convexity and Unique Solution

Advanced Microeconomics Problem Set 1

The Consumer, the Firm, and an Economy

Differentiable Welfare Theorems Existence of a Competitive Equilibrium: Preliminaries

Volume 30, Issue 3. Monotone comparative statics with separable objective functions. Christian Ewerhart University of Zurich

Nonlinear Programming (NLP)

Randomized dictatorship and the Kalai-Smorodinsky bargaining solution

SURPLUS SHARING WITH A TWO-STAGE MECHANISM. By Todd R. Kaplan and David Wettstein 1. Ben-Gurion University of the Negev, Israel. 1.

Nash Demand Game and the Kalai-Smorodinsky Solution

Advanced Microeconomics

No-envy in Queueing Problems

The Non-Existence of Representative Agents

Introduction to General Equilibrium: Framework.

Microeconomics, Block I Part 2

Economic Growth: Lecture 8, Overlapping Generations

Labor Economics, Lecture 11: Partial Equilibrium Sequential Search

Microeconomics II. MOSEC, LUISS Guido Carli Problem Set n 3

Advanced Microeconomics

Advanced Microeconomics

ANSWER KEY. University of California, Davis Date: June 22, 2015

Some Notes on Adverse Selection

The Coordinate-Wise Core for Multiple-Type Housing Markets is Second-Best Incentive Compatible

On the Non-Symmetric Nash and Kalai Smorodinsky Bargaining Solutions. Yigal Gerchak

Relative Benefit Equilibrating Bargaining Solution and the Ordinal Interpretation of Gauthier s Arbitration Scheme

Welfare Egalitarianism under Uncertainty

Notes on Mechanism Designy

UNIVERSITY OF NOTTINGHAM. Discussion Papers in Economics WEAK LINKS, GOOD SHOTS AND OTHER PUBLIC GOOD GAMES: BUILDING ON BBV

AGGREGATIVE PUBLIC GOOD GAMES

1 Axiomatic Bargaining Theory

Mathematical Social Sciences

Contracts under Asymmetric Information

Cooperative bargaining: independence and monotonicity imply disagreement

TWO-PERSON COOPERATIVE GAMES

Merging and splitting in cooperative games: some (im-)possibility results

Nash Bargaining in Ordinal Environments

IMPOSSIBILITY OF A WALRASIAN BARGAINING SOLUTION 1

Duality. for The New Palgrave Dictionary of Economics, 2nd ed. Lawrence E. Blume

Intro to Economic analysis

On the meaning of the Nash product. Walter Trockel

ECON2285: Mathematical Economics

Microeconomic Theory-I Washington State University Midterm Exam #1 - Answer key. Fall 2016

Applied cooperative game theory:

Week of May 5, lecture 1: Expected utility theory

Lecture 1. History of general equilibrium theory

Appendix II Testing for consistency

NOTES ON COOPERATIVE GAME THEORY AND THE CORE. 1. Introduction

CENTER FOR INTERNATIONAL ECONOMICS. Working Paper Series. Working Paper No On unication of solutions to the bargaining problem

Market Equilibrium and the Core

Economics 201B Economic Theory (Spring 2017) Bargaining. Topics: the axiomatic approach (OR 15) and the strategic approach (OR 7).

General Equilibrium and Welfare

Mean-Variance Utility

The Kuhn-Tucker Problem

Risk & Sustainable Management Group

EconS Microeconomic Theory II Homework #9 - Answer key

1 Uncertainty and Insurance

Randomized Household Labor Supply

Rationality and solutions to nonconvex bargaining problems: rationalizability and Nash solutions 1

Gi en Demand for Several Goods

CORVINUS ECONOMICS WORKING PAPERS. Young's axiomatization of the Shapley value - a new proof. by Miklós Pintér CEWP 7/2015

The collective model of household consumption: a nonparametric characterization

Nash Bargaining for Log-Convex Problems

Implementation of the Ordinal Shapley Value for a three-agent economy 1

Positive Models of Private Provision of Public Goods: A Static Model. (Bergstrom, Blume and Varian 1986)

First Welfare Theorem

Efficiency, Fairness and Competitiveness in Nash Bargaining Games

Manipulation of Preferences and Relative Utilitarianism

Ph.D. Preliminary Examination MICROECONOMIC THEORY Applied Economics Graduate Program May 2012

Lecture notes on Bargaining and the Nash Program

E ciency in Coalition Games with Externalities

Department of Economics The Ohio State University Final Exam Questions and Answers Econ 8712

Microeconomic Theory -1- Introduction

Transcription:

Department Discussion Paper DDP0702 ISSN 1914-2838 Department of Economics Almost Transferable Utility, Changes in Production Possibilities, and the Nash Bargaining and the Kalai-Smorodinsky Solutions Elisabeth Gugl Department of Economics, University of Victoria Victoria, B.C., Canada V8W 2Y2 Abstract August, 2007 Consider a two-person economy in which allocative efficiency is independent of distribution but cardinality of the agents utility functions precludes transferable utility. I show that both agents either benefit or lose with any change of production possibilities under the Nash Bargaining and the Kalai-Smorodinsky solutions. Keywords: JEL Classifications: Axiomatic bargaining, resource monotonicity, transferable utility, risk aversion C71, D13, D63 I thank Nick Baigent, Craig Brett, Hervé Moulin, David Scoones and Linda Welling for their helpful comments. Author Contact: Elisabeth Gugl, Dept. of Economics, University of Victoria, P.O. Box 1700, STN CSC, Victoria, B.C., Canada V8W 2Y2; e-mail: egugl@uvic.ca; Phone: (250) 721-8538; FAX: (250) 721-6214 1

1 Introduction An expansion of the utility possibility set (UPS) due to an increase in one of many goods in a two-person economy does not in general increase both agents utilities under the Nash Bargaining solution (NBS) or the Kalai-Smorodinsky solution (KSS) (Chun and Thomson, 1988). If, however, utility is transferable, both agents bene t with an increase in one of many goods in a two-person economy under NBS or KSS (Bergstrom, 1989). Bergstrom (1989, p.1147) de nes transferable utility (TU) as the requirement that any redistribution of utilities among agents along the utility possibility frontier (UPF) leads to a utility vector that sums up to the same constant as the sum of utilities did before the redistribution. A necessary condition for TU is that allocative e ciency must be independent of the distribution of welfare. 1 I show that in a two-person economy with an arbitrary number of goods produced, any change in the production possibility set (PPS) impacts both agents utilities in the same direction under the NBS or the KSS, if agents preferences are such that allocative e ciency is independent of distribution of welfare but agents utility functions do not yield TU. That means I consider utility functions that share the ordinal characteristics with utility functions that lead to TU. For example, if agents are strictly risk averse the cardinality of their utility functions precludes TU. Cardinality of agents utility functions also matters in welfare economics because bargaining solutions and the maximization of social welfare functions typically lead to di erent consumption bundles for individuals depending on which cardinal representation of their ordinal preferences are used. 2 The next section introduces the model, section 3 presents the main result, and section 4 concludes and discusses applications of my result. 2 The Model Two agents, Ava (i = A) and Bob (i = B), produce l 2 goods to consume. The PPS is given by Y, where Y 2 R l + is a convex set. The consumption bundle of agent i is denoted by x i. The set of feasible consumption bundles of the two agents is given by X. It contains at least one private good and may contain public goods and it is constrained by Y. Ava s utility function is given by u A (x A ), and Bob s utility function is given by 1 Preferences must allow the indirect utility representation of the Gorman Polar Form in an economy with only private goods (Bergstrom and Varian, 1985) and a form dual to the Gorman Polar form in an economy with public and private goods (Bergstrom and Cornes, 1981, 1983). 2 In the context of bargaining solutions, Nash (1950) explicitly states that agents have von Neumann-Morgenstern utility functions. In Rubinstein et al. (1992) s restatement of the Nash Bargaining problem in terms of preferences, choice under uncertainty plays an essential role. However, Kalai and Smorodinsky (1975) do not mention that utility functions are of the von Neumann-Morgenstern type, and neither do textbooks when they introduce the Nash bargaining problem (e.g., Moulin, 1988; MasColell et al., 1995). 2

u B (x B ). Agents utility functions are assumed to be continuous, concave and twice di erentiable. De nition 1 Let function f i (:) be increasing, twice di erentiable and convex. There is almost transferable utility if agents preferences are such that the utility possibility set is given by the convex set U = f(u A ; u B ) 2 R 2 : f A (u A ) + f B (u B ) g for all Y and where is a constant. In what follows I assume that the assumption of almost TU is satis ed. Note that for any Y, resource and technological constraints only play a role in the size of, but f A (u A ) + f B (u B ) are independent of these constraints. 3 De nition 2 Bargaining solutions. Let d = (d A ; d B ) be the threatpoint in the bargaining problem, where d 2 U, and f A (d A ) + f B (d B ) <. (i) The Nash bargaining solution is the unique utility vector u N that maximizes (u A d A )(u B d B ) s.t. f A (u A )+f B (u B ) =. (ii) Let u A (u B ) be the highest utility Ava (Bob) receives if Bob (Ava) receives d B (d A ). The Kalai-Smorodinsky solution is the unique utility vector u K that equalizes relative utility gains: (u A d A )=(u A d A ) = (u B d B )=(u B d B ) and f A (u A ) + f B (u B ) =. 3 Results Let v i (x i ) = f i (u i (x i )), that is, v i (x i ) is a monotonic transformation of u i (x i ). Allocative e ciency is given by max xa ;x B v A (x A ) + v B (x B ) s.t. (x A ; x B ) 2 X (Y ) (Bergstrom and Cornes, 1983 and Bergstrom and Varian, 1985). 4 Lemma (UPS expansion and contraction): Given almost TU, any change in production possibilities of the economy results in an expansion or contraction of the UPS. Proof. With almost TU, a change in the production possibility set Y and therefore a change in X can only impact. Since = max xa ;x B v A (x A) +v B (x B ) s.t. (x A ; x B ) 2 X(Y ), increases or decreases with a change in Y. Hence the old UPS is either entirely contained in the new UPS or the new UPS is entirely contained in the old UPS. Proposition Under the NBS or KSS, any change in production possibilities either bene ts both agents or makes both agents worse o if and only if agents utility functions yield almost TU. 3 For example preferences yielding a utility possibility frontier given by U = f(u A ; u B ) 2 R 2 : B u A + A u B = A B g, where i is equal to the highest utility of agent i if she receives all the resources available, violate the assumption, even if for a particular Y, A = B. 4 Since allocative e ciency is a purely ordinal concept, maximizing v A (x A )+v B (x B ) subject to technological and resource constraints leads to an e cient allocation. 3

Proof. For su ciency, Chun and Thomson (1988) show that if agents have concave utility functions over one good only, and this good s supply increases, both agents bene t under NBS and KSS. Express u i = f 1 i (v i ), where f 1 i (:) is a concave function. With this notation the NBS is found by max va;v B (f 1 A (v A) d A )(f 1 B (v B) d B ) s.t. v A + v B =, and the KSS by solving for v A and v B f given 1 A (v A) d A f = 1 f 1 B (v B) d B and v A ( f B(d B )) d A f 1 B ( f A(d A )) d A + v B =. Presented in this B way a change in plays the same role as a change in the only good provided in the one-good economy of Chun and Thomson (1988) and thus their proof applies. For completeness the proof is available on my webpage using the same notation as in this note and accounting for d 6= (0; 0) : 5 For necessity, note rst that if the UPS changes such that the old and the new UPF intersect, both NBS and KSS can lead to one agent being better o and the other agent being worse o. Figure 1 illustrates this case. 6 Second, I show that such a change in the UPS can be the result of a change in the PPS even if agents have identical utility functions, but allocative e ciency is not independent of distribution. Suppose Ava and Bob have well-behaved preferences over two private goods and the Inada conditions hold. Moreover, u (0; x i2 ) = u (x i1 ; 0) = 0 for all x i1 ; x i2 0: In order to nd the intercepts of the UPF, Ava s indi erence curve must be tangent to the production possibility frontier (PPF). See Figure 2, point A. If both agents have equal utility on the UPF, both agents must receive the same amount of both goods. Figure 2 shows that point A is not e cient if both agents receive equal utility, because Ava s marginal rate of substitution (MRS) when she receives half of the total amount of each good is not the same as the marginal rate of transformation (MRT) at point A. Thus changing the product mix by moving down along the PPF leads to another e cient allocation associated with the point on the UPF at which both agents have equal utility. In order to make the old and the new UPF intersect, now change the PPF so that point A is on the new PPF and has the same slope at point A as Ava s indi erence curve has if she receives half of the amounts of both goods. Point A on the new PPF is now the e cient allocation when Ava s and Bob s utility are equal. This implies that the point on the new UPF at which both agents enjoy equal utility lies inside the old UPS. This also means that the new PPF cuts the old PPF from above in point A and would therefore yield a new UPF with higher intercepts than the old PPF just like the two UPFs drawn in Figure 1. 3.1 Conclusion I focus on a class of agents preferences such that allocative e ciency is independent of distribution, a necessary condition for TU, but allow for agents to be 5 The result extends to n individuals under the class of bargaining solutions given by np max u1 ;:::;u n g i (u i d i ) s.t. np f i (u i ) = ; where g i is a concave function (Chun and i=1 i=1 Thomson, 1988). NBS is a special case of this class. 6 Figure 1 is drawn using KSS, but NBS leads to a qualitatively similar graph. 4

strictly risk averse or to have cardinal utility functions that preclude TU. Given this class of utility functions, for any change in the PPS the NBS and KSS will either increase or decrease both agents utilities. The Nash Bargaining solution has become increasingly important in the analysis of impacts of policy changes on intrafamily distribution. The results presented here establish under which conditions policy changes that lead to a change in production possibilities of a family change each family member s welfare in the same direction provided the threatpoint remains the same. The results are also useful for economists who combine elements of noncooperative behavior and cooperative bargaining in their models. For example, suppose agents have agreed to apply a bargaining solution to distribute goods once they are produced by agents actions in the economy, under what conditions do agents have an incentive to produce an e cient amount of goods? I show under what conditions on agents utility functions any change in production possibilities can only shrink or expand the UPS. Hence an expansion of the UPS is in everybody s best interest and agents actions, although chosen noncooperatively, will lead to Pareto e ciency. 7 4 Figures 7 Bergstrom (1989) is concerned with a similar question in the context of Gary Becker s Rotten Kid theorem. His results rely on TU. 5

Bob s utility Old UPF d New UPF Ava s utility Figure 1: Change in UPS makes Bob better off and Ava worse off. 6

Good 2 A: Efficient allocation at intercepts of UPF MRT flatter than MRS when u A =u B. PPF x A = 0 Edgeworth Box Figure 2 Good 1 5 References Bergstrom, Th. C., 1989, A Fresh Look at the Rotten Kid Theorem and Other Household Mysteries, Journal of Political Economy 97, 1138-59. Bergstrom, Th. C. and R. C. Cornes, 1983, Independence of Allocative E ciency from Distribution in the Theory of Public Goods, Econometrica 51, 1753-66. Bergstrom, Th. C. and R. C. Cornes, 1981, Gorman and Musgrave are Dual: An Antipodean Theorem on Public Goods, Economic Letters 7, 371-378. Bergstrom, Th. C. and H. R. Varian, 1985, When do market games have transferable utility? Journal of Economic Theory 35, 222-33. Chun, Y. and W. Thomson, 1988, Monotonicity Properties of Bargaining Solutions When Applied to Economics Mathematical Social Sciences 15, 11-27. Gugl, E., 2007, Proof of Su ciency of "Almost transferable utility, changes in production possibilities, and the Nash Bargaining and the Kalai-Smorodinsky 7

Solutions" webappendix, University of Victoria, http://web.uvic.ca/~egugl/almost TUapp.pdf. Kalai, E. and M. Smorodinsky, 1975, Other Solutions to Nash s Bargaining Problem, Econometrica 43, 513-18. Mas-Colell, A., M. D. Whinston and J. R. Green, 1995, Microeconomic Theory (Oxford University Press, New York). Moulin, H., 1988, Axioms of Cooperative Decision Making (Cambridge University Press, Cambridge). Nash, J. F. Jr., 1950, The Bargaining Problem, Econometrica 18, 155-62. Rubinstein, A., Z. Safra, and W. Thomson, 1992, On the Interpretation of the Nash Bargaining Solution and Its Extensions to Non-Expected Utility Preferences, Econometrica 60, 1171-81. 8