March 2, 2007 Menéndez-Benito. Quick Introduction to the Semantics of Modals 1

Similar documents
Modality: A Standard Analysis. Modality

Spring 2017 Ling 620. The Semantics of Modals, Part 3: The Ordering Source 1

Spring 2017 Ling 620. The Semantics of Modals, Part 2: The Modal Base 1

Intensional semantics: worlds, modals, conditionals

Spring 2018 Ling 620 The Semantics of Modals, Part 1: Basics of the Quantificational Analysis, and the Appearance of Ambiguity 1

Must... stay... strong!

At the center of our treatment of modality is the idea that modal operators effect quantification over possible worlds.

Singleton Indefinites (re. Schwarzschild 2000)

Intensionality. 1. Intensional Propositional Logic (IntPL).

Kripke on Frege on Sense and Reference. David Chalmers

Deontic Modality in Natural Language

Fox/Menendez-Benito 11/14/06. Wrapping up discussion on Kratzer 2005 (inconclusively!)

Hedging Your Ifs and Vice Versa

Semantics and Generative Grammar. Quantificational DPs, Part 3: Covert Movement vs. Type Shifting 1

The Semantics of Questions Introductory remarks

Kratzer on Modality in Natural Language

Semantics and Generative Grammar. An Introduction to Intensional Semantics 1

Spring 2018 Ling 620 The Basics of Intensional Semantics, Part 1: The Motivation for Intensions and How to Formalize Them 1

TEMPORAL AND CIRCUMSTANTIAL DEPENDENCE IN COUNTERFACTUAL MODALS. DORIT ABUSCH Department of Lingusitics Cornell University

Presuppositions (introductory comments)

The Puzzles of Deontic Logic

Spring 2017 Ling 620. An Introduction to the Semantics of Tense 1

Kaplan s Paradox and Epistemically Possible Worlds

Exhaustive interpretations: what to say and what not to say

Predicates, Quantifiers and Nested Quantifiers

A Note on the Good Samaritan Paradox and the Disquotation Theory of Propositional Content a

Spring 2017 Ling 620 Eliminating Res-Movement : An Introduction to Concept Generators

Spring 2018 Ling 620 Introduction to Semantics of Questions: Questions as Sets of Propositions (Hamblin 1973, Karttunen 1977)

Philosophy 244: Modal Logic Preliminaries

Relational semantics and domain semantics for epistemic modals

Modality. University of Massachusetts Amherst. From the SelectedWorks of Angelika Kratzer. Angelika Kratzer

Deriving indirectness and questioning entailment for epistemic must 1

Williamson s Modal Logic as Metaphysics

Seminar in Semantics: Gradation & Modality Winter 2014

Spring 2017 Ling 620 Conditionals as Modal Modifiers Conditional Constructions: Some Basic Terminology, Questions, and Assumptions

INTENSIONS MARCUS KRACHT

Counterfactual Attitudes and Assignment-Sensitivity

Meaning and Reference INTENSIONAL AND MODAL LOGIC. Intensional Logic. Frege: Predicators (general terms) have

Regularity analyses have failed; it is time to give up and try something else: a counterfactual analysis.

Module 7 D and Equivalent Systems

On the Deeply Contingent A Priori. David J. Chalmers

(An)Thony S. Gillies. Chicago Philosophy of Language/Semantics Workshop

CS1021. Why logic? Logic about inference or argument. Start from assumptions or axioms. Make deductions according to rules of reasoning.

Propositional Logic Truth-functionality Definitions Soundness Completeness Inferences. Modal Logic. Daniel Bonevac.

Introduction to Semantics. The Formalization of Meaning 1

Ling 98a: The Meaning of Negation (Week 5)

Michael Franke Fritz Hamm. January 26, 2011

Deliberative Modality under Epistemic Uncertainty

Handout 8: Bennett, Chapter 10

Philosophy 244: #14 Existence and Identity

Two Reconstruction Puzzles Yael Sharvit University of Connecticut

Indicative conditionals

Epistemic Modals and Informational Consequence

Philosophy 4310: Conditionals Spring 2017

An Invitation to Modal Logic: Lecture 1

Truth-Functional Logic

QUANTIFICATIONAL READINGS OF INDEFINITES

CL16, 12th September 2016

PHIL12A Section answers, 14 February 2011

Semantics and Generative Grammar. The Semantics of Adjectival Modification 1. (1) Our Current Assumptions Regarding Adjectives and Common Ns

Math 301: Matchings in Graphs

First-Degree Entailment

Is a Possible-Worlds Semantics of Modality Possible? A Problem for Kratzer s Semantics

Spring 2017 Ling 620 The Semantics of Control Infinitives: A First Introduction to De Se Attitudes

Evidence Sensitivity in Weak Necessity Deontic Modals *

Modality in Language

127: Lecture notes HT17. Week 8. (1) If Oswald didn t shoot Kennedy, someone else did. (2) If Oswald hadn t shot Kennedy, someone else would have.

Classical Menu of Pronouns

High and low readings in indicative donkeys 1 Andreas Walker University of Konstanz Maribel Romero University of Konstanz

Analyzing anankastic conditionals and sufficiency modals. Janneke Huitink

Comparative superlatives in relative clauses

Introduction to Semantics. Common Nouns and Adjectives in Predicate Position 1

Modal Subordination in Type Theoretic Dynamic Logic

Priority Structure in Deontic Logic

The problem Countable additivity Finite additivity Conglomerability Structure Puzzle. The Measure Problem. Alexander R. Pruss

A Way of Getting Rid of Things:

Uncertainty. Michael Peters December 27, 2013

Modal Logic. Introductory Lecture. Eric Pacuit. University of Maryland, College Park ai.stanford.edu/ epacuit. January 31, 2012.

Semantics Basics for Syntacticians

CS206 Lecture 21. Modal Logic. Plan for Lecture 21. Possible World Semantics

Five Problems for Quantificational Semantics for Deontic and Bouletic Modality

Kripke and Two-Dimensionalism. David Chalmers

Semantics and Generative Grammar. Formal Foundations: A Basic Review of Sets and Functions 1

Partial Implication Semantics for Desirable Propositions

Barriers to Inference

about conditionals. It is a good example of what might be called systematic ordinary

Presupposition and Montague Grammar (Krahmer 1998, Ch. 5)

09 Modal Logic II. CS 3234: Logic and Formal Systems. October 14, Martin Henz and Aquinas Hobor

To every formula scheme there corresponds a property of R. This relationship helps one to understand the logic being studied.

Homogeneity and Plurals: From the Strongest Meaning Hypothesis to Supervaluations

The Unified Theory. Theodore Korzukhin draft, Tuesday, July 17, 2012

FREE CHOICE IN MODAL CONTEXTS

Week 12: Introduction to Possible World Semantics Seminar: The Syntax-Semantics Interface M. Louie February Introduction

A new resolution of the Judy Benjamin problem

list readings of conjoined singular which -phrases

Propositional Logic: Models and Proofs

Subjective Ought. 1 For example, the literature on wide-scope obligations is at least partly based on assumptions

List of errors in and suggested modifications for First-Order Modal Logic Melvin Fitting and Richard L. Mendelsohn August 11, 2013

C. Modal Propositional Logic (MPL)

The Semantics of Definite DPs 1. b. Argument Position: (i) [ A politician ] arrived from Washington. (ii) Joe likes [ the politician ].

Transcription:

Quick Introduction to the Semantics of Modals 1 Syntactic assumptions (following von Fintel & Heim 2005): modals are raising predicates (see Wurmbrand 1999, Bhatt 1998) 1) John must go home. 2) [John [λ 1 [must [t 1 go home]]]] For simplicity, we will work with the reconstructed structures: 3) must [John go home] In a possible world semantics, modal expressions are treated as quantifiers over worlds. First try: Necessity modals (e.g., must, have to) are universal quantifiers. Possibility modals (e.g., might, can) are existential quantifiers. 4) [[must]] = λp <st> λw w : p(w ) = 1 5) [[can]] = λp <st,> λw w : p(w ) = 1 6) John must be home [must [John be home]] true iff John is home in all possible worlds 7) John may be home [may [John be home]] true iff there s some possible world where John is home. BUT: this doesn t account for - Contingency of modal statements: 8) John must be home now. 9) It must be raining outside In order to evaluate (8) and (9), we only consider worlds that are compatible with the evidence available to us. 1 Some parts of this handout are borrowed / adapted from von Fintel and Heim s notes on Intensional Semantics. I have also made use of Valentine Hacquard s handouts on modality, available at http://people.umass.edu/hacquard/ling720/calendar.htm Of course, all errors are mine. Page 1 of 8

- Different flavors of modality 10) John must have been the murderer [epistemic] 11) John must go to jail [deontic] 12) John must sneeze [circumstantial] (Kratzer 1991) Maybe modals are ambiguous? Kratzer 1977, 1981, 1981: NO. The kind of modality involved can be specified overtly: 13) In view of the available evidence, John must have been the murderer 14) In view of what the law provides, John must go to jail 15) In view of the present state of his nose, John must sneeze. The paraphrases above in 13), 14), 15) are not redundant. The must in these examples is a neutral modal. The existence of neutral modals suggests that non-neutral modals are not truly ambiguous. They just need a piece of information provided by the context of use (Kratzer 1991: 640) Second try: What we want: 16) (In view of what the law provides) John must go to jail true in a world w iff John goes to jail in all the worlds that are compatible with what the law provides in w. 17) In view of the available evidence, John must have been the murderer true in a world w iff John is the murderer in all the worlds that are compatible with the available evidence in w. 18) In view of the available evidence, John might have been the murderer true in a world w iff there s at least a world compatible with the evidence in w where John is the murderer. Kratzer s conversational backgrounds: Restrictions on the domain of quantification of modals are provided via conversational backgrounds. A conversational background is the sort of thing that is identified by phrases like what the law provides, what we know, etc. what we know What we know varies from one possible world to another. Page 2 of 8

What we know in a particular world is a set of propositions. The denotation of what we know is a function which assigns to every possible world the set of propositions that we know in that world. 19) [[what we know]] = λw. λp. p is one of the propositions that we know in w. what the law provides The denotation of what the law provides is a function which assigns to every possible world the set of propositions that the law provides in that world. 20) [[what the law provides]] = λw. λp. p is one of the propositions that the law provides in w. More generally, a conversational backgrounds is a function that takes maps any world w to (the characteristic function of) a set of propositions. Note: For any conversational background f of type <s<st,t>, we can define the corresponding accessibility relation R f of type <s<s,t> as follows: 21) R f := λw. λw. p [f(w)(p) = 1 [p(w ) = 1] ((21) is taken from von Fintel and Heim 2005; see definition 2 in Kratzer 1991) Denotation of modals. 22) [[must]]= λf <s<<s,t>,t>>> λp <s,t>. λw w (w f(w) p(w ) = 1) 23) [[can]]= λf <s<<s,t>,t>>> λp <s,t>. λw w (w f(w) & p(w ) = 1) [note: in Kratzer s definitions, the conversational background is a parameter of evaluation.] Or, given (21). 24) [[must]]= λr <s<s,t>> λp <s,t>. λw w (R(w)(w ) = 1 p(w ) = 1) 25) [[can]]= λr <s<s,t>> λp <s,t>. λw w (R(w)(w ) = 1 & p(w ) = 1) 26) In view of what the law provides, John must go to jail. The proposition that is true in w iff John goes to jail in all the worlds where the laws in w are obeyed. What if the conversational background is not explicit? (i) Recovered from context. 27) John must be home. (ii) Hard-wired for some modals (see Kratzer 1981, 1991) Page 3 of 8

This gives us: - Flavors of modality: different modal flavors correspond to different conversational backgrounds. - Contingency: modals are evaluated with respect to what the laws/the evidence/the circumstances are in the world of evaluation. But this is not enough: Consider the following example from von Fintel and Heim (2005) 28) John must pay a fine. The truth of 28) in the actual world depends on (i) what the facts are (what John has done), and (ii) what the law is. For instance, 28) will be judged true if (i) the law states that nobody obstructs a driveway, (ii) the law states that anybody who obstructs a driveway pays a fine, and (iii) John has obstructed a driveway. What are we quantifying over in this case? Perhaps: 29) {w : what happened in w up to now is the same as what happened in the actual world and w conforms to what the law in the actual world states} Problem: given the facts in the actual world (John has violated the law) the domain of quantification will be empty. Thus, 28) is predicted to be trivially true. Solution: How: the domain of quantification consists of all the worlds where the facts are as they are in the actual world and where the law is obeyed as well as it can be given the facts. We need to rank the worlds where the facts are as the are in the actual world with respect to how well they obey the laws. To do that, we will introduce a second conversational background. Third try: Ordering. Kratzer: modal operators are interpreted with respect to two conversational backgrounds. A modal base, which determines for every world the set of worlds that are accessible from it. An ordering source, which imposes a partial order on the set of worlds selected by the modal base. Page 4 of 8

How this works (simplified version, from von Fintel & Heim (2005)): Step 1: Defining a strict partial order with respect to a set of propositions [cf. with Kratzer s definition] 30) For any pair of worlds, w1 and w2, w1 comes closer than w2 (w1 < P w2) to the ideal set up by a set of propositions P iff the set of propositions belonging to P that are true in w2 is a proper subset of the set of propositions belonging to P that are true in w1. Step 2: Defining a function that selects the best worlds from any set X of worlds with respect to a partial order < P 31) X W: max P (X) = {w W: ~ w X: w < P w} Step 3: Formulate the semantics of must and can accordingly 2 32) [[must]] w = λf <s<<s,t>,t>>> λg <s<<s,t>,t>>> λq <s,t>. w max g(w) ( f(w)): q(w ) = 1) (von Fintel and Heim 2005: 55) 33) [[can]] w = λf <s<<s,t>,t>>> λg <s<<s,t>,t>>> λq <s,t>. w max g(w) ( f(w)): q(w ) = 1) must p is true iff p is true in all the worlds selected by the modal base that are best with respect to the ordering source. can p is true iff p is true in at least of of the worlds selected by the modal base that are best with respect to the ordering source. [Note: what we have above only works if we can in general assume that there are always accessible worlds that come closest to the ideal set up by the ordering source. According to Lewis (1973), we shouldn t make that assumption, which he calls the Limit Assumption. Kratzer (1991) follows Lewis in this respect. Hence, her semantics for modals is more complicated than what we have above.] Page 5 of 8

The driveway example: modal base: what the facts are [[what the facts are]](w 0 ) = {that John has obstructed a driveway} ordering source: what the law provides [[what the law provides]](w 0 ) = {that nobody obstructs a driveway, that anybody who obstructs a driveway pays a fine} 34) Accessible worlds Type 1 Type 2 Type 3 worlds worlds worlds John has obstructed a driveway F T T Nobody obstructs a driveway T F F Anybody who obstructs a driveway pays a fine T F T Optimal worlds Domain of quantification: Type 3 worlds John must pay a fine is true in w 0 iff John pays a fine in all the type 3 worlds. The Samaritan Paradox (Prior 1958) 35) John ought to help the person who was robbed. If we don t have an ordering semantics for modals: In all the worlds compatible with the ethics code, John helps the person robbed. But then 36) follows from 35) 36) It ought to be the case that someone was robbed. The doubly-relative analysis of modality avoids this prediction. Kratzer (1991) version of the Paradox with conditionals. The Law says that 37) No murder occurs. 38) If a murder occurs, the murderer will go to jail. Page 6 of 8

Assuming conditional is material implication, and assuming a standard semantics for modals, it follows that, It is necessary that: 39) If a murder occurs, the murderer will go jail. 40) If a murder occurs, the murderer will be knighted 41) If a murder occurs, the murderer will receive $100. Kratzer s solution: the if-clause restricts the modal base of the modal 42) If a murder occurs, the murderer must go to jail. In all of worlds where a murder occurs, and that are best with respect to what the law provides, the murderer goes to jail. Two types of modal reasoning: circumstantial vs. epistemic 43) (a) Hydrangeas can grow here. (b) There might be hydrangeas growing here. "Suppose I acquire a piece of land in a far away country and discover that soil and climate are very much like at home, where hydrangeas prosper everywhere. Since hydrangeas are my favorite plants, I wonder whether they would grow in this place and inquire about it. The answer is [43)a)] In such a situation, the proposition expressed by [43)a)] is true. It is true regardless of whether it is or isn t likely that there are already hydrangeas in the country we are considering. All that matters is climate, soil, the special properties of hydrangeas, and the like. Suppose now that the country we are in has never had any contacts whatsoever with Asia or America, and the vegetation is altogether different from ours. Given this evidence, my utterance of [43)b)] would express a false proposition. What counts here is the complete evidence available. And this evidence is not compatible with the existence of hydrangeas. [43)a)] together with our scenario illustrates the pure circumstantial reading of the modal can. The pure circumstantial reading of modals is characterized by a circumstantial modal base and an empty ordering source [PMB: the function which assigns the empty set to every possible world] [43)b)] together with our scenario illustrates the epistemic reading of modals (the ordering source may or may not be empty here). Circumstantial and epistemic conversational backgrounds involve different kinds of facts. In using an epistemic modal, we are interested in what else may or must be the case in our world given all the evidence available. " (Kratzer 1991: 646). Circumstantial modal base: picks out worlds in which certain relevant facts or circumstances hold. E.g., climate, soil, special properties of hydrangeas... Epistemic modal base: picks out worlds compatible with all the evidence available. If we know for a fact that hydrangeas do not grow here, (43))a) can still be true, but 43)b) is false. Page 7 of 8

Combinations of modal bases and ordering sources Epistemic modal base: combines with ordering source related to information: what the normal course of events is like, reports, beliefs: stereotypical ordering source ( in view of the normal course of events ) Some possibilities are more far fetched than others: 44) Michl must be the murderer. Michl is probably the murderer. There is a good possiblility that Michl is the murderer. There is a slight possibility that Michl is the murderer. Far fetched in view of the normal course of events: 45) Michl must be the murderer. In all the best worlds w.r.t. the normal course of events, among those compatible with my evidence, Michl is the murderer. Circumstantial modal base: combines with an ordering source related to laws, aims, plans, wishes: what the law provides, what is good for you, what we aim at, what is moral 46) Given your state of health, you should live in a warm climate In view of your state or health [circumstantial modal base] and in view of what is good for you [ordering source], you should live in a warm climate. One of the conversational backgrounds might be empty (technically, an empty conversational background maps every possible world to the empty set). A possible case in point, from Kratzer 1981: in order to evaluate 47) we need only consider certain properties inherent in the cup: circumstantial modal base & empty ordering source. 47) Diese Tasse ist zerbrechlich This cup is fragile Page 8 of 8