INCOMPATIBLE AND CONTRADICTORY RETRODICTIONS IN THE HISTORY APPROACH TO QUANTUM MECHANICS

Similar documents
What really matters in Hilbert-space stochastic processes

Incompatibility Paradoxes

Backward evolving quantum states

Locality and simultaneous elements of reality

Reasoning in Quantum Theory: Modus Ponens and the co-event interpretation

Consistent Histories. Chapter Chain Operators and Weights

arxiv:quant-ph/ v1 28 Sep 2005

Dependent (Contextual) Events

arxiv:quant-ph/ v3 18 May 2004

The Quantum-Classical Transition and Wave Packet Dispersion. C. L. Herzenberg

Stochastic Quantum Dynamics I. Born Rule

arxiv: v2 [gr-qc] 4 Sep 2013

Calculation of Fragmentation Functions in Two-hadron Semi-inclusive Processes

Relation of the Bell inequalities with quantum logic, hidden variables and information theory

arxiv: v1 [gr-qc] 14 May 2013

arxiv:gr-qc/ v1 15 Oct 1996

The Square of Opposition in Orthomodular Logic

Logical difficulty from combining counterfactuals in the GHZ-Bell theorems

Hardy s Paradox. Chapter Introduction

arxiv:quant-ph/ v2 6 Sep 1995

arxiv:gr-qc/ v1 1 May 1993

A General Argument Against the Universal Validity of the Superposition Principle

On the selection of preferred consistent sets

Consistent Quantum Reasoning

Two-State Vector Formalism

Stochastic Processes

THE OBJECTIVE PAST OF

Notes on Quantum Logic

Super-Quantum, Non-Signaling Correlations Cannot Exist

Lecture 2. Logic Compound Statements Conditional Statements Valid & Invalid Arguments Digital Logic Circuits. Reading (Epp s textbook)

arxiv: v3 [quant-ph] 19 Apr 2016

Physics 221A Fall 2018 Notes 22 Bound-State Perturbation Theory

The Two-State Vector Formalism

arxiv:quant-ph/ v1 28 Apr 2005

4.1 Real-valued functions of a real variable

NONINVARIANT ONE-WAY SPEED OF LIGHT AND LOCALLY EQUIVALENT REFERENCE FRAMES

arxiv: v1 [quant-ph] 16 Oct 2018

Counterfactuals in Quantum Mechanics

arxiv: v3 [quant-ph] 9 Feb 2018

Even quantum pigeons may thrive together

Existence of Antiparticles as an Indication of Finiteness of Nature. Felix M. Lev

Comments on There is no axiomatic system for the. quantum theory. Noname manuscript No. (will be inserted by the editor) J.

Recursive proof of the Bell Kochen Specker theorem in any dimension n>3

CAT L4: Quantum Non-Locality and Contextuality

arxiv:quant-ph/ v2 6 Jul 2005

arxiv:cond-mat/ v1 [cond-mat.mtrl-sci] 6 Jun 2001

arxiv:hep-ph/ v1 11 Mar 1994

Manual of Logical Style

arxiv:quant-ph/ v1 10 Oct 2001

A variational approach to Ising spin glasses in finite dimensions

arxiv:quant-ph/ v1 15 Jul 2004

Finite-size analysis via the critical energy -subspace method in the Ising models

Zeros of polynomials, solvable dynamical systems and generations of polynomials

From qubit to qudit with hybrid OAM-polarization quantum state

Quantum Information Types

arxiv:gr-qc/ v1 15 Apr 1997

Testing Lorentz invariance violations in the tritium beta-decay anomaly

Time-Symmetrized Counterfactuals in Quantum Theory 1

CHAPTER 3 THE COMMON FACTOR MODEL IN THE POPULATION. From Exploratory Factor Analysis Ledyard R Tucker and Robert C. MacCallum

Counterfactuals in Quantum Mechanics arxiv: v1 [quant-ph] 4 Sep 2007

Positive operator valued measures covariant with respect to an irreducible representation

Wave function collapse

Atomic effect algebras with compression bases

The Equivalence of Ergodicity and Weak Mixing for Infinitely Divisible Processes1

3 The Semantics of the Propositional Calculus

A No-Go Result on Common Cause Approaches via Hardy s Paradox

On the Onsager-Yang-Value of the Spontaneous Magnetization

Introduction to Bases in Banach Spaces

The Measurement Problem

arxiv: v1 [nucl-th] 1 Dec 2016

Warm-Up Problem. Write a Resolution Proof for. Res 1/32

arxiv:quant-ph/ v1 19 Oct 1995

Density Operators and Ensembles

Structure of Sn isotopes beyond N =82

A Note On Comparative Probability

Quantum Theory of Many-Particle Systems, Phys. 540

UNIVERSAL HYBRID QUANTUM PROCESSORS

ON POSITIVE-OPERATOR-VALUED MEASURE FOR PHASE MEASUREMENTS. Abstract. The unnormalizable Susskind-Glogower (SG) phase eigenstates, which

Must... stay... strong!

arxiv: v1 [gr-qc] 6 Dec 2016

Topic 3: Bohr, Einstein, and the EPR experiment

AN INTRODUCTION TO SEPARATION LOGIC. 2. Assertions

I. INTRODUCTION. Classical equations for quantum systems PHYSICAL REVIEW D VOLUME 47, NUMBER 8 15 APRIL 1993

On Markov Properties in Evidence Theory

Inequalities for Dealing with Detector Inefficiencies in Greenberger-Horne-Zeilinger Type Experiments

Turing Machines, diagonalization, the halting problem, reducibility

Physics 4022 Notes on Density Matrices

AI Principles, Semester 2, Week 2, Lecture 5 Propositional Logic and Predicate Logic

COLLECTIVE SPIN STATES IN THE ELECTRON GAS IN DIFFERENT DIMENSIONS AND GEOMETRIES*)

Singlet State Correlations

arxiv:quant-ph/ v1 14 Mar 2001

Lee Yang zeros and the Ising model on the Sierpinski gasket

KOLMOGOROV s PROBABILITY THEORY IN QUANTUM PHYSICS

Glossary of Logical Terms

Further Analysis of the Link between Thermodynamics and Relativity

POSITIVE AND NEGATIVE CORRELATIONS FOR CONDITIONAL ISING DISTRIBUTIONS

The Erwin Schrodinger International Pasteurgasse 6/7. Institute for Mathematical Physics A-1090 Wien, Austria

ON SPECTRA OF LÜDERS OPERATIONS

CHAPTER 4 ENTROPY AND INFORMATION

Projective Schemes with Degenerate General Hyperplane Section II

Transcription:

Foundations of Physics Letters, Vol. 11, No., 1998 INCOMPATIBLE AND CONTRADICTORY RETRODICTIONS IN THE HISTORY APPROACH TO QUANTUM MECHANICS Giulio Peruzzi and Alberto Rimini Dipartimento di Fi.sica Nucleare e Teorica Univer.sita di Pavia, I-71 00 Pavia, Italy Received 6 January 1998 We illustrate two simple spin examples which show that in the consistent histories approach to quantum mechanics one can retrodict with certainty incompatible or contradictory propositions corresponding to non-orthogonal or, respectively, orthogonal projections. Key words: quantum mechanics, history approach, quantum measurement, retrodictions. 1. INTRODUCTION A problem in the consistent-history approach to quantum mechanics is that in general there are different consistent sets of histories compatible with facts ascertained at certain times such that, depending on the choice of the consistent set, one can infer (in fact retrodict with certainty) definite values of incompatible physical quantities at other times. This feature of the theory was recognized and discussed by Griffiths in his seminal paper [1]. A simple example was given, where the considered system was a spin 1/. Griffiths' answer to the problem was that incompatible physical quantities cannot jointly be said to have definite values at a certain time because, according to the principles of the consistent-history approach, the corresponding properties cannot all be inserted in a single consistent history. Some time later, d'espagnat [] objected that such an attitude entails giving up one of the most important rules of logic. A type of answer different from that of Griffiths is the distinction proposed by Omnes [3] between true and reliable propositions. The propositions involved in the retrodictions referred to above would not be true but only reliable. Recently, Kent [4] has shown that, if the Hilbert space of the 01 0894-9875198/0400 001$15.00/0 1998 Ple"um Publishing Corporation

0 Peruzzi and Rlmlnl system is at least three-dimensional, one can retrodict with certainty different properties corresponding to orthogonal projections. A particular case was considered previously by Aharonov and Vaidman [5) in a conceptual framework different from the history approach. In a subsequent paper Kent [6) recalls his previous result and uses it to support the proposal of a new criterion for selecting meaningful sets of histories, called ordered con3i3tency, which would rule out this kind of difficulty. We think that points of view different from those of Griffiths and Omnes are legitimate, so that it is worthwhile exploring further the subject. The arguments in Refs. [4) and [5) have a formal character, 1 no example based on a specific physical system and specific physical quantities being given. It is our purpose to provide such an example, the physical system being a spin 1. In Sec., after briefly recalling Kent's formalism, we frame into it Griffiths' and our examples. In Sec. 3 we comment on the results.. INCOMPATIBLE AND CONTRADICTORY RETRODICTIONS FOR SPIN SYSTEMS In the Hilbert space 1-{ let ji} be the normalised state of a closed system at some initial time t = t 0 Consider the set of histories S specified at time t1 > t 0 by the properties p1 _ lm)(ml 1 - (mlm)' pi = 1 _ lm)(ml (mjm) (1) and at time t > t1 by the properties p- l/}(!1 1 - Ulf)' p = 1- l/}(!1. Ul!} () A sufficient condition in order that S be consistent is the (medium) decoherence condition of Gell-Mann and Hartle [7], which can be expressed as (!li)(mjm) = (!lm)(mli). (3) In the example considered by Griffiths, the system is a noninteracting spin 1/ in two-dimensional H. Let ji) = isz =+~)and 1 The example of Aharonov and Vaidman is formulated using the term "boxes" to indicate state vectors. The word box is evocative, but the example remains formal.

History Approach to Quantum Mechanics 03 If)= lsx =+!).Then it is easily seen that there are two ways to meet the consistency condition (3) by lm). The first possibility is that the intermediate state lm) coincides with the initial state of the system, i.e., lm) = li). Let Si be the consistent set of histories corresponding to this choice. The conditional probabilities for si are shown in the following diagram: li) -----~ 0 P l 1- The second possibility is that the intermediate state lm) coincides with the final state If), i.e., lm) = If). Let Sr be the consistent set corresponding to this choice. The conditional probabilities for Sr are shown in the following diagram: o It is obvious from the diagrams that, both for Si and Sr, from the property P[ at time t we can retrodict with certainty the property Pi at time t 1 In other words, we can retrodict with certainty both that the value of S: was +! and that the value of Sx was +! We say that we are faced with incompatible retrodictions. In our example the system is a non-interacting spin 1 in threedimensional 'H. Let the initial state of the system be?. (4) Kent uses in this case the term "complementary". We feel that the common meaning of the term "incompatible" is more adherent to describe the situation.

04 Peruzzi and Rlmlnl and the (non-normalised) state vectors If) and lm) be specified by If) = lsn = 0) = (5) ±-1_mx -imy y' 1 =fmz 1 (6) ±-1_mx +imy y' 1 ±mz in terms of two unit vectors n and m in the physical space. The components of n and m must satisfy the conditions On the other hand, the consistency condition (3) reduces to Let us take (7) (8) mx = anx, my = any, mz = -bnz, (9) where a and b are positive real numbers. Then the normalisation condition (7) for m gives (10) Using assumption (9) in expression (6), one finds (11) and (1)

History Approach to Quantum Mechanics 05 Thus the consistency condition (8) assumes, both for the upper and the lower sign, the form i.e., taking into account Eq. (10), a(1 + b n;) = b(1- b n;), (13) b -1 nz = b(b + 3) (14) It is easily seen that for b ~ 1 the value of n; is in the interval [0, 1/9] and is therefore acceptable (there are two values of b for each value of n; < 1/9). From the above discussion it follows that, for each acceptable pair of unit vectors n, m, one can consider two consistent sets of histories s+ and s_ corresponding to lm} = lm+} and lm} = lm-}, respectively. Chosen n and m, the conditional probabilities are the same for s+ and s_ and are shown in the diagram 1 p pl --~! / )i) where 1 = (3 /a and a= (ilm)(mli} = _1_ = 1- b n; (mlm} (mlm} (ilf)(fli} 1 (3 = (!If) = (!If} = nz. (15) (16) Let us exclude the choices nz = 0, mz = 0 (corresponding to the solution b = 1, nz = 0 of Eq. (14)) and nz = 0, mz = -1 (corresponding to b--+ oo, bnz --+ 1), for which the probability of the property P{ at time t is zero. Then it is apparent from the diagram that from the property P'f at time t one can retrodict with certainty both that the value of Sm was +1 and that it was -1 at time t1. We say that we are faced with contradictory retrodictions. 3 3 Kent uses in this case the term "contrary." We think that the term "contradictory" more explicitly describes the situation, even though the common use in logic would suggest the other term. What Kent designates as "contradictory" could be called, in our terminology, "exhaustively contradictory".

06 Peruzzi and Rlminl 3. CONCLUSIONS The spin-1 example given in Sec. shows that the situation formally discussed by Kent can take place in the case of "realistic observations of real experiments". Moreover the fact that the contradictory propositions correspond to opposite values of the same physical quantity sm makes the example particularly striking. Various types of proposal to answer the problems related to the existence of incompatible and contradictory retrodictions in the history approach have already been discussed by Griffiths[1,8], d'espagnat [], Omnes [3], and Kent [4,6]. We do not enter into the details of this debate. We only point out that in Kent's second paper, the occurrence of the difficulties is related to the fact that consistent sets like s+ and s_ do not satisfy a criterion, called ordered consistency, which would ensure that, in the framework of the history approach, implication by subspace inclusion is valid. To illustrate this point, let us rephrase Kent in the framework of our specific physical example. Consider the two histories h from S+ and h 0 from s_ given by h = {Pl(S+),Pf} and ho = {Pi(S-),Pf}. The projections at time t1 in the two cases are given by Pl(S+) =Ism= +1)(sm = +11 and Pi(S-) = 1 - Ism = -1)(sm = -11 = Jsm = +1)(sm = +11+ Ism= O)(sm =OJ, so that the subspace associated to Pl(S+) is contained in the subspace associated to Pi ( S-). Implication by subspace inclusion would mean that the occurrence of history h implies the occurrence of history h 0 But accepting such an implication contradicts the fact that Pr( h) = Ot"'f f:. 0 while Pr( h o) = t 1 - a) 0 = 0. The criterion of ordered consistency [6] would rule out sets of histories like s+ and s_. Our realistic example gives answers to some questions raised by Kent. First, as already noted, it proves that Kent's situation can take place in the case of real experiments, by preparing a spin 1 in the state Jsz = 0) and subsequently ascertaining that it is in the state Jsn = 0), with n as discussed in Sec.. Second, as a consequence, one can answer negatively to the question "whether quasiclassical domains should generally be expected to be ordered consistent sets:' In fact both S+ and$_ can be considered as coarsegrainings of the usual quasiclassical domain (or, more precisely, as coarse-grainings of two quasiclassical domains based on the same quasiclassical variables, the usual ones, which include the pointer variables of the apparatuses), but they do not satisfy Kent's constraint of ordered consistency. Therefore one can conclude that the constraint of quasiclassicality on consistent sets of histories does not include that of ordered consistency, so that the latter is actually an effective additional criterion. Acknowledgements. We thank Robert B. Griffiths for use-

History Approach to Quantum Mechanics 07 ful criticisms. This work is supported in part by the Istituto Nazionale di Fisica Nucleare. REFERENCES 1. R. B. Griffiths, J. Stat. Phys. 36, 19 (1984).. B. d'espagnat, Phys. Lett. A 14, 04 (1987). 3. R. Omnes, J. Stat. Phys. 6, 841 (1991 ). 4. A. Kent, Phys. Rev. Lett. 78, 874 (1997). 5. Y. Aharonov and L. Vaidman, J. Phys. A: Math. Gen. 4, 315 (1991). 6. A. Kent, preprint, gr-qc/9607073. 7. M. Gell-Mann and J.B. Hartle, Phys. Rev. D 47, 3345 (1993). 8. R. B. Griffiths, Phys. Rev. A 54, 759 (1996).