Antonio Quesada Universidad de Murcia. Abstract

Similar documents
APPLIED MECHANISM DESIGN FOR SOCIAL GOOD

Follow links for Class Use and other Permissions. For more information send to:

Strategic Manipulability without Resoluteness or Shared Beliefs: Gibbard-Satterthwaite Generalized

Coalitional Structure of the Muller-Satterthwaite Theorem

arxiv: v2 [math.co] 14 Apr 2011

Strategy-Proofness on the Condorcet Domain

Social Choice and Mechanism Design - Part I.2. Part I.2: Social Choice Theory Summer Term 2011

Comparing impossibility theorems

Coalitionally strategyproof functions depend only on the most-preferred alternatives.

Volume 31, Issue 1. Manipulation of the Borda rule by introduction of a similar candidate. Jérôme Serais CREM UMR 6211 University of Caen

Finite Dictatorships and Infinite Democracies

13 Social choice B = 2 X X. is the collection of all binary relations on X. R = { X X : is complete and transitive}

6.207/14.15: Networks Lecture 24: Decisions in Groups

"Arrow s Theorem and the Gibbard-Satterthwaite Theorem: A Unified Approach", by Phillip Reny. Economic Letters (70) (2001),

Social Choice Theory. Felix Munoz-Garcia School of Economic Sciences Washington State University. EconS Advanced Microeconomics II

Hans Peters, Souvik Roy, Soumyarup Sadhukhan, Ton Storcken

MAXIMAL POSSIBILITY AND MINIMAL DICTATORIAL COVERS OF DOMAINS

Dependence and Independence in Social Choice Theory

Strategic Manipulation and Regular Decomposition of Fuzzy Preference Relations

Economic Core, Fair Allocations, and Social Choice Theory

Antipodality in committee selection. Abstract

Integer Programming on Domains Containing Inseparable Ordered Pairs

Social Welfare Functions that Satisfy Pareto, Anonymity, and Neutrality: Countable Many Alternatives. Donald E. Campbell College of William and Mary

Arrow s Paradox. Prerna Nadathur. January 1, 2010

DICTATORIAL DOMAINS. Navin Aswal University of Minnesota, Minneapolis, USA Shurojit Chatterji Indian Statistical Institute, New Delhi, India and

Non-Manipulable Domains for the Borda Count

Social Choice. Jan-Michael van Linthoudt

INTEGER PROGRAMMING AND ARROVIAN SOCIAL WELFARE FUNCTIONS

Arrow s General (Im)Possibility Theorem

Fair Divsion in Theory and Practice

Reference-based Preferences Aggregation Procedures in Multicriteria Decision Making

Recap Social Choice Functions Fun Game Mechanism Design. Mechanism Design. Lecture 13. Mechanism Design Lecture 13, Slide 1

Quasi-transitive and Suzumura consistent relations

Efficiency and converse reduction-consistency in collective choice. Abstract. Department of Applied Mathematics, National Dong Hwa University

Approval Voting for Committees: Threshold Approaches

A General Impossibility Result on Strategy-Proof Social Choice Hyperfunctions

Algorithmic Game Theory Introduction to Mechanism Design

The Arrow Impossibility Theorem Of Social Choice Theory In An Infinite Society And Limited Principle Of Omniscience

Arrow s Theorem as a Corollary

3.1 Arrow s Theorem. We study now the general case in which the society has to choose among a number of alternatives

Michel Le Breton and John A. Weymark

On the Strategy-proof Social Choice of Fixed-sized Subsets

Single-plateaued choice

The Gibbard random dictatorship theorem: a generalization and a new proof

A topological approach to Wilson s impossibility theorem

Social choice theory, Arrow s impossibility theorem and majority judgment

Lecture Notes, Lectures 22, 23, 24. Voter preferences: Majority votes A > B, B > C. Transitivity requires A > C but majority votes C > A.

A MAXIMAL DOMAIN FOR STRATEGY-PROOF AND NO-VETOER RULES IN THE MULTI-OBJECT CHOICE MODEL

THREE BRIEF PROOFS OF ARROW S IMPOSSIBILITY THEOREM JOHN GEANAKOPLOS COWLES FOUNDATION PAPER NO. 1116

arxiv: v1 [cs.gt] 9 Apr 2015

Lecture 10: Mechanism Design

A Note on the McKelvey Uncovered Set and Pareto Optimality

Strategy-proof allocation of indivisible goods

CMU Social choice 2: Manipulation. Teacher: Ariel Procaccia

The Axiomatic Method in Social Choice Theory:

Resource Allocation via the Median Rule: Theory and Simulations in the Discrete Case

Arrow s Impossibility Theorem and Experimental Tests of Preference Aggregation

Acyclic and indifference-transitive collective choice functions.

A Role of Common Morality in Social Choice

MATH 19-02: HW 5 TUFTS UNIVERSITY DEPARTMENT OF MATHEMATICS SPRING 2018

UNIVERSITY OF KANSAS WORKING PAPERS SERIES IN THEORETICAL AND APPLIED ECONOMICS

Strategy proofness and unanimity in private good economies with single-peaked preferences

Arrovian Social Choice with Non -Welfare Attributes

Hans Peters, Souvik Roy, Ton Storcken. Manipulation under k-approval scoring rules RM/08/056. JEL code: D71, D72

Logic and Social Choice Theory

Probabilistic Aspects of Voting

Introduction. 1 University of Pennsylvania, Wharton Finance Department, Steinberg Hall-Dietrich Hall, 3620

CAHIER CANDIDATE STABILITY AND NONBINARY SOCIAL CHOICE. Lars EHLERS and John A. WEYMARK

Chapter 12: Social Choice Theory

A Systematic Approach to the Construction of Non-empty Choice Sets

Every Choice Correspondence is Backwards-Induction Rationalizable

On Social Choice Theory

Algorithmic Game Theory and Applications

Maskin monotonic coalition formation rules respecting group rights

Worst-case mechanism design with undominated strategies

Political Economy of Institutions and Development. Lectures 2 and 3: Static Voting Models

Expertise and Complexity in the Social and Engineering Sciences: An Extended Sen s Theorem

1 Introduction FUZZY VERSIONS OF SOME ARROW 0 S TYPE RESULTS 1. Louis Aimé Fono a,2, Véronique Kommogne b and Nicolas Gabriel Andjiga c

On the topological equivalence of the Arrow impossibility theorem and Amartya Sen s liberal paradox

Rationality and solutions to nonconvex bargaining problems: rationalizability and Nash solutions 1

An equity-efficiency trade-off in a geometric approach to committee selection Daniel Eckert and Christian Klamler

Arrovian Social Choice with Non -Welfare Attributes

Single-peaked consistency and its complexity

Voting. José M Vidal. September 29, Abstract. The problems with voting.

Minimal manipulability: anonymity and unanimity

14.770: Introduction to Political Economy Lectures 1 and 2: Collective Choice and Voting

Arrow s Impossibility Theorem: Preference Diversity in a Single-Profile World

Positive Political Theory II David Austen-Smith & Je rey S. Banks

This article appeared in a journal published by Elsevier. The attached copy is furnished to the author for internal non-commercial research and

Unanimity, Pareto optimality and strategy-proofness on connected domains

Notes on Social Choice Theory

First-Order Logic Formalisation of Impossibility Theorems in Preference Aggregation

Franz Dietrich, Christian List. The impossibility of unbiased judgment aggregation. RM/07/022 (RM/05/049 -revised-)

TitleNo-Envy, Efficiency, and Collective.

A DISTANCE-BASED EXTENSION OF THE MAJORITY JUDGEMENT VOTING SYSTEM

Partial lecture notes THE PROBABILITY OF VIOLATING ARROW S CONDITIONS

The Beach Party Problem: An informal introduction to continuity problems in group choice *

Ordered Value Restriction

A Characterization of Single-Peaked Preferences via Random Social Choice Functions

Game Theory: Spring 2017

Transcription:

From social choice functions to dictatorial social welfare functions Antonio Quesada Universidad de Murcia Abstract A procedure to construct a social welfare function from a social choice function is suggested and it is shown that the dictatorial are the only unanimous social welfare functions that can be reconstructed from a social choice function that does not change the social choice when a defeated alternative is moved to the last position in all the individual preferences. The difference between night and day can be illustrated by comparing the original version of this paper (night) with the final version that incorporates the two referees suggestions and corrections (day). I am very grateful to them for taking the trouble to make this transformation (and recommending the publication of this paper) and to Jordi Massó, the associate editor, for accepting the publication of this paper. Citation: Quesada, Antonio, (2002) "From social choice functions to dictatorial social welfare functions." Economics Bulletin, Vol. 4, No. 16 pp. 1 7 Submitted: July 19, 2002. Accepted: July 19, 2002. URL: http://www.economicsbulletin.com/2002/volume4/eb 02D70006A.pdf

1. Introduction Arrow s (1963) theorem, on the one hand, expresses an impossibility result: one cannot have a non-dictatorial preference aggregation rule (social welfare function) that satisfies unanimity and a condition of independence of irrelevant alternatives (IIA); see Feldman (1980) or Saari (1998, 2001). But, on the other, Arrow s theorem makes social choice theory challenging (and, therefore, interesting) because it merely makes apparent the inadequacy of a specific approach to construct reasonable social welfare functions. For strict preferences, this note suggests the alternative approach consisting of constructing social welfare functions from social choice functions, which are rules transforming preference profiles not into preferences but into alternatives. The motivating idea is to define aggregation rules (social welfare functions) from simpler aggregation rules (social choice functions), so that one can use the solution to a certain aggregation problem to solve a more complex aggregation problem. To see how just one social choice function can be used to construct a social welfare function, let P be a preference profile and g a social choice function defined on the universal domain and satisfying the weak Pareto principle 1 (see A4: if all individuals prefer alternative x to alternative y then g cannot select y). The first alternative in the social preference associated with P is g(p). The problem is next to determine the second alternative in the social preference associated with P using g. One possible solution consists of replacing P with some preference profile P' that is very close to P and such that g does not associate with P' the previously selected alternative g(p). Since g satisfies the weak Pareto principle, moving g(p) to the last position in each individual preference from profile P ensures that g(p) will not be chosen. The resulting preference profile P' is in a sense very close to P, because the ordering of the relevant alternatives (all but g(p)) is the same in both profiles. So g(p') could be chosen as the second alternative in the social preference associated with P. The same logic could now be applied to P' to determine the third alternative in the social preference: just define P'' to be the preference profile obtained from P' by ranking 1 I am very grateful to Referee 1 for calling to my attention that the iterative construction defined next is essentially the same one used in the proof of Lemma 2 in Ehlers and Weymark (2001) and to Referee 2 for noticing that, without the weak Pareto principle, the aggregation rule to be defined next need not be a social welfare function. 1

g(p') last in each individual preference from preference profile P' and declare that g(p'') is the third alternative in the social preference that corresponds to P. And so on. The interest of this procedure is that the instructions needed to run a social welfare function could be coded by a social choice function, which is a structure simpler than a social welfare function. With always strict preferences, the main result presented in this note (Proposition 2.2) characterizes dictatorial social welfare functions by means of the weak Pareto principle (see A1: if all individuals prefer alternative x to alternative y then x is socially preferred to y) and the condition that, using the previous procedure, the social welfare function can be reconstructed from a social choice function that, in addition, satisfies the following property: if preference profile P' is obtained from P by ranking alternative x g(p) last in each individual preference then g(p') = g(p) 2. In words, if all individuals give a defeated alternative the minimum support with everything else the same, then the winning alternative remains winning. Since Proposition 2.2 is proved by showing that a social welfare function satisfying the preceding condition also satisfies IIA it follows that IIA can be subsumed under the approach of trying to reduce social welfare functions to social choice functions. 2. Definitions, assumptions and result Let N = {1, 2,, n} be a finite set whose members designate individuals, A a finite set containing m elements representing alternatives and L the set of complete, transitive and asymmetric binary relations that can be defined on A. Each member of L expresses a strict preference relation on A (no two alternatives are indifferent) and can be represented by a vector π = (x 1,, x m ) of the m alternatives, with x p preferred to x q if, and only if, p < q. Intuitively, π consists of a ranking of m positions. For 1 k m, let kπ designate the alternative filling the kth position in ranking π. For π L, P L n, x A, y A\{x} and i N: (i) P i denotes individual i s preference in preference profile P; (ii) π {x,y} denotes the restriction of π to the set {x, y}; and (iii) 2 Postulating the property that a social welfare function can be reconstructed from a social choice function makes the requirement that g satisfies the weak Pareto principle unnecessary, because the property presumes that the outcome of the procedure must be a social welfare function. It is this presumption that automatically restricts the domain of social choice functions that can be used to construct a social welfare function. Without this presumption, the domain restriction must be explicit; for instance, the social choice function must satisfy the weak Pareto principle. 2

P {x,y} abbreviates (P 1 {x,y},, P n {x,y} ). The preference profile P x obtained from P L n by moving x A to the last position in each P i is the profile P' in which, for all i N, P' i is defined as follows. Let 1 k m be such that x = k P i. Then m P' i = x and, for all 1 r < m, r P' i = r P i if r < k and r P' i = r 1 P i if r > k. Given N and A with n 2 < m, a social welfare function is a mapping f : L n L. The interpretation is that, for (P 1,, P n ) L n, f(p 1,, P n ) is the social preference that f associates with individual preferences P 1,, P n. Social welfare function f is dictatorial if there is an i N such that, for all (P 1,, P n ) L n, f(p 1,, P n ) = P i ; that is, individual i (called dictator ) is such that the social preference always coincides with i s preference. In this context, Arrow s (1963, p. 97) theorem asserts that, for n 2 < m, every social welfare function that satisfies IIA (independence of irrelevant alternatives) and A1 (the weak Pareto principle) below is dictatorial. IIA. For all P L n, Q L n \{P}, x A and y A\{x}, if P {x,y} = Q {x,y} then f(p) {x,y} = f(q) {x,y}. A1. For all P L n, x A and y A\{x}, if xp i y for all i N then xf(p)y. Suppose that, for all i N, x is ranked above y in P i if, and only if, x is ranked above y in Q i. By IIA, x is ranked above y in f(p) if, and only if, x is ranked above y in f(q). Hence, the ranking between x and y at the social level depends only on the ranking between these two alternatives at the individual level. By A1, if x is above y in every individual ranking in P then x is above y in the social ranking f(p). Given N and A with n 2 < m, a social choice function is a mapping g : L n A. The interpretation is that, for (P 1,, P n ) L n, g(p 1,, P n ) is the social choice that g derives from individual preferences P 1,, P n. Social choice function g is dictatorial if there is an i N such that, for all (P 1,, P n ) L n, g(p 1,, P n ) = 1 P i. A2 next is the property that a social welfare function can be reconstructed from a social choice function as suggested in Section 1 when the social choice function is merely assumed to satisfy A3 (recall footnote 2). By A3, the social choice does not change when a defeated alternative is ranked last in all the individual preferences: if Q L n is obtained from P by ranking x last in every P i then g(q) = g(p). A2. There is a social choice function g : L n A satisfying A3 such that, for all P L n and 1 k m, k f(p) = g( k P), where 1 P = P and, for 2 t m, t P = t 1 P g( t 1 P) ( t P is obtained from t 1 P by ranking g( t 1 P) last in each individual ordering). 3

A3. For all P L n and x A\{g(P)}, g(p x) = g(p). Lemma 2.1. If n 2 < m and f : L n L satisfies A2 then it satisfies IIA. Proof. Suppose f does not satisfy IIA: there are P L n, Q L n \{P}, x A and y A\{x} such that P {x,y} = Q {x,y}, x is ranked above y in f(p) but y is ranked above x in f(q). By A2, let g be the social choice function from which f is defined. Let f(p) = (x 1,, x s, x, y 1,, y t, y, z 1,, z u ). Hence, by A2, 1 f(p x 1 ) = g(p x 1 ) = x 2. Similarly, with P' = P x 1, 1 f(p' x 2 ) = g(p' x 2 ) = x 3. Thus, if R L n is obtained from P by ranking last in each P i first x 1, then x 2,, and finally x s then, by A2, 1 f(r) = g(r) = x. Since f satisfies A2, g satisfies A3 and g(r) = x, 1 f(r y 1 ) = g(r y 1 ) = g(r) = x. In the same vein, with R' = R y 1, 1 f(r' y 2 ) = g(r' y 2 ) = g(r y 1 ) = x. Accordingly, if S L n is obtained from R by ranking last in each R i first y 1, then y 2,, and finally y t and next first z 1, then z 2,, and finally z u then, by A2, 1 f(s) = g(s) and, by A3, g(s) = g(r) = x. As a result, S {x,y} = P {x,y} and, for all i N, the ranking of the last m 2 alternatives in S i is (x 1,, x s, y 1,, y t, z 1,, z u ). Let f(q) = (a 1,, a p, y, b 1,, b q, x, c 1,, c r ). An analogous argument proves that 1 f(t) = y, where T L n is such that T {x,y} = Q {x,y} and, for all i N, the ranking of the last m 2 alternatives in T i is (a 1,, a p, b 1,, b q, c 1,, c r ). Given that {a 1,, a p, b 1,, b q, c 1,, c r } = {x 1,, x s, y 1,, y t, z 1,, z u }, the aim is now to rank the last m 2 alternatives in each T i in the same way as in each S i without altering the socially most preferred alternative. To begin with, identify x 1 in {a 1,, a p, b 1,, b q, c 1,, c r }. By A3, g(t x 1 ) = g(t) so, by A2, 1 f(t x 1 ) = 1 f(t) = y. This procedure can be applied to, in this order, x 2,, x s, y 1,, y t, z 1,, z u to define V L n from T such that: (i) by A2, 1 f(v) = y; (ii) V {x,y} = T {x,y} ; and (iii) for all i N, the ranking of the last m 2 alternatives in V i is (x 1,, x s, y 1,, y t, z 1,, z u ). Given this and the fact that P {x,y} = Q {x,y}, S {x,y} = P {x,y}, T {x,y} = Q {x,y} and V {x,y} = T {x,y} imply S {x,y} = V {x,y}, it follows that S = V. Yet, 1 f(s) = x y = 1 f(v): contradiction. Proposition 2.2. If n 2 < m then f : L n L is dictatorial if, and only if, it satisfies A1 and A2. Proof. If i is a dictator in f then: (i) A1 automatically holds; and (ii) A2 holds with g : L n A such that, for all P L n, g(p) = P i. If f satisfies A2 then, by Lemma 2.1, it satisfies IIA. As f satisfies IIA and A1, it is dictatorial by Arrow s theorem. 4

A4. For all P L n and x A, if g(p) = x then there is no y A\{x} such that, for all i N, yp i x. The credit of the following result should be attributed to Referee 2. Proposition 2.3. If n 2 < m then g : L n A is dictatorial if, and only if, it satisfies A3 and A4. Proof. It is easy to see that if g is dictatorial then A3 and A4 hold. Suppose g satisfies A3 and A4 but it is not dictatorial. As Referee 2 observes, if g satisfies A4 then the social welfare function f defined from g as suggested in Section 1 is well-defined (because winning alternatives that have been moved to the last position will never be winning again) and satisfies A1. Hence, being A3 true for g, f satisfies A2 and, by Proposition 2.2, f has some dictator i N. If i is not a dictator in g then there is P L n with g(p) 1 P i. By A2, 1 f(p) 1 P i, contradicting the fact that i is a dictator in f. Referee 2 suggests connecting Proposition 2.3 with the fact (Corollary 2.5) that social choice functions satisfying the weak Pareto principle (see A4) and Maskin (1999, p. 28) monotonicity (see A5) are dictatorial (see Muller and Satterthwaite (1977)). A5. For all P L n, Q L n \{P} and x A, if g(p) = x and, for all i N and y A\{x}, xp i y implies xq i y then g(q) = x. Lemma 2.4. A5 is equivalent to A3. Proof. Let g(p) = x and z A\{x}. Then Q = P z is such that, for all i N and y A\{x}, xp i y implies xq i y. By A5, g(q) = x; that is, g(p z) = g(p). Let g(p) = x. If, for all i N and y A\{x}, xp i y implies xq i y then Q must come from P by exchanging contiguous alternatives (different from x) in the individual rankings. It therefore suffices to show that g(q) = g(p) when Q differs from P only in that, for some i N, v A\{x} and z A\{v, x}, vp i z and zq i v, where P and Q are such that, for no t A, vp i tp i z and, for no t A, zq i tq i v. Suppose g(q) x. Without loss of generality, assume v g(q). By A3, g(p v) = g(p) = x and g(q v) = g(q) x. But P v = Q v: contradiction. Corollary 2.5. If n 2 < m then g : L n A is dictatorial if, and only if, it satisfies A4 and A5. Proof. Lemma 2.4 and Proposition 2.3. 5

The preceding results provide additional links between Arrow s and the Gibbard (1973)-Satterthwaite (1975) theorem: the condition A3 is related to the condition IIA for social welfare functions through Lemma 2.1 and also to strategy-proofness of social choice functions, through Lemma 2.4 and the equivalence of A5 to strategy-proofness. Referee 2 wonders whether Proposition 2.2 can be straightforwardly adapted to the case in which social indifference is allowed. In this case, since positions in the social preference can be filled by sets of alternatives and not just by singletons, social choice functions have to be replaced in A2 by social choice correspondences, which map preference profiles into sets of alternatives. Nevertheless, Lemma 2.1 does not hold for social choice correspondences. To see this, let g be the weak Pareto correspondence, where g(p) = {x A: there is no y A\{x} such that, for all i N, yp i x}. With N = {1, 2} and A = {x, y, z}, the profile P with P 1 = (z, x, y) and P 2 = (y, z, x) results in a social preference f(p) with y indifferent to z and both preferred to x, whereas the profile Q with preferences Q 1 = P 1 and Q 2 = (z, y, x) results in a social preference f(q) with z preferred to x and x indifferent to y. Thus, P {x,y} = Q {x,y} but f(p) {x,y} f(q) {x,y}. References Arrow, K. (1963) Social choice and individual values, 2nd. edn., Wiley: New York. Ehlers, L., and J. A. Weymark (2001) Candidate stability and non-binary social choice Economic Theory, forthcoming (working paper version: http://www.vanderbilt.edu/ Econ/wparchive/workpaper/vu01-w13.pdf). Feldman, A. (1980) Welfare economics and social choice theory, Martinus Nijhoff: Boston. Gibbard, A. (1973) Manipulation of voting schemes: A general result Econometrica 41, 587 601. Maskin, E. (1999) Nash equilibrium and welfare optimality Review of Economic Studies 66, 23 38. Muller, E., and M. Satterthwaite (1977) The equivalence of strong positive association and strategy proofness Journal of Economic Theory 14, 412 418. Saari D.G. (1998) Connecting and resolving Sen s and Arrow s theorems Social Choice and Welfare 15, 239 261. Saari, D.G. (2001) Decisions and elections, explaining the unexpected, Cambridge University Press: Cambridge. Satterthwaite, M. (1975) Strategy-proofness and Arrow s conditions: Existence and correspondence theorems for voting procedures and social welfare functions Journal of Economic Theory 10, 187 217. 6