GRW Theory (Ghirardi, Rimini, Weber Model of Quantum Mechanics)

Similar documents
GRW Theory. Roman Frigg, LSE

Intermediate Philosophy of Physics: Philosophy of Quantum Mechanics Somerville College Dr Hilary Greaves

Master Projects (EPFL) Philosophical perspectives on the exact sciences and their history

Against the field ontology of quantum mechanics

What is it like to be a quantum observer? And what does it imply about the nature of consciousness?

Probability in GRW Theory

The Foundations of Quantum Mechanics and The Limitations of Human Being

Probability in GRW Theory

What does it feel like to be in a quantum superposition?

GRW as an Ontology of Dispositions 1

The Measurement Problem

The Role of the Wave Function in the GRW Matter Density Theory

by Bradley Monton Department of Philosophy, University of Kentucky, Lexington KY USA phone: fax:

09a. Collapse. Recall: There are two ways a quantum state can change: 1. In absence of measurement, states change via Schrödinger dynamics:

Does the ψ-epistemic view really solve the measurement problem?

Reading list for the philosophy of quantum mechanics

The nature of Reality: Einstein-Podolsky-Rosen Argument in QM

The GRW flash theory: a relativistic quantum ontology of matter in space-time?

ARTICLE IN PRESS. Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics

Life and death in the tails of the GRW wave function

Bell s inequalities and their uses

The Measurement Problem of Quantum Mechanics Click to edit Master title style. Wells Wulsin SASS 24 September 2008

HSSP Philosophy of Quantum Mechanics 08/07/11 Lecture Notes

Tails of Schroedinger's Cat. In his famous thought experiment Schroedinger (1935) imagined a cat that measures the

Determinate Values for Quantum Observables

What really matters in Hilbert-space stochastic processes

The Philosophy of Quantum Mechanics (Handout Eight) between the microphysical and the macrophysical. The macrophysical world could be understood

On the Present Status of Quantum Mechanics

Some remarks on the mentalistic reformulation of the measurement problem. A reply to S. Gao

Counterfactuals in Quantum Mechanics

Quantum Theory: What is it about?

What does Quantum Mechanics Tell us about Time?

Hiding a collapse mechanism inside the standard model

Primitive ontology and quantum state in the GRW matter density theory

Particle creation as the quantum condition for probabilistic events to occur Physics Letters A 187 Abstract A 1. Introduction

On the property structure of realist collapse interpretations of quantum mechanics and the so-called counting anomaly

arxiv:quant-ph/ v1 19 Oct 1995

Quantum Theory and the Many- Worlds Interpretation. David Wallace (Balliol College, Oxford) LSE, October 2014

From No-signaling to Spontaneous Localization Theories: Remembering GianCarlo Ghirardi

Is quantum linear superposition exact on all energy scales? A unique case study with flavour oscillating systems

Wave function collapse

Quantum Mechanics: Interpretation and Philosophy

Some Remarks on Wave Function Monism

On Spontaneous Wave Function Collapse and Quantum Field Theory

Logical difficulty from combining counterfactuals in the GHZ-Bell theorems

Where is quantum theory headed?

ON THE POSSIBILITY OF NONLINEAR QUANTUM EVOLUTION AND SUPERLUMINAL COMMUNICATION

ON THE FAITHFUL INTERPRETATION OF PURE WAVE MECHANICS

Counterfactuals in Quantum Mechanics arxiv: v1 [quant-ph] 4 Sep 2007

Topic 10: Bohm s Theory

A possible quantum basis of panpsychism

Topic 2: The mathematical formalism and the standard way of thin

From Bohmian Mechanics to Bohmian Quantum Gravity. Antonio Vassallo Instytut Filozofii UW Section de Philosophie UNIL

Phil Notes #7: Time Travel

Curriculum vitae of Roderich Tumulka

Four Tails Problems for Dynamical Collapse Theories

COPENHAGEN INTERPRETATION:

Deep Metaphysical Indeterminacy

Incompatibility Paradoxes

DEEP METAPHYSICAL INDETERMINACY

QUANTUM HUMEANISM, OR: PHYSICALISM WITHOUT PROPERTIES

QUANTUM MECHANICS AND 3N-DIMENSIONAL SPACE. November 22, 2004

On the possibility of nonlinear quantum evolution and superluminal communication

Collapse or no collapse? What is the best ontology of quantum mechanics in the primitive ontology framework?

Compendium of Quantum Physics

Quantum structure and spacetime

Solving the Einstein Podolsky Rosen puzzle: The origin of non-locality in Aspect-type experiments

arxiv: v2 [quant-ph] 24 May 2018

Bohmian Mechanics. Detlef Dürr, Sheldon Goldstein, Roderich Tumulka, and Nino Zanghì. December 31, 2004

The hybrid-epistemic model of quantum mechanics and the solution to the measurement problem

Logical difficulty from combining counterfactuals in the GHZ-Bell theorems

Protective Measurement: A Paradigm Shift in Understanding Quantum Mechanics

Evidence and Theory in Physics. Tim Maudlin, NYU Evidence in the Natural Sciences, May 30, 2014

arxiv: v1 [quant-ph] 15 Mar 2016

Many Worlds: Quantum Theory and Reality? IÑAKI SAN PEDRO 1

Bohmian Quantum Mechanics and the Finite Square Potential Barrier

ON THE NOTION OF PRIMITIVE ONTOLOGY. Andrea Oldofredi Université de Lausanne MCMP (LMU) 29 Oct. 2014

A General Argument Against the Universal Validity of the Superposition Principle

arxiv:quant-ph/ v1 28 Sep 2005

Time in Bohmian Mechanics

INTRODUCTORY NOTES ON QUANTUM COMPUTATION

Cosmological quantum fluctuations from the

On the origin of probability in quantum mechanics

Instant Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics

Violation of the Born Rule: Implications for the Classical Electromagnetic Field. R. E. Kastner 1 16 Aprll 2016

Protective Measurement: A Paradigm Shift in Understanding Quantum Mechanics

Time-Symmetrized Counterfactuals in Quantum Theory 1

Bell s theorem and the issue of determinism and indeterminism

4. The twin paradox. HPS/Philosophy 2626 Philosophy of Physics Spring Part I: Space and Time

Journal of Theoretics

Einstein-Podolsky-Rosen paradox and Bell s inequalities

Photons uncertainty removes Einstein-Podolsky-Rosen paradox. Abstract

Entanglement and Disentanglement in Relativistic Quantum Mechanics

A Classification of Hidden-Variable Properties

A No-Go Result on Common Cause Approaches via Hardy s Paradox

Backward evolving quantum states

Quantum Mechanics as a Principle Theory

Interpretations of Quantum Mechanics

Is the electron s charge 2e? A problem of the de Broglie-Bohm theory

Primitive Ontology in a Nutshell

Transcription:

266 GRW Theory (Ghirardi, Rimini, Weber Model of Quantum Mechanics) Roman Frigg: GRW Theory, in: Daniel Greenberger, Brigitte Secondary Falkenburg, Roman Frigg: Literature Klaus GRW Hentschel Theory, and in: Daniel Friedel Greenberger, Weinert (eds.): Brigitte Compendium Falkenburg, of Klaus Quantum Hentschel Physics: and Friedel Concepts, Weinert Experiments, (eds.): Compendium History and Philosophy. of Quantum 2. Physics: R.M. Cooke, Concepts, M, Keane, Experiments, and W. Moran: An History Elementary and Proof Philosophy. of Gleason sspringer:berlin Theorem, Math. Heidelberg and Proc. Camb. Phil. and Soc. Berlin: 98, 117 28 Springer, (1985); reprinted 2009, in 266-270. [4], 321 46 Heidelberg, 2009, 266-270. 3. C. Hooker (ed.): The Logico-Algebraic Approach to Quantum Mechanics (Reidel, Dordrecht, 1975) 4. R.I.G. Hughes: The Structure and Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics (Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA 1989) 5. S. Kochen and E. Specker: The Problem of Hidden Variables in Quantum Mechanics, J. Math. Mech. 17, 59 87 (1967); reprinted in [3], 293 328 6. M. Redhead: Incompleteness, Nonlocality, and Realism: A Prolegomenon to the Philosophy of Quantum Mechanics. (Clarendon Press, Oxford, 1987) Grover s Algorithm See quantum computation. GRW Theory (Ghirardi, Rimini, Weber Model of Quantum Mechanics) Roman Frigg Consider a toy system consisting of a marble and box. The marble has two states, in and out, corresponding to the marble being inside or outside the box. These states are eigenvectors of the operator ˆB, measuring whether the marble is inside or outside the box. The formalism of quantum mechanics (QM) has it that not only in and out themselves, but any superposition m = a in + b out where a and b are complex numbers such that a 2 + b 2 = 1, can be the state of the marble. What are the properties of the marble in such a state? This question is commonly answered by appeal to the so-called Eigenstate-Eigenvalue Rule (EER): An observable Ô has a well-defined value for a quantum a system S in state if, and only if, is an eigenstate of Ô. Since in and out are eigenstates of ˆB, EER yields that the marble is either inside (or outside) the box if its state is in (or out ). However, states like m defy interpretation on the basis of EER and we have to conclude that if the marble is in such a state then it is neither inside nor outside the box. This is unacceptable because we know from experience that marbles are always either inside or outside boxes. Reconciling this fact of everyday experience with the quantum formalism is the infamous measurement problem. See also Bohmian mechanics; Measurement theory; Metaphysics in Quantum Mechanics; Modal Interpretation; Objectification; Projection Postulate.

GRW Theory (Ghirardi, Rimini, Weber Model of Quantum Mechanics) 267 Standard quantum mechanics solves this problem, following a suggestion of von Neumann s, by postulating that upon measurement the system s state is instantaneously reduced to one of the eigenstates of the measured observable, which leaves the system in a state that can be interpreted on the basis of EER ( Measurement Theory). However, it is generally accepted that this proposal is ultimately unacceptable. What defines a measurement? At what stage of the measurement process does the wave function collapse take place (trigger problem)? And why should the properties of a system depend on actions of observers? GRW Theory (sometimes also GRW model ) is a suggestion to overcome these difficulties (the theory has been introduced in Ghirardi et al. [1]; Bell [6] and Ghirardi [10] provide short and non-technical presentations of the theory; for a comprehensive discussion of the entire research programme to which GRW Theory belongs see Bassi and Ghirardi [5]). The leading idea of the theory is to eradicate observers from the picture and view state reduction as a process that occurs as a consequence of the basic laws of nature. The theory achieves this by adding to the fundamental equation of QM, the Schrödinger equation, a stochastic term which describes the state reduction occurring in the system. (For this reason GRW theory is not, strictly speaking, an interpretation of QM; it is a quantum theory in its own right). A system governed by GRW theory evolves according to the Schrödinger equation all the time except when a state reduction, a so-called hit, occurs (hits are also referred to as hittings, perturbations, spontaneous localisations, collapses, and jumps ). A crucial assumption of the theory is that hits occur at the level of the micro constituents of a system (in the above example at the level of the atoms that make up the marble). The crucial question then is: when do hits occur and what exactly happens when they occur? GRW Theory posits that the occurrence of hits constitutes a Poisson process. Generally speaking, Poisson processes are processes characterised in terms of the number of occurrences of a particular type of event in a certain interval of time τ, for instance the number of people passing through a certain street during time τ. These events are Poisson distributed if the probability that the number of events occurring during τ, n, takes value m is given by p(n = m) = e λτ (λτ) m /m!, where λ is the parameter of the distribution. One can show that λ is also the mean value of the distribution and hence it can be interpreted as the average number of events occurring per unit time. GRW theory sets λ = 10 16 s 1 and posits that this is a new constant of nature. Hence, in a macroscopic system that is made up of about 10 23 atoms there are on average 10 7 hits per second. A hit transforms the system s state into another state according to a probabilistic algorithm that takes the position basis as the privileged basis (in that the reduction process leads to a localisation of the system s state in the position basis). Let S be state of the entire system (e.g. the marble) before the hit occurs. When the kth particle, say, is hit the state is instantaneously transformed into another, more localised state: S S hit = L k,c S Lk,c S. G

268 GRW Theory (Ghirardi, Rimini, Weber Model of Quantum Mechanics) L k,c, the localisation operator, that has the shape of a Gaussian (a bell-shaped curve) centred around c, which is chosen at random according to the distribution p k (c) = Lk,c S 2 ; the width σ of the Gaussian is also a new constant of nature, and it is of the magnitude 10 7 m. The choice of this distribution assures that the predictions of GRW Theory coincide almost always with those of standard QM (there are domains in which the two theories do not yield the same predictions, but these are (so far) beyond the reach of experimental test; see Rimini [15]). Due to the mathematical structure of QM (more specifically, due to the fact that S is the tensor product of the states of all its micro constituents) the hits at the micro level amplify : if the marble is in state m and kth particle gets hit, then the entire state is transformed into a highly localised state, i.e. all terms except one in the superposition are suppressed. This is GRW s solution of the measurement problem. A macro system gets hit 10 7 times per second and hence superpositions are suppressed almost immediately; micro systems are not hit very often and hence retain their quantum properties for a very long time. This proposal faces two important formal problems. First, the wave function of systems of identical particles has to be either symmetrical (in the case of Bosons) or antisymmetrical (in the case of Fermions), and remain so over the course of time. GRW theory violates this requirement in that wave functions that are symmetric (or antisymmetric) at some time need not be (and generally are not) symmetric (or antisymmetric) at later times. Second, although hits occur at the level of the system s wave function, the fundamental equation of the theory is expressed in terms of the density matrix. This strikes physicists as odd and one would like to have an equation governing the evolution of the wave function itself. Both difficulties are overcome within the so-called CSL model (for continuous spontaneous localization ) introduced in Pearle [3] and Ghirardi et al. [2]. The model belongs to the same family of proposals as GRW theory in that it proposes to solve the measurement problem by an appeal to a spontaneous localisation processes. The essential difference is that the discontinuous hits of GRW theory are replaced by a continuous stochastic evolution of the state vector in Hilbert space (similar to a diffusion process). Another serious problem concerns the nature of GRW hits. Unlike the state reduction that von Neumann introduced into standard QM, the hits of GRW theory do not leave the system s state in an exact position eigenstate; the post-hit state is highly peaked, but nevertheless fails to be a precise position eigenstate. This is illustrated schematically in Fig. 1. Hence, strictly speaking the post-hit states are not interpretable on the basis of EER and we are back where we started; this problem is also know as the tails problem (see Albert and Loewer [4]). Common wisdom avoids this conclusion by pointing out that GRW post-hit states are close to eigenstates and positing that being close to an eigenstate is as good as being an eigenstate. This has been challenged by Lewis [12], who presents an argument for the conclusion that this move has the undesirable consequence that arithmetic does not apply to ordinary macroscopic objects. For a critical discussion of this argument see Frigg [12]. What is the correct interpretation of the theory? That is, what, if anything, does the theory describe? The answer to this question is less obvious than it might

GRW Theory (Ghirardi, Rimini, Weber Model of Quantum Mechanics) 269 Fig. 1 GRW hit seem. Clifton and Monton [7] regard it as a wave function only theory according to which the world literally is just the wave function that the theory describes. Monton [14] later criticises this view as mistaken and suggests a variation of the mass density interpretation originally proposed by Ghirardi et al. [11]. Lewis [12] points out that all versions of the mass density interpretation lead to a violation of common sense and should hence not be regarded as a problem-free alternative. How should we interpret the probabilities that the theory postulates in its hit mechanism? Are they best interpreted as propensities, frequencies, Humean chances, or yet something else? Or should the quest for such an interpretation be rejected as ill-conceived? This question is discussed in Frigg and Hoefer [9] who come to the conclusion that GRW probabilies can be understood either as single case propensities or as Humean chances, while all other options are ruled out by GRW Theory itself. See also Metaphysics in Quantum Mechanics; Quantum State Diffusion Theory. G Literature 1. G. C. Ghirardi, A. Rimini, T. Weber: Unified Dynamics for Microscopic and Macroscopic Systems. Physical Review 34D, 470 91 (1986) 2. G. C. Ghirardi, P. Pearle, A. Rimini: Markov Processes in Hilbert Space and Spontaneous Localization of Systems of Identical Particles. Physical Review 42A, 78 89 (1990) 3. P. Pearle: Combining Stochastic Dynamical State-Vector Reduction with Spontaneous Localization. Physical Review 39A, 2277 2289 (1989) 4. D. Z. Albert, B. Loewer: Tails of Schrödinger s Cat. In Perspectives on Quantum Reality: Non-Relativistic, Relativistic, and Field-Theoretic, ed. by R. Clifton (Kluwer, Dordrecht 1995, 81 92) 5. A. Bassi, G. C. Ghirardi: Dynamical Reduction Models. Physics Reports 379, 257 426 (2003) 6. J. S. Bell: Are There Quantum Jumps? In Speakable and unspeakable in quantum mechanics, ed. J. S. Bell (Cambridge University Press, Cambridge 1987, 201 212) 7. R. Clifton, B. Monton: Losing Your Marbles in Wavefunction Collapse Theories. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 50, 697 717 (1999) 8. R. Frigg: On the Property Structure of Realist Collapse Interpretations of Quantum Mechanics and the So-Called Counting Anomaly. International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 17, 43 57 (2003) 9. R. Frigg, C. Hoefer: Probability in GRW Theory. Forthcoming in Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 38 (2007)

270 GRW Theory (Ghirardi, Rimini, Weber Model of Quantum Mechanics) 10. G. C. Ghirardi: Collapse Theories. The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Spring 2002 Edition), URL = http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2002/contents.html 11. G. C. Ghirardi, R. Grassi, F. Benatti: Describing the Macroscopic World: Closing the Circle Within the Dynamic Reduction Program. Foundations of Physics 25, 5 38 (1995) 12. P. J. Lewis: Quantum Mechanics, Orthogonality, and Counting. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 48, 313 328 (1997) 13. P. J. Lewis: Interpreting Spontaneous Collapse Theories. Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 36, 165 180 (2005) 14. B. Monton: The Problem of Ontology for Spontaneous Collapse Theories. Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 35, 407 421 (2004) 15. A. Rimini: Spontaneous Localization and Superconductivity. In Advances in quantumphenomena, ed. by E. Beltrametti et al. (Plenum, New York 1995, 321 333)