Subjective multi-prior probability: a representation of a partial l

Similar documents
Subjective multi-prior probability: A representation of a partial likelihood relation

Dominance and Admissibility without Priors

Questions in Decision Theory

Lecture 3: Probability Measures - 2

Incomplete Preferences under Uncertainty: Indecisiveness in Beliefs vs. Tastes

Is it Possible to Define Subjective Probabilities in Purely Behavioral Terms? A Comment on Epstein-Zhang (2001)

Maxmin expected utility as resulting from information on others preferences

A Note on Cancellation Axioms for Comparative Probability

September 2007, France

Reverse Bayesianism: A Generalization

Conditional and Dynamic Preferences

A SUBJECTIVE APPROACH TO QUANTUM PROBABILITY. March 9, 2005

Measures. 1 Introduction. These preliminary lecture notes are partly based on textbooks by Athreya and Lahiri, Capinski and Kopp, and Folland.

Lexicographic Refinements in the Context of Possibilistic Decision Theory

Worst-Case Expected Utility

Inferring Probability Comparisons

Action-Independent Subjective Expected Utility without States of the World

Numerical representations of binary relations with thresholds: A brief survey 1

Decision Making Under Uncertainty. First Masterclass

1.1. MEASURES AND INTEGRALS

Rationality and Uncertainty

Axioms of Kleene Algebra

On minimal models of the Region Connection Calculus

Anscombe & Aumann Expected Utility Betting and Insurance

Great Expectations. Part I: On the Customizability of Generalized Expected Utility*

212a1214Daniell s integration theory.

RS Chapter 1 Random Variables 6/5/2017. Chapter 1. Probability Theory: Introduction

Sets and Motivation for Boolean algebra

A Theorem for Bayesian Group Decisions by Ralph L. Keeney and Robert Nau Fuqua School of Business Duke University Durham, NC

Hierarchy among Automata on Linear Orderings

Tomáš Madaras Congruence classes

Constructive Decision Theory

The Logic of Knightian Games

a + b = b + a and a b = b a. (a + b) + c = a + (b + c) and (a b) c = a (b c). a (b + c) = a b + a c and (a + b) c = a c + b c.

Properties of the Integers

1. Introduction to commutative rings and fields

1. Introduction to commutative rings and fields

ABOUT THE CLASS AND NOTES ON SET THEORY

BOOLEAN ALGEBRA INTRODUCTION SUBSETS

Uncertainty & Decision

THE SURE-THING PRINCIPLE AND P2

Section Summary. Relations and Functions Properties of Relations. Combining Relations

STAT 7032 Probability Spring Wlodek Bryc

The Uniform Distributions Puzzle

Ambiguity under Growing Awareness

An additively separable representation in the Savage framework

An Introduction to Bayesian Reasoning

Origins of Probability Theory

Measure and Integration: Concepts, Examples and Exercises. INDER K. RANA Indian Institute of Technology Bombay India

Axiomatic Foundations of Expected Utility. and Subjective Probability

On maxitive integration

Constructive Decision Theory

Statistical Inference

DECISIONS UNDER UNCERTAINTY

Economics 204 Fall 2011 Problem Set 1 Suggested Solutions

The uniform distributions puzzle

The Rational Core of Preference Relations

Some Basic Notations Of Set Theory

Nets and filters (are better than sequences)

Sets. Alice E. Fischer. CSCI 1166 Discrete Mathematics for Computing Spring, Outline Sets An Algebra on Sets Summary

A survey of the theory of coherent lower previsions

An Axiomatic Model of Reference Dependence under Uncertainty. Yosuke Hashidate

Pre-probabilistic sophistication. Osamu Kada. July, 2009

CHAPTER 7. Connectedness

Independence for Full Conditional Measures, Graphoids and Bayesian Networks

Regret aversion and opportunity dependence

THE SURE-THING PRINCIPLE AND P2

GENERALIZED DIFFERENCE POSETS AND ORTHOALGEBRAS. 0. Introduction

CALIFORNIA INSTITUTE OF TECHNOLOGY

A BOREL SOLUTION TO THE HORN-TARSKI PROBLEM. MSC 2000: 03E05, 03E20, 06A10 Keywords: Chain Conditions, Boolean Algebras.

Preference, Choice and Utility

(c) For each α R \ {0}, the mapping x αx is a homeomorphism of X.

Statistical Theory 1

3. FORCING NOTION AND GENERIC FILTERS

Definition: A binary relation R from a set A to a set B is a subset R A B. Example:

Agreeing to disagree: The non-probabilistic case

Recitation 7: Uncertainty. Xincheng Qiu

Construction of a general measure structure

Chapter 4. Measure Theory. 1. Measure Spaces

Lecture 2. Econ August 11

Continuity and completeness of strongly independent preorders

Part III. 10 Topological Space Basics. Topological Spaces

A Crash Course in Topological Groups

Measurable Ambiguity. with Wolfgang Pesendorfer. August 2009

Comment on The Veil of Public Ignorance

Uniform Sources of Uncertainty for Subjective Probabilities and

Extendibility of Choquet rational preferences on generalized lotteries

Second-Order Expected Utility

Chapter 2 Classical Probability Theories

The Measure Problem. Louis de Branges Department of Mathematics Purdue University West Lafayette, IN , USA

Decision Making under Uncertainty and Subjective. Probabilities

MTH 309 Supplemental Lecture Notes Based on Robert Messer, Linear Algebra Gateway to Mathematics

CSE 20 DISCRETE MATH. Winter

Subjective Expected Utility in Games

What are the recursion theoretic properties of a set of axioms? Understanding a paper by William Craig Armando B. Matos

18.175: Lecture 2 Extension theorems, random variables, distributions

We are going to discuss what it means for a sequence to converge in three stages: First, we define what it means for a sequence to converge to zero

Chapter 1. Measure Spaces. 1.1 Algebras and σ algebras of sets Notation and preliminaries

1 Axiomatic Bargaining Theory

Transcription:

Subjective multi-prior probability: a representation of a partial likelihood relation TAU, 22-11-2011

Outline of the talk: Motivation Background Examples Axioms Result Related literature Outline of the proof

Likelihood relation Motivation - Likelihood relation Why is it interesting to explore likelihood comparisons among events?

Likelihood relation Motivation - Likelihood relation Why is it interesting to explore likelihood comparisons among events? Examples: IAEA reports, US intelligence reports, assessments of market trends supplied by committees of experts or consulting firms, likelihood estimations of natural events.

Likelihood relation Motivation - Likelihood relation Why is it interesting to explore likelihood comparisons among events? Examples: IAEA reports, US intelligence reports, assessments of market trends supplied by committees of experts or consulting firms, likelihood estimations of natural events. Characteristics: Output = likelihood judgements among events. Assessments rely on objective data. Statements of the form event A is more likely than event B are key in producing the output.

Partial relation Motivation - Partial relation In the examples: ambiguity (arising from lack of information or knowledge), multiple opinions.

Partial relation Motivation - Partial relation In the examples: ambiguity (arising from lack of information or knowledge), multiple opinions. Implication: indecisiveness among certain pairs of events; There is no way to compare likelihood of events, and judge whether event A is at least as likely as event B or vice versa.

Partial relation Motivation - Partial relation In the examples: ambiguity (arising from lack of information or knowledge), multiple opinions. Implication: indecisiveness among certain pairs of events; There is no way to compare likelihood of events, and judge whether event A is at least as likely as event B or vice versa. Some comparisons among events may thus be left undetermined.

Axiomatization Motivation - Axiomatic treatment Why axioms, and why formulated on an at least as likely as binary relation over events?

Axiomatization Motivation - Axiomatic treatment Why axioms, and why formulated on an at least as likely as binary relation over events? The notion of at least as likely as judgement calls among events seem relatively easy to grasp. Convinces to use a functional form, which may be easier to formulate. Subscribes means to complete some of the comparisons among pairs of events. Lends normative justification to methods already using the functional form (later).

Goal Motivation - Our goal Our goal: suggest an axiomatic treatment of an at least as likely as relation over events, that does not have to be complete. What would be an adequate probabilistic representation of such a relation?...

Likelihood relation Background - Likelihood relation Ramsey (1931), De Finetti (1931,1937) and Savage (1954): Claimed that probability is a subjective notion, emerging from likelihood comparisons among events, and expressing an individual s degree of confidence in the occurrence of events. Worked in a purely subjective environment, with no exogenous probabilities assumed. Formulated conditions on a likelihood relation over events that imply that the relation may be represented by a probability measure.

Partial relation Background - Partial relation Critique of the completeness assumption: Von-Neumann and Morgenstern (1944) and Aumann (1962): - Preference over lotteries - Questioned completeness on descriptive as well as normative grounds Models where alternatives are mappings from events to consequences: - Criticized completeness based on ambiguity. - Most expressed ambiguity through an inability to formulate one prior probability, and described belief using a set of prior probabilities.

Conclusion Conclusion The same ambiguity considerations seem to apply for an at least as likely as relation over events.

Conclusion Conclusion The same ambiguity considerations seem to apply for an at least as likely as relation over events. If we are to represent a partial relation over events, a single prior probability will not do.

Conclusion Conclusion (cont.) In order to represent a partial at least as likely as relation over events, we employ a set of prior probabilities. Our result: A binary relation over events,, satisfies axioms..., iff, there exists a set of prior probabilities, P, such that for any two events A and B, A B µ(a) µ(b) for all µ P.

Example Let S = [0, 1), Σ the algebra generated by all intervals [a, b) contained in [0, 1), and the likelihood relation over Σ defined by: A B λ(a \ B) 3λ(B \ A). A set of probabilities P representing : For E Σ such that λ(e) = 1 4, let π E be the probability measure defined by the density: { 2 s E f E (s) = 2 3 s / E. Let P be the convex and closed set generated by all measures π E.

Notations S a nonempty set, with typical elements s, t,.... Σ an algebra of events over S, with typical elements A, B,.... 1 A the indicator function of event A. A binary relation over Σ. A statement A B is interpreted as A is at least as likely as B. A probability measure P agrees with if A B P(A) P(B). A probability measure P almost agrees with if A B P(A) P(B).

Axiomatization - Background De Finetti introduced four basic postulates: Complete Order: The relation is complete and transitive. Cancellation: For any three events, A, B and C, such that A C = B C =, A B A C B C. Positivity: For every event A, A. Non Triviality: S.

Axiomatization - Background De Finetti introduced four basic postulates: Complete Order: The relation is complete and transitive. Cancellation: For any three events, A, B and C, such that A C = B C =, A B A C B C. Positivity: For every event A, A. Non Triviality: S. Cancellation: any event has the same marginal contribution of likelihood, unrelated to other, disjoint events.

Axiomatization - Background De Finetti introduced four basic postulates: Complete Order: The relation is complete and transitive. Cancellation: For any three events, A, B and C, such that A C = B C =, A B A C B C. Positivity: For every event A, A. Non Triviality: S. Cancellation: any event has the same marginal contribution of likelihood, unrelated to other, disjoint events. The four assumptions are necessary for the relation to have an agreeing probability.

Axiomatization - Background De Finetti introduced four basic postulates: Complete Order: The relation is complete and transitive. Cancellation: For any three events, A, B and C, such that A C = B C =, A B A C B C. Positivity: For every event A, A. Non Triviality: S. Cancellation: any event has the same marginal contribution of likelihood, unrelated to other, disjoint events. The four assumptions are necessary for the relation to have an agreeing probability. De Finetti asked: are they also sufficient for the relation to have an agreeing probability, or even an almost agreeing probability?

Axiomatization - Background (cont.) The answer NO was given by Kraft, Pratt and Seidenberg (1959). Kraft et al., Scott (1964), Kranz et al. (1971) and Narens (1974), suggested a strengthening of Cancellation: Finite Cancellation For two sequences of events, (A i ) n i=1 and (B i) n i=1, If n 1 Ai (s) = i=1 n 1 Bi (s) for all s S, i=1 and A i B i for i = 1,..., n 1, then B n A n.

Axiomatization - Background (cont.) n i=1 1 A i (s) = n i=1 1 B i (s) for all s S: each state appears the same number of times in each sequence.

Axiomatization - Background (cont.) n i=1 1 A i (s) = n i=1 1 B i (s) for all s S: each state appears the same number of times in each sequence. + the same marginal contribution of likelihood

Axiomatization - Background (cont.) n i=1 1 A i (s) = n i=1 1 B i (s) for all s S: each state appears the same number of times in each sequence. + the same marginal contribution of likelihood it cannot be that the A-sequence weighs more than the B-sequence.

Axiomatization - Background (cont.) n i=1 1 A i (s) = n i=1 1 B i (s) for all s S: each state appears the same number of times in each sequence. + the same marginal contribution of likelihood it cannot be that the A-sequence weighs more than the B-sequence. likelihood weights - double-entry booking: credit column debit column A 1 B 1...... A n 1 B n 1

Axiomatization - Background (cont.) n i=1 1 A i (s) = n i=1 1 B i (s) for all s S: each state appears the same number of times in each sequence. + the same marginal contribution of likelihood it cannot be that the A-sequence weighs more than the B-sequence. likelihood weights - double-entry booking: credit column debit column A 1 B 1...... A n 1 B n 1 B n A n

Axiomatization - Main axiom Our main axiom, Generalized Finite Cancellation (GFC), is a simple extension. P4. Generalized Finite Cancellation: For two sequences of events, (A i ) n i=1 integer k N, and (B i) n i=1, and an n 1 n 1 If 1 Ai (s) + k1 An (s) = 1 Bi (s) + k1 Bn (s) for all s S, i=1 i=1 and A i B i for i = 1,..., n 1, then B n A n.

Axiomatization - Additional basic axioms P1. Reflexivity: For all A Σ, A A. P2. Positivity: For all A Σ, A. P3. Non Triviality: ( S).

Finite case - Result Theorem Suppose that S is finite, and let be a binary relation over events in S. Then statements (i) and (ii) below are equivalent: (i) satisfies Reflexivity, Positivity, Non Triviality and Generalized Finite Cancellation. (ii) There exists a nonempty set P of additive probability measures over events in S, such that for every A, B S, A B µ(a) µ(b) for every µ P.

Finite case - Result (cont.) Remarks: The set of prior probabilities need not be unique. Even if completeness is added, uniqueness is not implied. A possible set of priors to consider - the maximal w.r.t inclusion set = the union of all representing sets. Contains all the almost agreeing probabilities.

Finite case - Example Let S = {H, T } and Σ = 2 S. Suppose that H T. Any probability measure of the sort (H : p ; T : 1 p), for 0.5 p 1, represents the relation.

Finite case - Example Let S = {H, T } and Σ = 2 S. Suppose that H T. Any probability measure of the sort (H : p ; T : 1 p), for 0.5 p 1, represents the relation. No uniqueness, even in the complete case.

Infinite case - Richness assumption Definition For two events A, B Σ, the notation A B states that there exists a finite partition {G 1,..., G r } of S, such that A \ G i B G j for all i, j. P5. Non Atomicity: If (A B) then there exists a finite partition of A c, {A 1,..., A m}, such that for all i, A i and (A A i B).

Definition A set P of probability measures is said to be uniformly absolutely continuous, if: (a) For any event B, µ(b) > 0 µ (B) > 0 for every pair of probabilities µ, µ P. (b) For every ε > 0, there exists a finite partition {G 1,..., G r } of S, such that for all j, µ(g j ) < ε for all µ P. In particular, every probability measure µ in P is locally dense: for every event B, the set {µ(a) A B} is dense in [0, µ(b)].

Infinite case - Result Theorem Let be a binary relation over Σ. Then statements (i) and (ii) below are equivalent: (i) satisfies axioms P1-P5. (ii) There exists a nonempty, uniformly absolutely continuous set P of additive probability measures over Σ, such that for every A, B Σ, A B µ(a) µ(b) for every µ P.

Background - Related literature Bewley (2002) Alternatives are mappings from an abstract set of states to lotteries over an abstract set of consequences (as in Anscombe and Aumann, 1963). Axiomatized a partial relation that admits a multi-prior expected utility representation: for every pair of alternatives f and g, f g E µ (u(f )) E µ (u(g)) for every µ P, for a unique convex and closed set of priors P and a vn-m utility function u. Axioms = AA axioms minus completeness ; Result = multi-prior EU instead of (a single prior) EU.

Background - Related literature (cont.) Bewley (2002) Bewley s model with only two consequences (better/worse) yields an at least as likely as relation over events.

Background - Related literature (cont.) Bewley (2002) Bewley s model with only two consequences (better/worse) yields an at least as likely as relation over events. Downside: his setup is not purely subjective, as it employs mixtures with exogenous probabilities.

Background - Related literature (cont.) Ghirardato et al (2003) Alternatives are mappings from an abstract set of states to an abstract set of consequences = purely subjective environment (no exogenous probabilities). An á la Bewley result.

Background - Related literature (cont.) Ghirardato et al (2003) Alternatives are mappings from an abstract set of states to an abstract set of consequences = purely subjective environment (no exogenous probabilities). An á la Bewley result. Downside: Impossible to apply the model for two consequences alone, hence cannot be applied to identify solely an at least as likely relation over events.

Background - Related literature (cont.) Nehring (2009) The primitive is a relation over events, not multi-valued alternatives. No exogenous probabilities assumed. A multi-prior probability result: there exists a set of prior probabilities, P, such that for any two events A and B, A B µ(a) µ(b) for all µ P. for a unique convex and closed set P.

Background - Related literature (cont.) Nehring (2009) Downside: explicit assumption that any event can be divided into two equally-likely events. That is, Implications: for any event A there exists an event B A, such that µ(b) = µ(a)/2 for all µ P. In particular, all the priors agree on a rich algebra of events: the one generated by dividing the entire space into n 2 n equally likely events, for any integer n. (Note: not satisfied in the example presented earlier.) Result cannot be applied to a finite state space.

Outline of the proof Define the closed convex cone generated by { 1 A 1 B A B }. Show that if 1 A 1 B = n i=1 α i(1 Ai 1 Bi ) for α i > 0, A i B i, then A B This is precisely GFC (first for rational coefficients, then for real coefficients). In the finite case, the convex cone is generated by a finite number of indicator differences, therefore is closed. A separation theorem yields the result. In the infinite case, Non Atomicity yields that there cannot be 1 A 1 B on the boundary of the cone with (A B). A separation theorem again yields the result.