INSEPARABLE SEQUENCES AND FORCING

Similar documents
Lusin sequences under CH and under Martin s Axiom

Lusin sequences under CH and under Martin s Axiom

A NEW LINDELOF SPACE WITH POINTS G δ

TOPOLOGIES GENERATED BY CLOSED INTERVALS. 1. Introduction. Novi Sad J. Math. Vol. 35, No. 1, 2005,

ITERATIONS WITH MIXED SUPPORT

GAMES ON BOOLEAN ALGEBRAS

FORCING WITH SEQUENCES OF MODELS OF TWO TYPES

BPFA and BAAFA. Their equiconsistency and their nonequivalence. Thilo Weinert. February 4, 2009

GREGORY TREES, THE CONTINUUM, AND MARTIN S AXIOM

CCC Forcing and Splitting Reals

SELF-DUAL UNIFORM MATROIDS ON INFINITE SETS

The Bounded Axiom A Forcing Axiom

A DIRECT PROOF OF THE FIVE ELEMENT BASIS THEOREM

Independence of Boolean algebras and forcing

Distributivity of Quotients of Countable Products of Boolean Algebras

The Proper Forcing Axiom: a tutorial

Topology Proceedings. COPYRIGHT c by Topology Proceedings. All rights reserved.

FORCING AXIOMS AND THE CONTINUUM HYPOTHESIS, PART II: TRANSCENDING ω 1 -SEQUENCES OF REAL NUMBERS

On the Length of Borel Hierarchies

Annals of Pure and Applied Logic

The Arkhangel skiĭ Tall problem under Martin s Axiom

The axiom of choice and two-point sets in the plane

Forcing Axioms and Inner Models of Set Theory

M ath. Res. Lett. 15 (2008), no. 00, NN c International Press 2008 A UNIVERSAL ARONSZAJN LINE. Justin Tatch Moore. 1.

ON A THEOREM OF BANACH AND KURATOWSKI AND K-LUSIN SETS. Tomek Bartoszyński

COMPLETE NORMALITY AND COUNTABLE COMPACTNESS

Jónsson posets and unary Jónsson algebras

A variant of Namba Forcing

NAMBA FORCING, WEAK APPROXIMATION, AND GUESSING

A NOTE ON THE EIGHTFOLD WAY

SET MAPPING REFLECTION

UNIFORMIZING LADDER SYSTEM COLORINGS AND THE RECTANGLE REFINING PROPERTY

Cardinal characteristics, projective wellorders and large continuum

PROPER FORCING REMASTERED

SEPARATION IN CLASS FORCING EXTENSIONS. Contents

Combinatorial dichotomies and cardinal invariants

Löwenheim-Skolem Theorems, Countable Approximations, and L ω. David W. Kueker (Lecture Notes, Fall 2007)

An introduction to OCA

Tallness and Level by Level Equivalence and Inequivalence

An Iterated Forcing Extension In Which All Aleph-1 Dense Sets of Reals Are Isomorphic

SMALL SUBSETS OF THE REALS AND TREE FORCING NOTIONS

CH AND THE MOORE-MROWKA PROBLEM

SOME REMARKS ON NON-SPECIAL COHERENT ARONSZAJN TREES


BOUNDING THE CONSISTENCY STRENGTH OF A FIVE ELEMENT LINEAR BASIS

Diagonalize This. Iian Smythe. Department of Mathematics Cornell University. Olivetti Club November 26, 2013

Tutorial 1.3: Combinatorial Set Theory. Jean A. Larson (University of Florida) ESSLLI in Ljubljana, Slovenia, August 4, 2011

Ultrafilters with property (s)

EXTERNAL AUTOMORPHISMS OF ULTRAPRODUCTS OF FINITE MODELS

Appalachian Set Theory Workshop on Coherent Sequences Lectures by Stevo Todorcevic Notes taken by Roberto Pichardo Mendoza

VARIATIONS FOR SEPARATING CLUB GUESSING PRINCIPLES

A FIVE ELEMENT BASIS FOR THE UNCOUNTABLE LINEAR ORDERS

Slow P -point Ultrafilters

MORE ABOUT SPACES WITH A SMALL DIAGONAL

AMS regional meeting Bloomington, IN April 1, 2017

PSEUDO P-POINTS AND SPLITTING NUMBER

Weak Choice Principles and Forcing Axioms

TOPOLOGY PROCEEDINGS Volume 28, No. 1, 2004 Pages

MONOTONICALLY COMPACT AND MONOTONICALLY

FORCING (LECTURE NOTES FOR MATH 223S, SPRING 2011)

Increasing δ 1 2 and Namba-style forcing

On the open-open game

The ideal of Sierpiński-Zygmund sets on the plane

PFA(S)[S] and the Arhangel skiĭ-tall Problem

20 Ordinals. Definition A set α is an ordinal iff: (i) α is transitive; and. (ii) α is linearly ordered by. Example 20.2.

Club degrees of rigidity and almost Kurepa trees

TEST GROUPS FOR WHITEHEAD GROUPS

Non-trivial automorphisms from variants of small d

1. Introduction Definition 1.1. For an L ω1,ω-sentence φ, the spectrum of φ is the set

On the Length of Borel Hierarchies

DENSELY k-separable COMPACTA ARE DENSELY SEPARABLE

ALMOST DISJOINT AND INDEPENDENT FAMILIES. 1. introduction. is infinite. Fichtenholz and Kantorovich showed that there is an independent family

Appalachian Set Theory Workshop, May 31, 2008 Lectures by Justin Tatch Moore Notes taken by David Milovich

Forcing notions in inner models

Jónsson Properties for Non-Ordinal Sets Under the Axiom of Determinacy

Between O and Ostaszewski

Topology Proceedings. COPYRIGHT c by Topology Proceedings. All rights reserved.

Diamond, Continuum, and Forcing

Projective well-orderings of the reals and forcing axioms

Silver trees and Cohen reals

COMPACT C-CLOSED SPACES NEED NOT BE SEQUENTIAL

THE LENGTH OF THE FULL HIERARCHY OF NORMS

On The Model Of Hyperrational Numbers With Selective Ultrafilter

Ordering functions. Raphaël Carroy. Hejnice, Czech Republic January 27th, Universität Münster 1/21

ON VAN DOUWEN SPACES AND RETRACTS OF βn

Covering a bounded set of functions by an increasing chain of slaloms

D, such that f(u) = f(v) whenever u = v, has a multiplicative refinement g : [λ] <ℵ 0

TRANSFERING SATURATION, THE FINITE COVER PROPERTY, AND STABILITY

Convergence and submeasures in Boolean algebras

SEPARATING CLUB GUESSING PRINCIPLES IN THE PRESENCE OF FAT FORCING AXIOMS

GROUPS WITH UNBOUNDED POTENTIAL AUTOMORPHISM TOWER HEIGHTS

PCF THEORY AND CARDINAL INVARIANTS OF THE REALS

UNIVERSALITY OF THE LATTICE OF TRANSFORMATION MONOIDS

The modal logic of forcing

Embeddings into P(N)/fin and extension of automorphisms

Maharam Algebras. Equipe de Logique, Université de Paris 7, 2 Place Jussieu, Paris, France

SOME CALKIN ALGEBRAS HAVE OUTER AUTOMORPHISMS

Commentationes Mathematicae Universitatis Carolinae

3. FORCING NOTION AND GENERIC FILTERS

Transcription:

Novi Sad J. Math. Vol. 43, No. 2, 2013, 185-189 INSEPARABLE SEQUENCES AND FORCING Boris Šobot 1 Abstract. An inseparable sequence is an almost disjoint family A ξ : ξ < ω 1 of subsets of ω such that for no D ω there are uncountably many A ξ such that A ξ D is finite and uncountably many A ξ such that A ξ \ D is finite. We investigate under which conditions is an inseparable sequence destroyed by forcing. We translate these conditions into forcing language and use them to obtain several necessary conditions for destroying inseparability. In particular, we prove that in order to get such a notion of forcing with c.c.c. we must assume at least MA, and in order to get such a notion of forcing that is proper we must assume at least PFA. AMS Mathematics Subject Classification (2010): 03E40, 03E20. Key words and phrases: almost disjoint families, inseparable sequences, forcing. 1. Introduction A family A = A ξ : ξ < ω 1 of infinite subsets of ω is an almost disjoint family if A ξ A ζ < ℵ 0 for all ξ ζ. An inseparable sequence is an almost disjoint family such that there is no D ω such that X [ω 1 ] ℵ 1 ξ X A ξ D < ℵ 0 Y [ω 1 ] ℵ1 ξ Y A ξ \ D < ℵ 0. Since there are only ℵ 0 finite subsets of ω, we can find uncountable subsets of X and Y that enumerate subsets with same intersections and differences with D, and replace the above conditions by (1) (2) S [ω] <ℵ 0 X [ω 1 ] ℵ 1 ξ X A ξ D = S T [ω] <ℵ0 Y [ω 1 ] ℵ1 ξ Y A ξ \ D = T. Lusin in [7] defined a stronger concept, a Lusin sequence, and proved that it can be constructed in ZFC. Abraham and Shelah in [1] proved that it is independent from ZFC whether every inseparable sequence has a Lusin subsequence. 2. When forcing destroys inseparability Our goal is to investigate the effect of forcing on inseparable sequences. One way to kill an inseparable sequence would be, of course, to collapse ℵ 1. 1 Department of Mathematics and Informatics, Faculty of Science, University of Novi Sad, e-mail: sobot@dmi.uns.ac.rs

186 Boris Šobot However, we are interested only in forcing notions that preserve ℵ 1, so we will concentrate our attention on destroying separability by means of adding a set D that satisfies (1) and (2). A forcing preserving ℵ 1 adds a set D destroying the inseparability of A iff 1 D ˇω ( S ([ω] <ℵ 0 )ˇ X [ˇω 1 ]ˇℵ 1 ξ X Ǎξ D = S T ([ω] <ℵ 0 )ˇ Y [ˇω 1 ]ˇℵ 1 ξ Y Ǎξ \ D = T ). Let N n (κ) denote the set of nice names for subsets of κ (see [3], Lemma VII 5.12). Using the Maximum principle ([2], Lemma 14.19) we get: a forcing preserving ℵ 1 adds a set D destroying the inseparability of A iff σ, π, µ N n (ω) θ, τ N n (ω 1 ) 1 ( π < ℵ 0 µ < ℵ 0 θ = ℵ 1 τ = ℵ 1 ξ θ (Ǎξ σ = π) ξ τ (Ǎξ \ σ = µ)). To make things as simple as possible, we will assume that we force with a complete Boolean algebra B. Thus we can take our nice names to be of the form σ = { ň, σ(n) : n ω} π = { ň, π(n) : n ω} µ = { ň, µ(n) : n ω} θ = { ˇα, θ(α) : α ω 1 } τ = { ˇα, τ(α) : α ω 1 }. In this case we have ˇξ ρ = ρ(ξ), for each name ρ and ξ dom(ρ). Now we state a modification of Lemma 1 from [6]. The quantifier κ α means there are κ-many ordinals α. Our forcing-including formulas will be adjusted for complete Boolean algebras: + r q means there is r q such that r > 0, and similarly for + r q. q r means that the elements q, r B are compatible in B \ {0}, i.e. q r > 0. Lemma 1. If B is a complete Boolean algebra, p B +, ρ N n (κ) and 1 reg(ˇκ), then: (a) p ρ = ˇκ iff + q p κ α q ρ(α); (b) p ρ < ˇκ iff + r p + q r β < κ α β q (ρ(α)). Proof. Using 1 reg(ˇκ) we get p ρ = ˇκ p β < ˇκ α > β α ρ β < κ + q p + r q α β r ˇα ρ + q p β < κ α β + r q r ρ(α) + q p β < κ α β q ρ(α) which proves (a), and (b) is proved similarly.

Inseparable sequences and forcing 187 Lemma 2. If B is a complete Boolean algebra, φ is a formula and ρ N n (κ), then the following conditions are equivalent: (i) 1 ˇξ ρ φ(ˇξ). (ii) ρ(ξ) φ(ˇξ). Proof. We have 1 ˇξ ρ φ(ˇξ) iff ˇξ ρ φ(ˇξ) iff ρ(ξ) φ(ˇξ). Using the preceding two lemmas, we get Lemma 3. Let V be the ground model, A an inseparable sequence in V and B a complete Boolean algebra. The inseparability of A is destroyed in every forcing extension by B iff there are σ, π, µ N n (ω) and θ, τ N n (ω 1 ) such that (3) (4) (5) (6) (7) (8) p B + ℵ 1 ξ p θ(ξ) p B + ℵ 1 ξ p τ(ξ) p B + + q p m ω n m q (π(n)) p B + + q p m ω n m q (µ(n)) ξ ω 1 θ(ξ) Ǎξ σ = π ξ ω 1 τ(ξ) Ǎξ \ σ = µ. 3. Some necessary conditions In this section we prove several conditions necessary for a complete Boolean algebra to destroy the inseparability of a sequence A. We remind the reader of a few facts about distributivity. A maximal antichain in a Boolean algebra B is also called a partition (of unity). A partition U is a refinement of a partition W if for every w W there is u U such that u w. B is (κ, λ)-distributive if every family {W α : α < κ} of partitions of cardinality λ has a common refinement. Lemma 4. If forcing with a complete Boolean algebra B destroys the inseparability of a sequence A, then B is not (ω, 2)-distributive. Proof. It is well-known that B is (κ, 2)-distributive iff forcing with B does not add any subsets of κ ([2], Theorem 15.38). So if B were (ω, 2)-distributive, the set D V [G] that separates A would also have to belong to V. Of course, the finite sets S and T from (1) and (2) are also in V. But A ξ D = S and A ξ \ D = T are absolute, so D would separate A in V as well. We say that forcing with P adds an unsupported subset of κ if in V P [G] there is a set U [κ] κ such that for no W ([κ] κ ) V W U holds. With r.o.(p) we denote the completion of P. Lemma 5. If forcing with P destroys the inseparability of a sequence A, then it also adds an unsupported subset of ω 1, so r.o.(p) can not contain a countable dense subset.

188 Boris Šobot Proof. Let V [G] be a generic extension via P and let S, T, D, X, Y V [G] be as in (1) and (2). We will show that at least one of the sets X and Y is unsupported. To prove that, suppose the opposite: let Z, W ([ω 1 ] ℵ 1 ) V be such that Z X and W Y. We define C = ξ W (A ξ \ T ). Now, since A ξ \ T D, we have C D. Of course, C V and A ξ \ C T for ξ W. But for every ξ Z we also have ξ X, so A ξ C A ξ D = S. Thus A ξ C is finite in V [G], and hence in V as well. It follows that C separates A, a contradiction. The last statement follows directly from [5], Proposition 5. Theorem 6. (a) Let V = MA ℵ1. If the inseparability of a sequence A is destroyed in every forcing extension by P, then P is not c.c.c. (b) Let V = PFA. If the inseparability of a sequence A is destroyed in every forcing extension by P, then P is not proper. Proof. (a) Since P is c.c.c. iff its completion is, we may assume without loss of generality that we force with a complete Boolean algebra B. So suppose the opposite, that B is c.c.c. in V. Let π, µ, σ, θ, τ be as in Lemma 3. We define, for α ω 1 and n ω, D α = {p B + : ξ α p θ(ξ)} E α = {q B + : ζ α q τ(ζ)} F = {p B + : m ω n m p (π(n)) } H = {q B + : m ω n m q (µ(n)) } S n = {r B + : r σ(n) r σ (n)}. The conditions (3), (4), (5) and (6) clearly imply that D α, E α (for all α < ω 1 ), F and H are dense in B \ {0}; moreover they are open dense. Therefore D α = D α F and E α = E α H are dense for α < ω 1. It is obvious that S n is dense for all n ω. Hence it follows from MA ℵ1 that there is a filter G V intersecting all D α, all E α and all S n. For each n ω there is r S n G. This means that either σ(n) G or σ (n) G. Let us define D = {n ω : σ(n) G}, and prove that D separates A. For each α < ω 1 let p α D α G, q α E α G, and let ξ α, ζ α be such that p α θ(ξ α ) and q α τ(ζ α ). The sets X = {ξ α : α < ω 1 } and Y = {ζ α : α < ω 1 } are uncountable, since each ξ can appear as ξ α only for α ξ. Let ξ = ξ α X; we want to prove A ξ D < ℵ 0. Suppose the opposite. From (7) we have p α Ǎξ σ π, which can also be written as n A ξ p α σ(n) π(n). Since p α F there is m ω such that p α (π(n)) for all n m. Let n A ξ D be greater than m; we have p α σ(n) G, so p α σ(n) 0. But this element is below both π(n) and (π(n)), a contradiction. Analogously we prove that A ξ \ D < ℵ 0 for ξ Y. Practically the same proof works for (b). 4. Concluding remarks It would be interesting to find an example of a notion of forcing that destroys inseparability. The results in the previous section may serve to direct such a

Inseparable sequences and forcing 189 construction. Since one needs to preserve ℵ 1, one should try either to construct a c.c.c.notion of forcing (and by Theorem 6(a) has to assume at least MA ℵ1 ) or a proper notion of forcing (assuming, by Theorem 6(b), at least PFA). Todorčević s method, described for example in [4], could prove useful for this purpose. Acknowledgement The author wishes to thank the referee for his valuable suggestions, and to acknowledge that the research was supported by the Ministry of Education, Science and Technological Development of the Republic of Serbia (Project 174006). References [1] Abraham, U. Shelah, S. Lusin sequences under CH and under Martin s axiom. Fund. Math. 169(2) (2001), 97-103. [2] Jech, T. Set theory. the Third Millenium Edition, Berlin-New York: Springer- Verlag, 2002. [3] Kunen, K. Set theory, an introduction to independence proofs. Amsterdam- London: North-Holland, 1980. [4] Koszmider, P. Models as side conditions. In: Set theory. (DiPrisco et el., ed.) Kluwer Academic Publishers, 1998. [5] Kurilić, M. Unsupported Boolean algebras and forcing. Math. Log. Quart. 50 no. 6, (2005), 594-602. [6] Kurilić, M. Mad families, forcing and the Suslin hypothesis. Arch. Math. Logic 44 (2005), 499-512. [7] Lusin, N. Sur les parties de la suite naturelle des nombres entiers. Comptes Rendus (Doklady) de l Academie des Sciences de l URSS 40 (1943), 175-178. Received by the editors May 26, 2013