Conceptual Mathematics,

Similar documents
Category Theory. Categories. Definition.

Hilbert and the concept of axiom

Abstract and Variable Sets in Category Theory 1

Industrial revolution and reform of mathematics

Category theory and set theory: algebraic set theory as an example of their interaction

Observations on Category Theory. John L. Bell

1. Characterization and uniqueness of products

CHAPTER 0: BACKGROUND (SPRING 2009 DRAFT)

Intuitive infinitesimals in the calculus

Mathematical Forms and Strategies

0.G. Notational conventions for elementary geometry

Why is the Universe Described in Mathematics? This essay attempts to address the questions, "Why is the Universe described in

Introduction to Metalogic

Affine Planes: An Introduction to Axiomatic Geometry

Introduction to Logic and Axiomatic Set Theory

Euclid Geometry And Non-Euclid Geometry. Have you ever asked yourself why is it that if you walk to a specific place from

INTRODUCTION TO LOGIC

Paper read at History of Science Society 2014 Annual Meeting, Chicago, Nov. 9,

CHAPTER 1. Introduction

A NEW SET THEORY FOR ANALYSIS

via Topos Theory Olivia Caramello University of Cambridge The unification of Mathematics via Topos Theory Olivia Caramello

Section 2.1: Introduction to the Logic of Quantified Statements

CM10196 Topic 2: Sets, Predicates, Boolean algebras

Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz (1666)

The Axiom of Infinity, Quantum Field Theory, and Large Cardinals. Paul Corazza Maharishi University

Vector Spaces. Chapter 1

Symbolic Analytic Geometry and the Origins of Symbolic Algebra

Introduction to Logic

3.C. Further comments on axioms for geometry

Beyond Newton and Leibniz: The Making of Modern Calculus. Anthony V. Piccolino, Ed. D. Palm Beach State College Palm Beach Gardens, Florida

chapter 11 ALGEBRAIC SYSTEMS GOALS

SCIENTIFIC REVOLUTION

Chapter Three. Deciphering the Code. Understanding Notation

Chapter 4. Basic Set Theory. 4.1 The Language of Set Theory

Procedure for Setting Goals for an Introductory Physics Class

MATH1014 Calculus II. A historical review on Calculus

CHAPTER 1: Functions

Category-Theoretic Radical Ontic Structural Realism

Module 3: Cartesian Coordinates and Vectors

Mathematics that Every Physicist should Know: Scalar, Vector, and Tensor Fields in the Space of Real n- Dimensional Independent Variable with Metric

Philosophies of Mathematics. The Search for Foundations

FACTORIZATION AND THE PRIMES

Geometry and Philosophy

2.23 Theorem. Let A and B be sets in a metric space. If A B, then L(A) L(B).

Physics 141 Energy 1 Page 1. Energy 1

Lecture 12. Statement Logic as a word algebra on the set of atomic statements. Lindenbaum algebra.

Making Sense. Tom Carter. tom/sfi-csss. April 2, 2009

An Intuitive Introduction to Motivic Homotopy Theory Vladimir Voevodsky

From Algebraic Geometry to Homological Algebra

Just-in-Time-Teaching and other gadgets. Richard Cramer-Benjamin Niagara University

Why write proofs? Why not just test and repeat enough examples to confirm a theory?

Axiomatic set theory. Chapter Why axiomatic set theory?

ORDER AND ARITHMETIC OF CARDINALITIES

CHAPTER 2 INTRODUCTION TO CLASSICAL PROPOSITIONAL LOGIC

Review of Coherence in Three-Dimensional Category Theory by Nick Gurski (Cambridge University Press, 2013).

In this initial chapter, you will be introduced to, or more than likely be reminded of, a

MAT 417, Fall 2017, CRN: 1766 Real Analysis: A First Course

(January 6, 2006) Paul Garrett garrett/

(1.3.1) and in English one says a is an element of M. The statement that a is not an element of M is written as a M

1 Differentiable manifolds and smooth maps

A history of Topology

Lesson 14: An Axiom System for Geometry

Algebra II Honors Curriculum

Section 7.1: Functions Defined on General Sets

To Infinity and Beyond

Logic. Quantifiers. (real numbers understood). x [x is rotten in Denmark]. x<x+x 2 +1

With Question/Answer Animations. Chapter 2

UNIT 10 Equations NC: Algebra 3c, 3d

35 Chapter CHAPTER 4: Mathematical Proof

MEP: Demonstration Project Unit 2: Formulae

Seminaar Abstrakte Wiskunde Seminar in Abstract Mathematics Lecture notes in progress (27 March 2010)

What Comes After Structural Realism?

Shi Feng Sheng Danny Wong

Dominoes and Counting

2 THE SCIENTIFIC REVOLUTION IN ENGLAND AND EUROPE, Lesson Title: The Scientific Revolution in England and Europe,

What is proof? Lesson 1

How Euler Did It. by Ed Sandifer. Foundations of Calculus. September 2006

Infinity. Newton, Leibniz & the Calculus

SECTION 5: EILENBERG ZILBER EQUIVALENCES AND THE KÜNNETH THEOREMS

THE RISE OF MODERN SCIENCE CHAPTER 20, SECTION 2

The Arithmetic of Reasoning. Chessa Horomanski & Matt Corson

THE GEOMETRY OF THALES

Sets. Alice E. Fischer. CSCI 1166 Discrete Mathematics for Computing Spring, Outline Sets An Algebra on Sets Summary

Amount of Substance and Its Unit Mole- Connecting the Invisible Micro World to the Observable Macro World Part 2 (English, mp4)

What is a Revolution? A Revolution is a complete change, or an overthrow of a government, a social system, etc.

MAGIC Set theory. lecture 1

Symposium: L.E.J. Brouwer, Fifty Years Later. Free Choice Sequences: A Temporal Interpretation Compatible with Acceptance of Classical Mathematics

ABSTRACT DIFFERENTIAL GEOMETRY VIA SHEAF THEORY

Model theory, algebraic dynamics and local fields

THE MEANING OF RELATIVITY

Quantum Quandaries: A Category Theoretic Perspective

Elementary Linear Algebra, Second Edition, by Spence, Insel, and Friedberg. ISBN Pearson Education, Inc., Upper Saddle River, NJ.

Euclid: The Father of Geometry In our day and age, it is rare to read and research a person who has shaped such a fundamental

The roots of computability theory. September 5, 2016

Section 1: Sets and Interval Notation

Using Algebra Fact Families to Solve Equations

The Scientific Revolution

Kant and Finitism. Crossing Worlds: Mathematical logisc, philosophy, art: For Juliette Kennedy. Bill Tait. 4 June 2016

GÖDEL S COMPLETENESS AND INCOMPLETENESS THEOREMS. Contents 1. Introduction Gödel s Completeness Theorem

#26: Number Theory, Part I: Divisibility

Transcription:

Conceptual Mathematics, 0. the Conceptual Infrastructure By conceptual infrastructure of mathematics I mean the concepts, the terminology, the symbols, and the notations that mathematicians and people who apply mathematics use in their daily professional activities. This is very different from what is often called the conceptual foundation of mathematics, which deals critically with the deeper meaning of these concepts, an activity which only some mathematicians, and these only occasionally, worry about. I believe that the infrastructure of mathematics was and still is being developed in four stages (all quotations in Sects 1-2 are from Mathematical Thought from Ancient to Modern Times, 1972, by Morris Kline): 1. Axioms, Theorems, and Proofs Mathematics as an organized, independent, and reasoned discipline did not exist before the classical Greeks of the period from 600 to 300 B.C.. The Greeks introduced mathematics as a deductive discipline, with axioms, theorems, and proofs. The Greeks had some knowledge of number theory (e.g. they had the proof that there is no largest prime number), but most of their contributions dealt with geometry. Euclids Elements (about 300 B.C.) gave a comprehensive account of Greek mathematics, and it has been part of the infrastructure of mathematics ever since. 2. Efficient Notations, Variables Fundamental additions to the infrastructure were introduced in the 16th and 17th century The advance in algebra that proved far more significant than the technical progress of the 16th century was the introduction of better symbolism. Familiar notations such as +,, <, >, =, and the use of parentheses, square brackets, and braces were introduced during that time (For example, = was introduced by Robert Recorde in 1557.) The most significant change in the character of algebra was introduced in connection with symbolism by Francois Vieta (1540-1603)... He was the first to use letters purposefully and systematically, not just to represent an unknown or powers of an unknown but as general coefficients. Improvements in Vieta s use of letters are due to Descartes (1596-1650). He used first letters of the alphabet for known quantities and last letters for unknowns,... Leibniz (1646-1716) must be mentioned in the history of symbolism,... He made prolonged studies of the various notations, asked the opinions of his contemporaries, and then chose the best... Thus, by the end of the 17th century, the deliberate use of symbolism - as opposed to the incidental and accidental use - and the awareness of the power of generality it confers entered mathematics. The idea of a function was developed in the 17th century and made the invention of differential calculus possible. It was Leibniz, in the late 1600 s, who introduced the concepts as well as the terms variable, constant, and parameter. 1

A function was defined to be the relation between an independent variable and a dependent variable. Newton used the term fluent for such a relation. It was Leibniz who introduced also the concepts as well as the notations of calculus, such as dy dx and the integral sign. Without the infrastructure introduced in the 16th and 17th century the rapid advances of mathematics in the 18th and 19th century would have been impossible. 3. Sets, Mapping, and Mathematical Structures The end of the 19th century saw the beginning of a fundamental shift in the infrastructure of mathematics, starting with the work on the concept of a set by Georg Cantor. More and more, mathematics is seen to be dealing with sets and mappings, rather than with variables. The concepts of domain and codomain of a mapping are made explicit. Functions are special kinds of mappings and are considered as objects in themselves and are given names, generic or specific. Instead of y = f(x) to denote a function, in the language of sets and mappings one uses just the single letter f by itself and considers the domain Dom f and codomain Cod f of f to be parts of the specification of f. So it becomes possible to consider sets (spaces) of functions rather than only specific functions considered one by one. A functional is a mapping whose domain is a set of functions. The now standard notations of the language of sets, such as for membership, for inclusion, for union, and for intersection are fairly recent. They were not yet used when I first learned about set theory while in high school (from the little book by E.Kamke, published first in the early 1930 s). Even more recent are notations such as f : D C and U := {x S...x...}. Using the concept of a set as a background, the past 100 years or so saw the introduction of the idea of an abstract mathematical structure. Examples of such structures are groups, rings, fields, topological spaces, linear spaces. The multi-volume work of Bourbaki, Éléments de Mathématique, starting in 1939, explicitly introduced the concept of a mathematical structure and gave a systematic description of the important structures, using the language of sets and mappings. 4. Categories and Functors In 1942, Eilenberg and Mac Lane introduced the concepts as well as the terms category, functor and natural transformation, and thereby added very importantly to the infrastructure of mathematics. Eilenberg died in January 1998, and the November 1998 issue of the Notices of the American Mathematical Society contains the following descriptions of his role and his views, which bear upon the conceptual infrastructure of mathematics. Alex Heller: As I perceived it then, Sammy considered that the highest value in mathematics was to be found, not in specious depth nor in overcoming of overwhelming difficulty, but rather in providing the definitive clarity that would 2

illuminate its underlying order. This was to be accomplished by elucidating the true structure of the objects of mathematics. Let me hasten to say that this was in no sense an ontological quest: the true structure was intrinsic to mathematics and was to be discerned only by doing more mathematics. Sammy had no patience for metaphysical argument.. He was not a Platonist: equally, he was not a non-platonist. It might be more to the point to make a different distinction: Sammys mathematical aesthetic was classical rather than romantic. Category theory was one of Sammy s principal tools in his search for mathematical reality. Category theory also developed into a mathematical subject with its own honorable history and practitioners, beginning with MacLane and including, notably, F.W.Lawvere, Sammy s most remarkable student, who saw it as a foundation for all of mathematics and justified this intuition with such innovations as categorical semantics and topos theory. Sammy did not, I think want to be reckoned a member of this school. I believe, in fact, that he would have rejected the idea that mathematics needed a foundation. Category theory was for him only a tool - in fact, a powerful one - for expanding our understanding.. It was his willingness to search for this understanding at an ever higher level that really set him apart and that made him, in my estimation, the author of a revolution in mathematics as notable as that initiated by Cantor s invention of set theory, Like Cantor, Sammy has changed the way we think about mathematics. Hyman Bass: He fit squarely into the tradition of Hilbert, E.Artin, E.Noether, and Bourbaki: He was a champion of the axiomatic unification that so dominated the early postwar mathematics. His philosophy was that the aims of mathematics are to find and articulate with clarity and economy the underlying principles that govern mathematical phenomena. Complexity and opaqueness were, for him, signs of insufficient understanding. He sought not just theorems, but ways to make the truth transparent, natural, inevitable for the right thinking person. It was this right thinking, not just facts, that Sammy tried to teach and that, in many domains, he succeeded in teaching to a whole generation of mathematicians. Eilenberg was the only non-french member of the Bourbaki-group. 5. The present situation At the present time, all four stages of the conceptual infrastructure described above are used to some extent. High school geometry is still done more or less as described in Euclids Elements. ( I remember being forced to memorize by rote some of Euclids axioms in an 8th grade geometry course; it almost turned me away from mathematics.) High school algebra and elementary calculus are still done, in most cases, using the language of variables and constants as described in stage 2 above. On this level, a function is still denoted by y = f(x) rather than just f. People are reluctant to use sin or cos by themselves rather than sin x or cos x. The identity function of the real numbers is described by y = x. 3

The language of sets and mappings as described in stage 3 above provides for much more precision, clarity, and economy than the language of variables and constants. In 1972 (?), I taught an elementary calculus course here at CMU in which I systematically used the language of sets and mappings. (I introduced the notation ι for the identity function of the reals.) There is still much resistance against the language of sets and mappings. An attempt to introduce this language into high school mathematics, known as the New Math, turned out to be an utter failure, because teachers cannot teach something that they do not understand themselves. During my Ph.D. Final in 1954, the examiners circulated a note with too much Bourbaki on it. A review of a volume of selected papers by me and collaborators downgrades much of my work as merely presenting well-known and well-understood concepts in continuum mechanics or thermodynamics in the idiom of elementary set theory. I am convinced that the concepts of sets, mappings, and mathematical structures will eventually displace the older modes of conceptual mathematics. But this change requires more and better concepts, terminology, and notation than the illogical and ambiguous mishmash that is now considered to be standard. During the past 25 years or so, Juan Schäffer and I have developed such an infrastructure for the basic parts of mathematics (in connection with our undergraduate honors program entitled Mathematical Studies). Although we had no interaction with Eilenberg, our philosophy has been the same as the one ascribed to him above: His philosophy was that the aims of mathematics are to find and articulate with clarity and economy the underlying principles that govern mathematical phenomena. Complexity and opaqueness were, for him, signs of insufficient understanding. He sought not just theorems, but ways to make the truth transparent, natural, inevitable for the right thinking person. The language of categories and functors is used extensively in algebraic topology but not yet very much in other fields of mathematics. One should carefully distinguish between the language of sets and mappings and the language of categories and functors on the one hand and set theory and category theory on the other. The latter have become specialties and have been pursued by specialists in their fields, but as such have had very little influence on the rest of mathematics. 6. Isocategories A mathematical structure is obtained by prescribing a list of ingredients and postulating a list of axioms. For example, to obtain a topological space, one must specify a set and a collection of subsets of it (the open sets) and then require that certain axioms be satisfied. Perhaps the simplest example of an algebraic structure is that of a pre-monoid : the ingredients are a set M and a mapping cmb : M M M, called combination in the abstract or multiplication, addition, or composition in special cases. The only axiom is the associative law.monoids and groups are obtained from pre-monoids by adding ingredients and axioms. 4

A species of structure consists of all mathematical structures obtained by a particular recipe. For example, the species of topological spaces consists of all topological spaces. For each species, there is a natural definition of isomorphism between two members of the species. Thus, every species gives rise immediately to an isocategory: its objects are the members of the species and its morphisms are the isomorphisms. Most branches of mathematics deal extensively with procedures that start with a given structure and construct from it a new structure that may or may not belong to the same species as the given one. For example, from each set S one can construct the set SubS of all subsets of S and also the group PermS of all permutatioms of S. Both Sub and Perm may be viewed as isofunctors. From the point of view of category theory, isocategories may not be particularly interesting, but I believe that they can provide a powerful conceptual tool for articulating with clarity and economy the underlying principles that govern many mathematical phenomena. Most other examples of categories can be obtained from isocategories by extending the class of isomorphism to a larger class of morphisms. For example, one can use the isocategory of topological spaces to construct an enlarged category of topological spaces by taking all continuous mappings or all open mappings to be the morphisms. In a paper entitled Isocategories and Tensor Functors, written in 1992, I have shown how one can gain better insight into many aspects of linear algebra and differential geometry by using a special type of isofunctor which I call tensor functor. 5