DISCUSSION CENSORED VISION. Bruce Le Catt

Similar documents
Tooley on backward causation

Regularity analyses have failed; it is time to give up and try something else: a counterfactual analysis.

Appendix A Lewis s Counterfactuals

EASTERN DIVISION OF THE AMERICAN PHILOSOPHICAL ASSOCIATION 2009 GROUP MEETING: THE PHILOSOPHY OF TIME SOCIETY

Counterfactuals and comparative similarity

Properties of Sequences

Philosophy 5340 Epistemology. Topic 3: Analysis, Analytically Basic Concepts, Direct Acquaintance, and Theoretical Terms. Part 2: Theoretical Terms

1 The problem of survival analysis

CAUSATION CAUSATION. Chapter 10. Non-Humean Reductionism

Of Miracles and Interventions

Why Care About Counterfactual Support? The Cognitive Uses of Causal Order Lecture 2

Delayed Choice Paradox

Mathematical Logic Prof. Arindama Singh Department of Mathematics Indian Institute of Technology, Madras. Lecture - 15 Propositional Calculus (PC)

Mathematics-I Prof. S.K. Ray Department of Mathematics and Statistics Indian Institute of Technology, Kanpur. Lecture 1 Real Numbers

Hardy s Paradox. Chapter Introduction

As you scroll through this review, you move your hand; this causes the

Universalism Entails Extensionalism

1.1 Statements and Compound Statements

Direct Proof and Counterexample I:Introduction

Direct Proof and Counterexample I:Introduction. Copyright Cengage Learning. All rights reserved.

Why Learning Logic? Logic. Propositional Logic. Compound Propositions

Dependent (Contextual) Events

David Lewis. Void and Object

Of Miracles and Interventions

Comments on The Role of Large Scale Assessments in Research on Educational Effectiveness and School Development by Eckhard Klieme, Ph.D.

INTENSIONS MARCUS KRACHT

Lecture 34 Woodward on Manipulation and Causation

Baker. 1. Classical physics. 2. Determinism

Response to Kadri Vihvelin s counterfactuals and dispositions

David Lewis. Causation

CAUSATION. Chapter 5. Humean Reductionism - Counterfactual Approaches

An Intuitive Introduction to Motivic Homotopy Theory Vladimir Voevodsky

146 Philosophy of Physics: Quantum Mechanics

LECTURE FOUR MICHAELMAS 2017 Dr Maarten Steenhagen Causation

Measurement Independence, Parameter Independence and Non-locality

Properties of Arithmetic

Indicative conditionals

Absolute motion versus relative motion in Special Relativity is not dealt with properly

Two kinds of long-distance indefinites Bernhard Schwarz The University of Texas at Austin

MITOCW MITRES6_012S18_L22-10_300k

The Uniqueness of Maxwell's Equations Dr. Christopher S. Baird University of Massachusetts Lowell

Lecture 12: Arguments for the absolutist and relationist views of space

Communication Engineering Prof. Surendra Prasad Department of Electrical Engineering Indian Institute of Technology, Delhi

Causal Modeling and Transitivity

Critical Notice: Bas van Fraassen, Scientific Representation: Paradoxes of Perspective Oxford University Press, 2008, xiv pages

For Philosophy and Phenomenolgical Research

Supplementary Notes on Inductive Definitions

The Philosophy of Physics. Is Space Absolute or Relational?

Lewis Counterfactual Theory of Causation

Conceivability and Modal Knowledge

The Integers. Math 3040: Spring Contents 1. The Basic Construction 1 2. Adding integers 4 3. Ordering integers Multiplying integers 12

Searle: Proper Names and Intentionality

The Power of Possible Causation

MODAL LOGIC WITH SUBJUNCTIVE MARKERS: A NEW PERSPECTIVE ON RIGID DESIGNATION

CS 453 Operating Systems. Lecture 7 : Deadlock

Notes on Huygens Principle 2000 Lawrence Rees

What is it like to be a quantum observer? And what does it imply about the nature of consciousness?

Superposition - World of Color and Hardness

(Refer Slide Time: 0:21)

CAUSATION. Chapter 14. Causation and the Direction of Time Preliminary Considerations in Support of a Causal Analysis of Temporal Concepts

A Structuralist Account of Logic

Lecture - 30 Stationary Processes

3. Nomic vs causal vs dispositional essentialism. 1. If quidditism is true, then properties could have swapped their nomic roles.

Singlet State Correlations

Inference and Explanation in Counterfactual Reasoning

Toward a Mechanistic Interpretation of Probability

The Integers. Peter J. Kahn

Statistical mechanics and the asymmetry of counterfactual dependence

A proof of Bell s inequality in quantum mechanics using causal interactions

MITOCW watch?v=0usje5vtiks

Causal Inference. Prediction and causation are very different. Typical questions are:

Seminaar Abstrakte Wiskunde Seminar in Abstract Mathematics Lecture notes in progress (27 March 2010)

Essay Review: Cause and Chance: Causation in an Indeterministic World, Phil Dowe and Paul Noordhof, eds., Routledge, 2004

FORMAL PROOFS DONU ARAPURA

SIMILARITY IS A BAD GUIDE TO COUNTERFACTUAL TRUTH. The Lewis-Stalnaker logic systems [2] account for a wide range of intuitions about

Selected Topics in Mathematical Physics Prof. Balakrishnan Department of Physics Indian Institute of Technology, Madras

Replay argument. Abstract. Tanasije Gjorgoski Posted on on 03 April 2006

4 Derivations in the Propositional Calculus

Today. A little more scale... The Scientific Method. Naked Eye Observations: the Appearance of the Sky

2. Prime and Maximal Ideals

Formal Epistemology: Lecture Notes. Horacio Arló-Costa Carnegie Mellon University

Brit. J. Phil. Sci. 46 (1995), Redundant Causation. Michael McDermott

Identity in Physics and Elsewhere

1 Computational problems

Mathematical Reasoning. The Foundation of Algorithmics

Take the measurement of a person's height as an example. Assuming that her height has been determined to be 5' 8", how accurate is our result?

Lewis 2 Definitions of T-terms

CSE 331 Winter 2018 Reasoning About Code I

Special Theory of Relativity Prof. Shiva Prasad Department of Physics Indian Institute of Technology, Bombay

What if Every "If Only" Statement Were True?: The Logic of Counterfactuals

PROOF-THEORETIC REDUCTION AS A PHILOSOPHER S TOOL

Chapter 1 Review of Equations and Inequalities

Philosophy 240 Symbolic Logic. Russell Marcus Hamilton College Fall 2013

4.1 Real-valued functions of a real variable

Mathematical Foundations of Programming. Nicolai Kraus. Draft of February 15, 2018

KRIPKE S THEORY OF TRUTH 1. INTRODUCTION

Basic Thermodynamics Prof. S.K. Som Department of Mechanical Engineering Indian Institute of Technology, Kharagpur

CH 59 SQUARE ROOTS. Every positive number has two square roots. Ch 59 Square Roots. Introduction

CAUSES, COUNTERFACTUALS, AND NON-LOCALITY. Mathias Frisch

Transcription:

Australasian Journal of Philosophy Vol. 60, No. 2; June 1982 DISCUSSION CENSORED VISION Bruce Le Catt When we see in the normal way, the scene before the eyes causes matching visual experience. And it does so as part of an extensive pattern of counterfactual dependence: over a wide range of different alternative scenes and correspondingly different alternative experiences, other scenes would likewise have caused matching visual experience. The same is true if we see in certain abnormal ways, for instance by means of a prosthetic device. But abnormal cases are possible in which the scene before the eyes might cause matching visual experience by triggering some one-off or random causal mechanism, insensitive to the details of the scene, which just happens to produce the right experience. In such a case, matching depends on the scene being just right. Other scenes would not have likewise caused matching experience. These are cases of hallucination, not seeing, despite the fact that the hallucination happens to be veridical in its content. If we considered only cases of these two kinds, we might well agree with David Lewis's proposal that if the scene before the eyes causes matching visual experience as part of a suitable pattern of counterfactual dependence, then the subject sees; if the scene before the eyes causes matching visual experience without a suitable pattern of counterfactual dependence, then the subject does not see. 1 But there is a third sort of case to be considered. The scene may cause matching experience by a good mechanism: one that is not one-off and not random, one that is properly sensitive at every step of its operation, one that would -- if left to itself -- produce matching experience over a suitably wide range of alternatives. This mechanism, however, may be subject to external interference in such a way that there is no suitable pattern of counterfactual dependence of experience on scene. In the extreme case, we may have no dependence at all. Lewis himself considers just such a case. The Censor. My natural or prosthetic eye is in perfect condition and functioning normally, and by means of it the scene before my eyes causes matching visual experience. But if the scene were any different my visual experience would be just the same. For there is a censor standing by, ready l David Lewis, 'Veridical Hallucination and Prosthetic Vision', Philosophy, 58 (1980), pp. 239-249, especially p. 245. 158 Australasian Journal of

Bruce Le Catt 159 to see to it that I have precisely that visual experience and no other, whatever the scene may be... So long as the scene is such as to cause the right experience, the censor does nothing. But if the scene were any different, the censor would intervene and cause the same experience by other means. (Op. cir., p. 248.) Lewis calls the case 'hard' and 'misleading', but he stubbornly insists that it is a case of veridical hallucination. He is wrong. It is a clear case of seeing -- of seeing without a suitable pattern, or any pattern, of counterfactuai dependence. Therefore it is a counterexample against his proposal. Or so say I, and so say the great majority of those whose intuitions I have consulted. (The case has several versions. The censor might be entirely outside the subject; or it might be some mechanism in the subject's own brain, so long as it is separate from the mechanism by which the scene causes experience in the actual case. The censor might be a purposive being; it might be an artifact that serves the purpose of its maker; or it might be a mechanism that acts as a censor entirely by accident. I think (and Lewis agrees -- personal communication) that these differences do not matter.) Lewis's proposal must be corrected to reverse its false verdict against the possibility of censored vision. But a fresh start would be uncalled for. For the most part, we should keep both Lewis's verdicts and his reasons for them. Fortunately, the makings of a conservative correction are not far to seek. We can find the main ingredient in Lewis's own treatment of causal preemption. and also in Christopher Peacocke's distinction between jump and stepwise recoverability of information. 2 In brief: let us look to dependences involving the intermediate stages of the causal process that actually goes on. We may diagram this actual causal process as follows. There is a causal chain that runs from the scene S O via an intermediate stage I 0 to the visual experience E 0. (Of course there are many other intermediate stages, which we need not bother to display.) There is also an alternative causal chain from C, the censor's initial readiness, to the same experience E 0. But this chain does not go to completion; the part shown as a broken line does not occur. The chain is cut off by the arrival of a causal signal M 0 that branches off the chain from S O to I 0 and E. Call M 0 the monitoring signal, and call the point at which it branches off the monitoring point (MP). The monitoring point might be part way along the chain (as shown); or it might be at the beginning, the scene itself. C'.,. - - ",,",- ~-... -)'E 0 So /'M i0 "'a, ~ E0 MP If the scene had been different, matters would have gone differently. We may diagram the causal process that would then have taken place as follows. 2 David Lewis, 'Causation', Journal of Philosophy, LXX (1973), pp. 556-567, especially p. 567; Christopher Peacocke, Holistic Explanation (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1979), pp. 79-84.

160 Censored Vision The causal chain from C to E 0 would have gone to completion, since the different monitoring signal M~ would not have been such as to render the censor idle. The causal chain from the different scene S 1 via the different intermediate stage 11 to the different matching experience El, on the other hand, would not have gone to completion. It would have been cut off at the intervention point (IP) by a causal signal from the censor. Thus E l, the experience at the end of this cut-off chain, would not have occurred. E0, produced by the censor, would have taken its place. However the intermediate stage I1, which precedes the intervention point, would have occurred. C' / M r ~, ~ ~E S I -" ) I~... ~'E I MP IF Now let us return to the actual case. And from the standpoint of actuality, let us ask: what would have happened if 11 had occurred in place of I0? The answer might seem to be: if so, then the scene would have been S 1 and we would have had the causal process just considered, ending in E 0. But that answer is wrong. It involves counterfactual backtracking, a form of hypothetical reasoning which, as Lewis has argued, is not proper in causal contexts. 3 The right answer is as follows. Until a point very shortly before the occurrence of 11 -- call this the divergence point (DP) -- there would have been no difference at all from the actual course of events. The scene would have been So, as in actuality. The monitoring signal would have been Mo, as in actuality (assuming that the monitoring point precedes the divergence point). Nevertheless, I l would somehow have occured in place of I 0. If that requires the counterfactual situation to break laws that actually prevail, so be it. After I1, events would have taken their lawful course -- any further breaking of the actual laws would be gratuitous m and that lawful course would have ended in the experience E 1. The censor would not have intervened, having been rendered idle, as in actuality, by the monitoring signal M o. Also the chain from C to E 0 would not have gone to completion, and the experience E 0 at the end of this cut-off chain would not have occurred. Diagramatically: M ",,,, ~E,I" S O - --11 )-'E 1 MP DP IP 3 See Lewis, 'Veridical Hallucination and Prosthetic Vision', p. 247; Lewis, 'Causation', pp. 566-567; and Lewis, 'Counterfactual Dependence and Time's Arrow', Nog.s, XIII (1979), pp. 455-476.

Bruce Le Catt 161 To summarise. In actuality the scene was So, the intermediate stage was I0, and the experience was E 0. If the scene had been Sl, the experience would still have been E 0. But if the scene had been S~, the intermediate stage would have been I1; and if the intermediate stage had been 11, the experience would have been E I. (The case illustrates the intransitivity of counterfactuals.) The same goes for other alternative scenes, over a suitably wide and varied range. In the case of the censor, we have no suitable pattern of counterfactual dependence of visual experience on the scene before the eyes. But we do have a suitable pattern of stepwise counterfactual dependence, as we may call it. Visual experience depends counterfactuauy on what happens at the intermediate stage, and that in turn depends counterfactually on the scene before the eyes. Taken together, these two patterns of dependence serve to link scenes with matching experience, and they do so over a suitably wide range of alternative scenes and alternative experiences. Stepwise dependence is not dependence simpliciter, but it will do as a substitute. The case of the censor is a case of seeing because there is stepwise dependence. Lewis's other cases of veridical hallucination are indeed not cases of seeing, because in those cases there is neither dependence nor stepwise dependence. In place of Lewis's proposal we have this correction: if the scene before the eyes causes matching visual experience as part of a suitable pattern of counterfactual dependence, or as part of a suitable pattern of stepwise counterfactual dependence, then the subject sees; if the scene before the eyes causes matching visual experience without a pattern of either sort, then the subject does not see. In the case considered, we needed only two steps, involving only one intermediate stage. But more complicated cases of censored vision and stepwise dependence are possible, and these too should count as cases of seeing. Suppose there are two censors monitoring the causal chain at different points, both rendered idle by the monitoring signals they receive, as follows. Ct C' So -\-... ~-Eo... -7"... *,-... n,,,- M 0 " " / M 0 ' t "( _ 1- I0 ".i, ~- I0' ~ E0 MP IP MP' IP' In this case, visual experience does not depend on the scene before the eyes; experience does not even depend on what happens at the first intermediate stage; and what happens at the second intermediate stage does not depend on the scene. But experience does depend on what happens at the second intermediate stage, which depends in turn on what happens at the first, which depends in turn on the scene. We have a pattern of stepwise dependence in three steps. Other cases could require more steps, conceivably any finite number.

162 Censored Vision (What if there are infinitely many censors, monitoring the chain at infinitely many points? 4 Then visual experience might not depend on what happens at any intermediate stage, since any intermediate stage might be followed by further potential censorship. If such a case is a case of seeing, the corrected proposal fails. But is it? The case is too different from anything that could really happen, too liable to mislead us by false analogies between the finite and the infinite, and any intuitions we may have about it are not to be trusted. Let it fall where it may.) Stepwise dependence is an existentially quantified condition. We need not say how to select the appropriate intermediate stage (or stages); we require only that there is some selection that will do the job. Indeed, there should be a good deal of latitude. Anything will do, provided that it comes before the intervention point and its divergence point comes after the monitoring point. We should expect an adequate interval between the monitoring point and the intervention point, given the stipulation that the censor was something separate from the mechanism by which the scene actually causes experience. (What if there is instantaneous action at a distance, or causation over empty time gaps? Again, the cases are too different from what could really happen; let us doubt any intuitions we may have and let them fall where they may.) Thus it matters that the censor was taken to be external. And that seems right intuitively. Integrate the censor into the operative mechanism, and neither intuition nor our corrected proposal will any longer give a clear verdict that the subject sees. Princeton, N. J. Received August 1981 4 A similar problem concerning the analysis of causal preemption is raised in William K. Goosens, 'Causal Chains and Counterfactuals', Journal of Philosophy, LXXVI (1979), pp. 489-495.