Gi en Demand for Several Goods

Similar documents
It is convenient to introduce some notation for this type of problems. I will write this as. max u (x 1 ; x 2 ) subj. to. p 1 x 1 + p 2 x 2 m ;

Advanced Microeconomics Fall Lecture Note 1 Choice-Based Approach: Price e ects, Wealth e ects and the WARP

Microeconomics, Block I Part 1

CHAPTER 3: OPTIMIZATION

Advanced Microeconomics I: Consumers, Firms and Markets Chapters 1+2

The Kuhn-Tucker and Envelope Theorems

Microeconomic Theory-I Washington State University Midterm Exam #1 - Answer key. Fall 2016

CHAPTER 1-2: SHADOW PRICES

STATIC LECTURE 4: CONSTRAINED OPTIMIZATION II - KUHN TUCKER THEORY

Nonlinear Programming (NLP)

Week 9: Topics in Consumer Theory (Jehle and Reny, Chapter 2)

Lecture 8: Basic convex analysis

Optimal taxation with monopolistic competition

Exercises - SOLUTIONS UEC Advanced Microeconomics, Fall 2018 Instructor: Dusan Drabik, de Leeuwenborch 2105

c 2007 Je rey A. Miron

Microeconomics II Lecture 4. Marshallian and Hicksian demands for goods with an endowment (Labour supply)

Addendum to: International Trade, Technology, and the Skill Premium

Recitation 2-09/01/2017 (Solution)

The Kuhn-Tucker Problem

3. Neoclassical Demand Theory. 3.1 Preferences

Chapter 4. Maximum Theorem, Implicit Function Theorem and Envelope Theorem

ECON0702: Mathematical Methods in Economics

Microeconomic Theory -1- Introduction

UNIVERSITY OF NOTTINGHAM. Discussion Papers in Economics WEAK LINKS, GOOD SHOTS AND OTHER PUBLIC GOOD GAMES: BUILDING ON BBV

Advanced Microeconomics

The Kuhn-Tucker and Envelope Theorems

Fixed Point Theorem and Sequences in One or Two Dimensions

1 Uncertainty. These notes correspond to chapter 2 of Jehle and Reny.

1.4 FOUNDATIONS OF CONSTRAINED OPTIMIZATION

Adv. Micro Theory, ECON

Economics 205 Exercises

Near convexity, metric convexity, and convexity

1 Uncertainty and Insurance

The Optimal Depletion of Exhaustible Resources: A Complete Characterization.

Intro to Economic analysis

3.2 THE FUNDAMENTAL WELFARE THEOREMS

Economic Growth

Lecture 3 - Axioms of Consumer Preference and the Theory of Choice

The Fundamental Welfare Theorems

Local disaggregation of demand and excess demand functions: a new question

Lecture 6: Contraction mapping, inverse and implicit function theorems

ECONOMIC OPTIMALITY. Date: October 10, 2005.

; p. p y p y p y. Production Set: We have 2 constraints on production - demand for each factor of production must be less than its endowment

Appendix II Testing for consistency

Positive Models of Private Provision of Public Goods: A Static Model. (Bergstrom, Blume and Varian 1986)

Simultaneous Choice Models: The Sandwich Approach to Nonparametric Analysis

Fluctuations. Shocks, Uncertainty, and the Consumption/Saving Choice

Week 6: Consumer Theory Part 1 (Jehle and Reny, Chapter 1)

Part I Analysis in Economics

Volume 30, Issue 3. Monotone comparative statics with separable objective functions. Christian Ewerhart University of Zurich

a = (a 1; :::a i )

Addendum to: New Trade Models, Same Old Gains?

Note on social choice allocation in exchange economies with Cobb-Douglas preferences

Solving Extensive Form Games

CONSUMER DEMAND. Consumer Demand

Econ Spring Review Set 1 - Answers ELEMENTS OF LOGIC. NECESSARY AND SUFFICIENT. SET THE-

Economics 121b: Intermediate Microeconomics Midterm Suggested Solutions 2/8/ (a) The equation of the indifference curve is given by,

Chapter 5 Symbolic Increments

Week 7: The Consumer (Malinvaud, Chapter 2 and 4) / Consumer November Theory 1, 2015 (Jehle and 1 / Reny, 32

Optimization. 1 Some Concepts and Terms

Almost Transferable Utility, Changes in Production Possibilities, and the Nash Bargaining and the Kalai-Smorodinsky Solutions

ECON501 - Vector Di erentiation Simon Grant

Hicksian Demand and Expenditure Function Duality, Slutsky Equation

Notes on the Mussa-Rosen duopoly model

Microeconomic Theory: Lecture 2 Choice Theory and Consumer Demand

3.3.1 Linear functions yet again and dot product In 2D, a homogenous linear scalar function takes the general form:

Some Notes on Adverse Selection

ECON2285: Mathematical Economics

The Ohio State University Department of Economics. Homework Set Questions and Answers

Unlinked Allocations in an Exchange Economy with One Good and One Bad

UNIVERSIDAD CARLOS III DE MADRID MATHEMATICS II EXERCISES (SOLUTIONS )

Final Exam (Solution) Economics 501b Microeconomic Theory

1 General Equilibrium

Risk Aversion over Incomes and Risk Aversion over Commodities. By Juan E. Martinez-Legaz and John K.-H. Quah 1

Partial Solutions to Homework 2

EconS Microeconomic Theory I Recitation #5 - Production Theory-I 1

Lecture 7: General Equilibrium - Existence, Uniqueness, Stability

Consumer theory Topics in consumer theory. Microeconomics. Joana Pais. Fall Joana Pais

Chiang/Wainwright: Fundamental Methods of Mathematical Economics

8. MARKET POWER: STATIC MODELS

Advanced Microeconomics Problem Set 1

Non-parametric Identi cation and Testable Implications of the Roy Model

CONSUMPTION. (Lectures 4, 5, and 6) Remark: (*) signals those exercises that I consider to be the most important

Optimization Paul Schrimpf September 12, 2018

Microeconomics, Block I Part 2

Walrasian Equilibrium in an exchange economy

Notes on Consumer Theory

Using Economic Contexts to Advance in Mathematics

INTENSITY OF THE SENSE OF FAIRNESS: MEASUREMENT AND BEHAVIORAL CHARACTERIZATION. October 2000

3/1/2016. Intermediate Microeconomics W3211. Lecture 3: Preferences and Choice. Today s Aims. The Story So Far. A Short Diversion: Proofs

Chapter 1. GMM: Basic Concepts

Concave Consumption Function and Precautionary Wealth Accumulation. Richard M. H. Suen University of Connecticut. Working Paper November 2011

Beyond CES: Three Alternative Classes of Flexible Homothetic Demand Systems

Microeconomics. Joana Pais. Fall Joana Pais

Received 24 November 2015; accepted 17 January 2016; published 20 January 2016

Duality. for The New Palgrave Dictionary of Economics, 2nd ed. Lawrence E. Blume

Midterm #1 EconS 527 Wednesday, February 21st, 2018

U b (x b ) = xb 1x b 2 x a 1. means the consumption of good i by an h-type person.

Index. Cambridge University Press An Introduction to Mathematics for Economics Akihito Asano. Index.

Structural Properties of Utility Functions Walrasian Demand

Transcription:

Gi en Demand for Several Goods Peter Norman Sørensen January 28, 2011 Abstract The utility maimizing consumer s demand function may simultaneously possess the Gi en property for any number of goods strictly less than all. By way of a simple eample it is possible to illuminate the preference characteristics conducive to such a result. Department of Economics, University of Copenhagen, Øster Farimagsgade 5 Building 26, DK 1353 Copenhagen K, Denmark. Phone: +45 3532 3056. Fa: +45 3532 3000. E-mail: peter.sorensen@econ.ku.dk. Web: http://www.econ.ku.dk/sorensen. 1

1 Introduction Recent eamples of simple, standard utility functions can be used to obtain a fuller understanding of the Gi en e ect in standard demand theory. 1 The Gi en e ect arises when a consumer s demand for a good is locally increasing in the good s own price. Microeconomics tetbooks often mention that the demand function for one good may possess the Gi en property; that Gi en goods must be inferior; and that not all goods can be simultaneously inferior. By implication, not all goods can be simultaneously Gi en. 2 Here, the converse statement is eplored. Any number but one of the goods can simultaneously have the Gi en property. A particular price-income pair is held ed, and the demand for each good in question is locally a strictly increasing function of its own price. 3 Generalizing the main idea from Sørensen s (2007) two-good analysis, the present article considers a consumer with utility function u() = minfu 1 (); : : : ; u L ()g, where u 1 ; : : : ; u L are themselves standard utility functions over L-good consumption bundles = ( 1 ; : : : ; L ). The utility function u represents preferences for perfect complements in the intermediate utility indices u 1 ; : : : ; u L. Bearing in mind that the most popular eamples of utility functions (perfect substitutes, perfect complements, Cobb-Douglas, constant elasticity of substitution) derive the utility inde as some weighted average of the consumed amounts 1 ; : : : ; L, it is natural to compound the average of such averages. 4 Along the lines of Sørensen (2007), the focus is on the budget situations where the consumer optimally demands a bundle ^ at an intersection of the L indi erence surfaces, u 1 (^) = = u L (^) = ^u. At such a corner of the indi erence surface u() = ^u, there is no substitution e ect as the price changes. The consumer s reaction to a small price increase is then equivalent to the reaction to a small income reduction. 5 A good now has 1 Heijman and von Mouche (2009) survey the literature. 2 For completeness, a new version of this result is spelled out towards the end of this article. 3 Holding ed only the price vector, but allowing the income to change, di erent goods can have the Gi en property at di erent income levels. In this weaker sense it is possible for all goods to ehibit the Gi en property at some price vector. An eplicit eample appears in Eample 5 of Sørensen (2004). 4 This construction of utility functions has been suggested before, see e.g. eercise 8.13 of Varian (1992) and eercises 1.12(b) and 1.27 of Jehle and Reny (2001). 5 Figure 17.E.1 of Mas-Colell et al. (1995) illustrates preferences of a very similar nature. The epansion 2

the local Gi en property if and only if it is locally inferior. The only remaining problem is then to place a backward-bending income epansion path, which is analytically simple. 6 2 Utility Let J; L 2 N. Consider a consumer with consumption set R L + whose utility function satis es u() = minfu 1 (); : : : ; u J ()g, where each u j is a function from R L + to R. The utility function u from R L + to R satis es many usual properties if each of the component utility functions u j does so. Here is a list of such properties (see also Section 3.B of Mas- Colell et al., 1995). Property (vi) is also known as conveity of the underlying preference relation. (i) Continuity: u is a continuous function. (ii) Monotonicity: if y, then u (y) > u (). (iii) Strong Monotonicity: if y and y 6= then u (y) > u (). (iv) Weak Monotonicity: if y then u (y) u (). (v) Concavity: u is a concave function. (vi) Quasi-Concavity: for any u 2 R, the upper contour set 2 R L + : u () u conve. is (vii) Strict Quasi-Concavity: for any u 2 R, any ; y 2 R L + with 6= y, and any 2 (0; 1), if u () u and u (y) u, then u ( + (1 ) y) > u. (viii) Homogeneity of Degree 1: u maps R L + into R +, and u () = u () for all 2 R +. It is easy to verify that each of those 8 properties, one by one, is inherited by u from u 1 ; : : : ; u J : curves are parallel to the aes, providing a Gi en neutrality e ect, where the demand for a good does not respond to a marginal change in its own price. 6 constructing a utility function with Gi en demand, Mo att (2002) proceeds in the reverse direction. He rst takes the backward-bending income epansion path, and then attaches a string of nearly-kinked indi erence curves to it. 3

Lemma 1 Let n 2 fi; : : : ; viiig. Suppose that u 1 ; : : : ; u J all satisfy property (n). Then u satis es (n). Proof. (i) min is a continuous function, and continuity is preserved by the composition of functions. (ii) and (iii) Suppose y and are as assumed in the property. By de nition of u there eists some j such that u (y) = u j (y). Given that u j satis es the property, then u () u j () < u j (y) = u (y). (iv) Similar to (ii) and (iii), ecept that the assumption is u j () u j (y), which su ces for the conclusion. (v) Let ; y 2 R L + and 2 [0; 1], and verify Jensen s inequality: u ( + (1 ) y) = minfu 1 ( + (1 ) y); : : : ; u J ( + (1 ) y)g minfu 1 ()+(1 ) u 1 (y) ; : : : ; u J ()+(1 ) u J (y)g u ()+(1 ) u (y), where the rst inequality uses the concavity of the u j functions with min being increasing in its arguments, and the second uses concavity of min. (vi) Suppose that 2 R L + and u 2 R. From the de nition of u, u () u if and only if for every j, u j () u. Thus the upper contour set for u is the intersection of the J sets for u 1 ; : : : ; u J. Since the intersection of conve sets is conve, (vi) follows. (vii) Suppose that u; ; y; are given as stated, and that u () ; u (y) u. By the de nition of u, there eists some j such that u ( + (1 ) y) = u j ( + (1 ) y). As noticed in the proof of (vi), we must have u j () ; u j (y) u. Since u j satis es (vii), it follows that u ( + (1 ) y) = u j ( + (1 ) y) > u as desired. (viii) We obtain u() = minfu 1 (); : : : ; u J ()g = minfu 1 (); : : : ; u J ()g = minfu 1 (); : : : ; u J ()g = u (). If the consumption set allows good 1 to vary throughout all of R, a straightforward eercise proves that Lemma 1 also applies to this property of quasi-linearity with respect to good 1: u ( + e 1 ) = u () + for all 2 R, where e 1 = (1; 0; : : : ; 0). Lemma 1 can be generalized to handle the minimum of an in nite family of utility functions. Suppose thus that U () = min j2i u (; j) where I is a compact set and u is continuous. These assumptions guarantee that the minimum is achieved, but also imply that U is continuous by the Theorem of the Maimum. It is a straightforward eercise to see that the proof of Lemma 1 can be modi ed to show that the other 7 properties (ii),...,(viii) of u (; j) are again inherited by U. The following standard result will be useful in the remainder. 4

Lemma 2 Suppose that u is a function from R L + to R satisfying (i) continuity, (ii) monotonicity and (vi) quasi-concavity. For any 2 R L +, there eists p 2 R L + such that u (y) > u () implies p y > p. If u is di erentiable at with ru () 6= 0, then p must be proportional to ru (). Proof. First, let A = y 2 R L +ju (y) > u (). Properties (i) and (vi) imply that A is open and conve, and =2 A by construction. A standard separation theorem for conve sets, such as 11.2 in Rockafellar (1970), yields the eistence of p 2 R L with p y > p for all y 2 A. Also, p 0 is necessary since (ii) implies that fg + R L ++ A. Second, suppose that u is di erentiable at with ru () 6= 0. If p is not proportional to ru (), then there eists z 2 R L with p z < 0 < ru () z. By di erentiability, there eists " > 0 with u ( + "z) > u (), so that + "z 2 A. The separation result then implies p ( + "z) > p, in contradiction to p z < 0. 3 Demand Suppose L 2. Given income m > 0 and price vector p = (p 1 ; : : : ; p L ) 2 R L ++, the consumer chooses = ( 1 ; : : : ; L ) to maimize utility u () subject to the budget constraint p = p 1 1 + + p L L m. The maimand is the Marshallian demand (p; m). The Marshallian demand for good ` possesses the Gi en property at price-income pair (p; m) if there is a strictly positive marginal response in ` (p; m) to a partial change in p`. In the following, we will suppose that J = L and that the consumer s utility function satis es u() = minfu 1 (); : : : ; u L ()g. We wish to study the consumer s demand function near a situation where the demanded bundle sits at a kink of the indi erence surface for u. Naturally, such a kink arises at where u 1 () = = u J () and the gradient vectors ru 1 () ; : : : ; ru J () are linearly independent. Note that such a point would not de ne a kink of the indi erence surface if J < L, and that J L of the functions u j would be redundant in the de nition of the utility function u near if J > L. Hence, the remainder of the tet assumes J = L. Proposition 3 Suppose that u 1 ; : : : u L all satisfy (i) continuity, (ii) monotonicity and (vi) 5

quasi-concavity. Assume that ^ 2 R L ++ solves u 1 (^) = = u L (^), that u 1 ; : : : ; u L are C 1 at ^, and that the gradient vectors ru 1 (^) ; : : : ; ru L (^) are linearly independent. Take as given any price vector ^p = 1 ru 1 (^) + + L ru L (^) with ( 1 ; : : : ; L ) 0, and let ^m = ^p ^. De ne ^d 2 R L n f0g by ^d = 1 1 ru 1 (^) j j ru L (^) 1 : (1) If ^d` < 0, then good ` is a Gi en good near (^p; ^m) for the consumer with utility function u. Proof. First, observe that ^ is a solution to the utility maimization problem given (^p; ^m). De ne ^u 2 R by ^u = u 1 (^). By de nitions, ^ is feasible in the problem and achieves utility level ^u. Consider any y 2 R L + with u (y) > ^u. Observe that for any j, u j (y) u (y) > ^u = u j (^). By Lemma 2 applied to u j, then ru j (^) y > ru j (^) ^. Since every j > 0, it follows that ^p y > ^p ^ = ^m, so any such y lies outside the budget set. Second, by the Theorem of the Maimum, the maimal utility that the consumer can achieve is a continuous function of (p; m). Since the utility functions u j are C 1, and since the gradient vectors are linearly independent, the rst part of the proof etends to an open region of price-income pairs (p; m) near (^p; ^m), in which region a solution (p; m) near ^ to the utility maimization problem solves the equations u 1 ( (p; m)) = = u L ( (p; m)) = ~u (p; m) for some ~u (p; m) near ^u. Third, an increase in the price of good ` will ceteris paribus decrease the utility level, so the demanded bundle moves along the curve solving u 1 () = = u L () = ~u for decreasing utility level ~u. The claim is then that ` is a decreasing function of ~u when ^d` < 0. This follows from an application of the implicit function theorem to the L equations u 1 () = ~u; : : : ; u L () = ~u. The proposition actually veri es a stronger property than Gi en s when more than one good is involved. If the entries in ^d are negative for all of some subset K of the goods, then holding ed the income as well as prices of all other goods, the Marshallian demand for all K goods in the subset will increase when all their prices are simultaneously marginally increased. The proposition eploits the zero substitution e ect at a kink in the indi erence curve. 6

This etreme can be relaed through approimation. The function minfu 1 ; : : : ; u L g is approimated by the constant elasticity of substitution (CES) function (u 1 + + u L )1= as! 1. If u 1 ; : : : ; u L are concave functions of, then also u () = (u 1 () + + u L ())1= is concave in. The function u therefore represents continous, monotone, conve preferences. When is su ciently large, all indi erence curves near ^ are su ciently close to those of minfu 1 (); : : : ; u L ()g, and the sign of ^d determines whether the good is Gi en also in the CES case. 4 Eample An eample will illustrate how the proposition can be applied to construct demand functions with local Gi en behavior. Let L 2. Suppose that each u j is of the familiar Cobb-Douglas form u j ( 1 ; : : : ; L ) = a j1 1 a jl L ; (2) with strictly positive constants a j1 ; : : : ; a jl. This utility function satis es (i) continuity, (ii) monotonicity and (vi) quasi-concavity. Speci cally, we will suppose that the vectors a 1 ; : : : ; a L 2 R L + are de ned by a j = (1; : : : ; 1; b; 1; : : : ; 1) =c j with b > 1 in the j th coordinate, and c j b + L 1. Since a j1 + + a jl 1, the utility function u j is concave. For the sake of the eample, focus will be on the consumption bundle ^ = (1; : : : ; 1). For ^u = 1, we have u j (^) = ^u; and u j is C 1 at ^ with ru j (^) = a 0 j. The assumptions of the proposition are satis ed, so calculation of the vector ^d helps to determine which are Gi en goods at ^. It is simple to verify that ru1 (^) j j ru L (^) 1 = G (3) where row j of matri G is g j = c j [ 1; : : : ; 1; b + L 2; 1; : : : ; 1] (4) b (b + L 2) (L 1) with b + L 2 in the j th coordinate. Note that b > 1 and L 2 imply b + L 2 > 1 as well as b (b + L 2) (L 1) > 0. 7

Now, it follows from (1) that ^d` = LX g j` = c` (b + L 2) b (b + L 2) (L 1) : (5) j=1 P j6=` cj Since the denominator is positive, it should be clear that the sign of ^d` is determined by the relative size of c` to P j6=` cj. In particular, ^d` < 0 and ` is a local Gi en good around the price-income pairs de ned in the proposition, when c` is su ciently relatively small. The only assumption is that each such positive constant is at least b + L 1, so it is not hard to make all but one such constant relatively small (by making the last one very large). For an illustration, let 1 k < L and suppose that b + L 1 c 1 = : : : = c k < c k+1 = : : : = c L. Each of the rst k goods will simultaneously be local Gi en goods provided c 1 (b + L 2 k + 1) < (L k) c L. This is true when c L is su ciently large. A natural interpretation of the utility function minfu 1 (); : : : ; u L ()g follows from Lancaster s (1966) new consumer theory, in which consumers care about characteristics produced by the purchased bundle. In the present contet, think of the concave Cobb- Douglas functions as production functions. 7 The assumption that b > 1 means that factor ` is relatively essential for the production of characteristic `. The illustration then provides the important insight that, given the eistence of a kink point ^, good ` is more likely to be Gi en if c` is relatively large. This means that the production of characteristic ` o ers a relatively high marginal return to all its inputs. The following intuitive reason can then eplain the Gi en property. When the price of good ` rises, the production of all characteristics will be scaled back. Since characteristics are perfect complements, those with lower marginal returns can scale back their relatively essential factors a lot for a small reduction in the characteristic. In turn, this scaling back would give too great a reduction in the high-marginal return characteristic ` if it were not for an increase in its relatively essential factor `. 7 This interpretation does not permit the consumer to allocate inputs in di erent proportions across productive activities. Lancaster (1966) formulates the model both with and without such a possibility. 8

5 Converse As already mentioned in the introduction, it is commonly accepted that there cannot eist a price-income pair at which all L goods are simultaneously Gi en. The standard derivation of this result goes via the Slutsky equation. The argument thus invokes an assumption of di erentiability of the demand function which needs not always be satis ed. For the sake of completeness, here is a result derived from rst principles. The solution to the utility maimization problem must satisfy the following weak aiom of revealed preferences (WARP). Given two pairs (p; m) ; (p 0 ; m 0 ) 2 R L+1 ++, if (p; m) 6= (p 0 ; m 0 ) and if p (p 0 ; m 0 ) m then p 0 (p; m) > m 0. Interpreting this, p (p 0 ; m 0 ) m implies that (p 0 ; m 0 ) is a feasible choice at (p; m), so that utility maimization reveals the preference relation u ( (p; m)) > u ( (p 0 ; m 0 )). 8 For convenience, it will be assumed that the demand function is continuous. only purpose of this assumption in the argument is to ensure that there is a neighborhood around the hypothetical L Gi en good point (p; m) in which the demand function is bounded away from zero in all coordinates. Continuity of the demand function can be derived as a necessary implication of properties (i) continuity and (vii) strict quasi-concavity of the utility function. Proposition 4 Suppose that the demand function is continuous. The There does not eist any (p; m) 2 R L+1 ++ with the property that for all ` 2 f1; : : : ; Lg, good ` is is Gi en in a neighborhood of (p; m). Proof. Suppose to the contrary that such (p; m) 2 R L+1 ++ eists. The proof will seek a contradiction. Denote 0 = (p; m). Observe that 0 0 since the non-negative consumption of every good will be strictly smaller when its own price falls. Observe also that p 0 = m, for there would otherwise eist ^p = p + "p 1 close enough to p with " > 0 such that ^p 0 m, in contradiction to the WARP because (^p; m) 6= 0 and p (^p; m) ^p (^p; m) m. Denote `1 = 1. Choose p 1 2 R L ++ close to p such that p 1` = p` for all ` 6= `1; and p 1`1 > p`1. Denote 1 = (p 1 ; m). Observe that 1`1 > 0`1 0 8 See for instance chapters 1 3 in Mas-Colell, Whinston and Green (1995) for details. 9

since `1 is a local Gi en good. Also, p 1 < p 1 1 m = p 0 ; ruling out 1 0. Hence, there eists some `2 2 f2; : : : ; Lg with the property that 1`2 < 0`2. Net, choose p 2 2 R L ++ such that p 2` = p` for all ` 6= `2; and p p`1 1`1 1 = p `1 2`2 p`2 1 `2. Denote 2 = (p 2 ; m). Note that p 2 is arbitrarily close to p when p 1 was chosen close enough to p. By construction, p 2 1 = p`1 1`1 + p 2`2 1`2 + P`6=`1;`2 p` 1` = p1`1 1`1 + p`2 1`2 + P`6=`1;`1 p` 1` = p1 1 m. Since `2 is a local Gi en good, 2`2 > 0`2 > 1`2, so 2 6= 1. By the WARP, we have u ( 2 ) > u ( 1 ) and p 1 2 > m p 2 2. Epanding this inequality, observe that p p`1 1`1 2 > p `1 2`2 p`2 2 > p `2 2`2 p`2 1 = p `2 1`1 p`1 1 `1, implying 2`1 > 1`1 > 0`1. Re-iterating the previous argument, 2 0 is impossible, so there must eist some `3 6= `1; `2 with 2`3 < 0`3. Repeat this step inductively, until a nal L-th iteration, in L 1 = `L 1 which p L 2 R L ++ is de ned by p L` = p` for all ` 6= `L 1 ; and p L 1 `L 1 p`l 1 p L`L p`l L 1 `L. Continuity of the demand function implies that if the rst choice of p 1 is su ciently close to p, then every p 2 ; : : : ; p L constructed in this fashion is so close to p that all the Gi en properties hold. Again, u L > u L 1 by the WARP, implying L`L 1 > L 1 `L 1 > 0`L 1. The Gi en good property of L and the result of the previous induction step give L`L > 0`L > L 1. Also, for every z 2 f1; : : : ; L 1g, u L > `L u L z implies p L z L > m = p L L. This is epanded as p L z `L z p`l z L > `L z p L`L p`l L `L > p L`L p`l L 1 `L = p L 1 `L 1 p`l 1 L 1 `L 1 > > p L z `L z p`l z L z. `L z Hence, L`L z > L z `L z > 0`L z for every z 2 f1; : : : ; L 1g. Since also L`L > 0`L, it follows that L 0. This is the desired contradiction to p L < p L L = m = p 0. 6 References Heijman Wim and von Mouche Pierre, On Simple Concrete Gi en Utility Functions: Old and New Results, discussion paper, 2009, Mansholt Graduate School. Jehle, Geo rey A. and Philip J. Reny, Advanced Microeconomic Theory, Second Edition, 2001, Addison-Wesley. Lancaster Kelvin J., A New Approach to Consumer Theory, Journal of Political Economy, 1966, 74, 132 157. Mas-Colell, Andreu, Michael D. Whinston and Jerry R. Green, Microeconomic Theory, 10

1995, Oford University Press. Mo att, Peter G., Is Gi en behaviour compatible with the aioms of consumer theory, Journal of Mathematical Economics, 2002, 37, 259 267. Sørensen, Peter N., Simple Utility Functions with Gi en Demand, discussion paper 04-22, 2004, University of Copenhagen. Sørensen, Peter N., Simple Utility Functions with Gi en Demand, Economic Theory, 2007, 31, 367 370. Varian, Hal R., Microeconomic Analysis, Third Edition, 1992, Norton. 11