Model theory, algebraic dynamics and local fields

Similar documents
Model theory, algebraic dynamics and local fields

p-jets and Uniform Unramified Manin-Mumford

Model theory, algebraic dynamics and local fields

Model theory, stability, applications

MODEL THEORY OF DIFFERENCE FIELDS

Applications of model theory in extremal graph combinatorics

Intermediate Model Theory

Model Theory of Differential Fields

A MODEL-THEORETIC PROOF OF HILBERT S NULLSTELLENSATZ

More Model Theory Notes

MATH 8253 ALGEBRAIC GEOMETRY WEEK 12

Measures in model theory

Tame definable topological dynamics

THE ABSOLUTE MORDELL-LANG CONJECTURE IN POSITIVE CHARACTERISTIC. 1. Introduction

A trichotomy of countable, stable, unsuperstable theories

Lecture 2: Syntax. January 24, 2018

PRESERVATION THEOREMS IN LUKASIEWICZ MODEL THEORY

2010 SUMMER COURSE ON MODEL THEORY: CHAPTER 1

HOW DO ULTRAFILTERS ACT ON THEORIES? THE CUT SPECTRUM AND TREETOPS

MATHEMATICS: CONCEPTS, AND FOUNDATIONS Vol. II - Model Theory - H. Jerome Keisler

Geometry with Valuations

What is the right type-space? Humboldt University. July 5, John T. Baldwin. Which Stone Space? July 5, Tameness.

Pseudofinite Model Theory. Anand Pillay, and friends

ω-stable Theories: Introduction

Lecture 1: Overview. January 24, 2018

AN INTRODUCTION TO GEOMETRIC STABILITY THEORY

Disjoint n-amalgamation

This is logically equivalent to the conjunction of the positive assertion Minimal Arithmetic and Representability

Basic Model Theory of Algebraically Closed Fields

Math 225A Model Theory. Speirs, Martin

Classifying classes of structures in model theory

VC-dimension in model theory and other subjects

Compact complex manifolds with the DOP and other properties.

Model theory of algebraically closed fields

Model Theory and Differential Algebraic Geometry

Introduction to Model Theory

FINITE MODEL THEORY (MATH 285D, UCLA, WINTER 2017) LECTURE NOTES IN PROGRESS

MORLEY S CATEGORICITY THEOREM

Introduction. Itaï Ben-Yaacov C. Ward Henson. September American Institute of Mathematics Workshop. Continuous logic Continuous model theory

Löwenheim-Skolem Theorems, Countable Approximations, and L ω. David W. Kueker (Lecture Notes, Fall 2007)

Definably amenable groups in NIP

Handbook of Logic and Proof Techniques for Computer Science

Introduction to Model Theory

AN APPROXIMATE LOGIC FOR MEASURES

MODEL THEORY FOR ALGEBRAIC GEOMETRY

NONSINGULAR CURVES BRIAN OSSERMAN

The Vaught Conjecture Do uncountable models count?

Categoricity Without Equality

Morley s Proof. Winnipeg June 3, 2007

Model Theory and Modules, Granada

INVERSE LIMITS AND PROFINITE GROUPS

POSITIVE CHARACTERISTIC MANIN-MUMFORD THEOREM

Pseudo-finite model theory

Non-standard tight closure for affine C-algebras

A DISCUSSION OF KEISLER S ORDER

COMPLEX VARIETIES AND THE ANALYTIC TOPOLOGY

Proof Theory and Subsystems of Second-Order Arithmetic

Fifty Years in the Model Theory of Differential Fields. ASL Winter Meeting 2019 JMM Baltimore

tp(c/a) tp(c/ab) T h(m M ) is assumed in the background.

Math 418 Algebraic Geometry Notes

Embedding Differential Algebraic Groups in Algebraic Groups

EXCURSIONS IN MODEL THEORY

DIVIDING AND WEAK QUASI-DIMENSIONS IN ARBITRARY THEORIES

Qualifying Exam Logic August 2005

On Mordell-Lang in Algebraic Groups of Unipotent Rank 1

Lattices, closure operators, and Galois connections.

Meta-logic derivation rules

Solutions to Unique Readability Homework Set 30 August 2011

Stable embeddedness and N IP

HINDMAN S THEOREM AND IDEMPOTENT TYPES. 1. Introduction

A Super Introduction to Reverse Mathematics

Boolean Algebras, Boolean Rings and Stone s Representation Theorem

On the strong cell decomposition property for weakly o-minimal structures

Weight and measure in NIP theories

The Countable Henkin Principle

PROBLEMS, MATH 214A. Affine and quasi-affine varieties

VAUGHT S THEOREM: THE FINITE SPECTRUM OF COMPLETE THEORIES IN ℵ 0. Contents

Syntactic Characterisations in Model Theory

ALGEBRAIC RELATIONS AMONGST PERIODIC POINTS OF A LIFTING OF FROBENIUS

Foundations. September 4, Foundations. A Model Theoretic Perspective. John T. Baldwin. sociology. Thesis I. Thesis II. A Concept Analysis

Exploring the Exotic Setting for Algebraic Geometry

AMS regional meeting Bloomington, IN April 1, 2017

ULTRAPRODUCTS AND MODEL THEORY

Ultraproducts and the Foundations of Higher Order Fourier Analysis

1 Model theory; introduction and overview

Topology. Xiaolong Han. Department of Mathematics, California State University, Northridge, CA 91330, USA address:

08a. Operators on Hilbert spaces. 1. Boundedness, continuity, operator norms

USING ULTRAPOWERS TO CHARACTERIZE ELEMENTARY EQUIVALENCE

Definability in fields Lecture 1: Undecidabile arithmetic, decidable geometry

Generalizing Gödel s Constructible Universe:

Isomorphisms of Non-Standard Fields and Ash s Conjecture

Reid 5.2. Describe the irreducible components of V (J) for J = (y 2 x 4, x 2 2x 3 x 2 y + 2xy + y 2 y) in k[x, y, z]. Here k is algebraically closed.

Introduction to Model theory Zoé Chatzidakis CNRS (Paris 7) Notes for Luminy, November 2001

INTRODUCTION TO GEOMETRIC STABILITY

Lecture 6: Etale Fundamental Group

arxiv:math.lo/ v1 28 Nov 2004

2. Prime and Maximal Ideals

Course 311: Michaelmas Term 2005 Part III: Topics in Commutative Algebra

Lectures on Zariski-type structures Part I

March 3, The large and small in model theory: What are the amalgamation spectra of. infinitary classes? John T. Baldwin

Transcription:

Model theory, algebraic dynamics and local fields Thomas Scanlon University of California, Berkeley 8 June 2010 Thomas Scanlon (University of California, Berkeley) Model theory, algebraic dynamics and local fields 8 June 2010 1 / 19

Compactness theorem Theorem Let T be a set of sentences in some first-order language L (τ) and suppose that for each finite subset T 0 T that there is some model M 0 = T 0, then there is a model M = T. There are several proofs of the compactness theorem; the original being a corollary of Gödel s Completeness Theorem (not the more famous Incompleteness Theorems) while the best known version to non-logicians is obtained as a corollary of Loś s Theorem on ultraproducts. Thomas Scanlon (University of California, Berkeley) Model theory, algebraic dynamics and local fields 8 June 2010 2 / 19

Loś s Theorem on Ultraproduct Given a collection of L (τ) structures M i i I indexed by some nonempty set I, there is a natural product i I M i whose underlying universe is the product in the category of sets. Given a finitely additive {0, 1}-valued measure µ : P(I ) {0, 1} (or, equivalently, an ultrafilter: U := µ 1 {1}), one may define an equivalence relation on the product by (a i ) U (b i ) µ({i I : a i = b i }) = 1 and the quotient of the product by this equivalence relation is naturally an L (τ)-structure called the ultraproduct /U M i Theorem ( Loś) If φ is any L (σ)-sentence, then M i = φ {i I : M i = φ} U /U Thomas Scanlon (University of California, Berkeley) Model theory, algebraic dynamics and local fields 8 June 2010 3 / 19

Proof of compactness from Loś s theorem Let I be the set of all finite subset of T. For each T 0 I, let M T0 = T 0 be some model of that finite set. By a standard Zorn s Lemma argument, one shows that there is a finitely additive {0, 1}-valued measure µ on I such that for each T 0 I we have µ({s I : T 0 S}) = 1. Set M := µ M T 0. Then if φ T, since {S I : M S = φ} {S I : {φ} S}, we have that µ({s I : M S = φ}) = 1. Hence, by Loś s Theorem, M = T. Thomas Scanlon (University of California, Berkeley) Model theory, algebraic dynamics and local fields 8 June 2010 4 / 19

Corollary of compactness: Undefinability of finiteness Theorem Let L (τ) be any first-order language, φ(x, y) an L (τ) formula with free variables x and y and T an L (τ) theory. Then either there is a number N = N(φ) such that for any model M = T and parameter b from M if φ(m, b) is finite, then it has cardinality at most N or {b M : φ(m, b) is finite } is not definable relative to T. Proof. If such a bound N exists, then the set of parameters b for which φ(n, b) is finite is defined by the formula ( x 1 ) ( x N+1 )( N+1 i=1 φ(x i, y) i<j x i = x j ) Thomas Scanlon (University of California, Berkeley) Model theory, algebraic dynamics and local fields 8 June 2010 5 / 19

Proof, continued Theorem Let L (τ) be any first-order language, φ(x, y) an L (τ) formula with free variables x and y and T an L (τ) theory. Then either there is a number N = N(φ) such that for any model M = T and parameter b from M if φ(m, b) is finite, then it has cardinality at most N or {b M : φ(m, b) is finite } is not definable relative to T. Proof. Suppose no such bound exists but that the formula ϑ(y) defines the set of parameters for which φ(m, y) is finite as M ranges through the models of T. The following set of sentences in L (τ ) where τ is obtained from τ by adding one new constant symbol c would be finitely satisfiable T {ϑ(c)} {( x 1 ) ( x n ) n i=1 φ(x i, c)& i<j x i x j By compactness, there is a model (M, c) of this set of sentences and we have M = T, φ(m, c) is infinite, but M = ϑ(c). Thomas Scanlon (University of California, Berkeley) Model theory, algebraic dynamics and local fields 8 June 2010 6 / 19

Soft proofs of boundedness From the principle that finite definable sets have bounded cardinality, we can sometimes prove the existence of bounds at the cost of proving finiteness in every model. The fact that if f : X Y is a map of varieties over an algebraically closed field K then there is a number N so that for any point y Y (K) either f 1 {y} N or f 1 {y} is infinite is a reflection of this principle. It does not follow from Faltings theorem (as a simple application of compactness) that there is a bound depending just on the genus g > 1 for the number of rational points on a curve of genus g. It would follow if one could show that for a nonstandard model of the theory of the rationals that every high genus curve has only finitely many rational points. Thomas Scanlon (University of California, Berkeley) Model theory, algebraic dynamics and local fields 8 June 2010 7 / 19

Injective self-morphisms Theorem (Ax) If f : X X is a regular self-map on a complex algebraic variety which is injective on C-points, then f is surjective. Proof. The result is true with F alg p in place of C as f : X (F alg p ) X (F alg p ) may be expressed as a direct limit of injective (and, therefore, surjective) self-maps on finite sets. The statement of the theorem is not a first-order sentence in the language of rings, but by restricting the complexity of the defining equations for X and f it may be expressed as a set of sentences. It follows by compactness that the theorem is true for some algebraically closed field of characteristic zero and then by completeness of the theory of algebraically closed fields of a fixed characteristic, for all algebraically closed fields. homas Scanlon (University of California, Berkeley) Model theory, algebraic dynamics and local fields 8 June 2010 8 / 19

Secret ingredient? From what I can see of the paper so far, the proofs of the combinatorial statements in Hrushovski s paper proceed by a correspondence principle or compactness and contradiction method, in which one assumes that the combinatorial statement fails, and extracts from this (via compactness) some infinitary limit structure which is supposed to ultimately lead to some sort of contradiction. Fair enough I ve seen many arguments of this sort before, such as in Gromov s proof of his theorem on groups of polynomial growth, or Furstenberg s proof of Szemerédi s theorem. My question though is what is the secret ingredient in the infinitary world that makes this correspondence powerful, and which is then difficult to replicate in the finitary world? T. Tao, 19 October 2009 Thomas Scanlon (University of California, Berkeley) Model theory, algebraic dynamics and local fields 8 June 2010 9 / 19

Is stability the secret? Here is a kind of response to Terence Tao s question about the power of the model theoretic methods. As with the other examples he mentions (theory of topological groups, measurable dynamics,...) there is a powerful and nontrivial theory around, namely stability theory, or rather neo-stability theory. This is a specialised area of model theory, which many people in the subject may not be exposed to. Stability theory (developed originally by Shelah) includes notions of forking, stationarity, orthogonality,... and was originally developed just in the context of stable (first order) theories, for reasons I will not go into here.... So my basic point is that there is a theory here, going considerably beyond compactness, which one is plugging into. A. Pillay, 20 October 2009 Thomas Scanlon (University of California, Berkeley) Model theory, algebraic dynamics and local fields 8 June 2010 10 / 19

Automatic uniformity Theorem (S., following Hrushovski, Pillay) Let X be an algebraic variety over a field K and Ξ X (K) a set of K-rational points. We say that a subvariety Y X n is Ξ-special if Y = Y (K) Ξ n. Suppose that the class of Ξ-special varieties is closed under intersection. Then for any algebraic family Y X B of subvarieties of X there is an associated constructible family Z X C so that for any b B(K) there is some c C(K) with Y b (K) Ξ = Z c. In particular, this implies that there is a bound depending just on the family for the cardinality of Y b (K) Ξ when finite. The hypotheses apply directly to the Manin-Mumford and André-Oort conjectures yielding bounds for the complexity of the exceptional groups and Hecke correspondences appearing in the conclusions. One may weaken the hypotheses asking only that if Y, Z X n are Ξ special and C is a component of X Y with C(K) Ξ n, then C is Ξ special and thereby include the Mordell-Lang conjecture and its dynamical variants. homas Scanlon (University of California, Berkeley) Model theory, algebraic dynamics and local fields 8 June 2010 11 / 19

Ingredients in proof of automatic uniformity The proof of automatic uniformity is soft, using compactness, but also a large dose of (elementary) stability theory. The principle in question here goes under the name of Lagrange interpolation in algebraic geometry but more generally is (uniform) definability of types: Theorem (Shelah) Suppose that T is a stable theory, M = T is a model of T, and A M n is a subset of some cartesian power of the universe of M and X M n is an M-definable set, then there is an A-definable set Y M n for which X (M) A = Y (M) A. Moreover, if X varies in a definable family, then Y may be chosen from a fixed definable family. The moreover clause, namely, the assertion of uniformity, follows from the first part of the theorem via a nontrivial compactness argument. Thomas Scanlon (University of California, Berkeley) Model theory, algebraic dynamics and local fields 8 June 2010 12 / 19

What is stability theory? Stability theory arose from Morley s proof of Loś s Categoricity conjecture (if T is a countable theory having the property that for some uncountable cardinal κ there is exactly one model of T of size κ up to isomorphism, then for every uncountable cardinal λ there is exactly one model of T of size λ). The central objects of study are types. Indeed, combinatorially, the most natural definition of stability is in terms of numbers of types: a theory T is stable just in case for some cardinal κ T for any model M = T of cardinality at most κ, there are no more than κ many 1-types over M. Thomas Scanlon (University of California, Berkeley) Model theory, algebraic dynamics and local fields 8 June 2010 13 / 19

What is a type? Definition If M is an L (τ)-structure, A M is a subset of the universe of M, and b M n is a tuple from M, then the type of b over A is tp(b/a) := {φ(x 1,..., x n ) : M = φ(b), φ an L (τ)-formula with parameters from A} More generally, an n-type over A is a complete consistent extension of the theory of M with parameters from A in the language L (τ) augmented by n new constant symbols x 1,..., x n. By the compactness theorem, if p(x) is a type over A, then there is a model N M and a tuple b from N with p = tp(b/a). We write S n (A) for the space of n-types over A. This set carries a natural topology with respect to which it is compact, Hausdorff, and totally disconnected, but the topology may be safely ignored for now. Thomas Scanlon (University of California, Berkeley) Model theory, algebraic dynamics and local fields 8 June 2010 14 / 19

Types relative to the theory of algebraically closed fields Given an algebraically closed field K and a subring k K, there is a natural map ρ : S n (k) A n k = Spec k[x 1,..., x n ] given by p {Q(x 1,..., x n ) k[x 1,..., x n ] : Q(x) = 0 p} It follows from elementary algebra that ρ is surjective. It follows from Tarski s quantifier elimination theorem that ρ is injective. Moreover, ρ is continuous, but it is not a homeomorphism. Thomas Scanlon (University of California, Berkeley) Model theory, algebraic dynamics and local fields 8 June 2010 15 / 19

Types relative to the theory of real closed fields Given a subring k R of the real numbers, again we have a natural map ρ : S n (k) A n k but it is neither injective nor surjective. For example, if k = Q, then tp(π/k) tp(e/k) as ( y)x = y 2 + 3 tp(π/k) tp(e/k) but both these types map to the generic point of A1 Q. Likewise, the point (x 2 + 1) is not in the image of ρ. A correct spectral description of the type space for real fields requires the notion of the real spectrum. Thomas Scanlon (University of California, Berkeley) Model theory, algebraic dynamics and local fields 8 June 2010 16 / 19

Definability of types At one level it does not make sense to speak of types as being definable since they are infinitary objects, but they might reasonably be pro-definable. Definition We say that a type p(x) S n (A) (where A M, M is an L (τ)-structure) is definable if for each formula φ(x; y) = φ(x 1,..., x n ; y 1,..., y m ) there is another formula ψ(y), possibly defined with parameters, such that {a A m : φ(x; a) p} = {a A m : M = ψ(a)} If p(x) = tp(b/a) then it is easy to get a definition of p using b as a parameter: set ψ(y) := φ(b; y). This notion is useful only when we can find the definition of the type over a set of parameters which is somehow independent from the realization. Thomas Scanlon (University of California, Berkeley) Model theory, algebraic dynamics and local fields 8 June 2010 17 / 19

Equivalence of definability of types and stable embeddedness Proposition The following are equivalent for a theory T. If M = T, A M and p(x) S n (A) is a type over A, then p is definable over A. If M = T, A M, X M n is M-definable, then there is Y M n which is A-definable and satisfies X (M) A = Y (M) A. We prove = : Proof. Write X (M) = φ(b; M) for some tuple b from M. As tp(b/a) is A-definable, there is some ψ(y) defined with parameters from A so that for a A we have φ(x; a) tp(b/a) M = ψ(a). That is, letting ψ define Y, we have X (M) A = Y (M) A. Thomas Scanlon (University of California, Berkeley) Model theory, algebraic dynamics and local fields 8 June 2010 18 / 19

Looking ahead: canonical bases and moduli The trick of interchanging the rôles of parameter and object variables and more generally of regarding types themselves as definable objects will recur throughout these lectures. Suppressing some hypotheses, we will associate to a type p(x) its canonical base, Cb(p), which may be identified with the set of φ-definitions of p (as φ ranges through the language). The canonical base acts as a generalized moduli point, or more accurately since definable sets are naturally subobjects, as a kind of point in a Hilbert scheme or Douady space. Our three highlights of the theory of canonical bases are the Chatzidakis/Hrushovski approach to descent in algebraic dynamics, the Pillay/Ziegler jet space theory for difference and differential varieties, and the Hrushovski/Loeser treatment of Berkovich spaces. Thomas Scanlon (University of California, Berkeley) Model theory, algebraic dynamics and local fields 8 June 2010 19 / 19