Von Neumann Morgenstern Expected Utility. I. Introduction, Definitions, and Applications. Decision Theory Spring 2014

Similar documents
14.12 Game Theory Lecture Notes Theory of Choice

Recitation 7: Uncertainty. Xincheng Qiu

Choice under Uncertainty

Almost essential: Consumption and Uncertainty Probability Distributions MICROECONOMICS

Choice under uncertainty

1 Uncertainty. These notes correspond to chapter 2 of Jehle and Reny.

Intertemporal Risk Aversion, Stationarity, and Discounting

Choice Under Uncertainty

Expected Utility Framework

ECO 317 Economics of Uncertainty Fall Term 2009 Notes for lectures 3. Risk Aversion

Follow links for Class Use and other Permissions. For more information send to:

Range-Dependent Utility

1 Uncertainty and Insurance

Quantum Decision Theory

Homework #6 (10/18/2017)

This corresponds to a within-subject experiment: see same subject make choices from different menus.

4.1. Chapter 4. timing risk information utility

Projective Expected Utility

Consumer theory Topics in consumer theory. Microeconomics. Joana Pais. Fall Joana Pais

Utility and Decision Making 1

Advanced Microeconomic Analysis Solutions to Homework #2

Midterm Exam, Econ 210A, Fall 2008

Preference, Choice and Utility

Course Handouts ECON 4161/8001 MICROECONOMIC ANALYSIS. Jan Werner. University of Minnesota

3 Intertemporal Risk Aversion

Professors Blume, Halpern and Easley Econ 476/ December 2004 CIS 576. Final Exam

Asset Pricing. Chapter V. Risk Aversion and Investment Decisions, Part I. June 20, 2006

Utility Theory CHAPTER Single period utility theory

ECON4510 Finance Theory Lecture 1

Game Theory Lecture Notes

Lecture 6: Recursive Preferences

Uncertainty. Michael Peters December 27, 2013

MAS368: Decision making and Bayes linear methods

Name: 180A MIDTERM 2. (x + n)/2

Recursive Ambiguity and Machina s Examples

* Professor of Finance at INSEAD, Boulevard de Constance, Fontainebleau Cedex, France.

Math , Fall 2012: HW 5 Solutions

Pessimistic Portfolio Allocation and Choquet Expected Utility

Game Theory without Decision-Theoretic Paradoxes

THE UTILITY PREMIUM. Louis Eeckhoudt, Catholic Universities of Mons and Lille Research Associate CORE

1: PROBABILITY REVIEW

ECON4510 Finance Theory Lecture 2

Uncertainty & Decision

A CONCEPTUAL FOUNDATION FOR THE THEORY OF RISK AVERSION YONATAN AUMANN. Bar Ilan University Ramat Gan, Israel

Anti-comonotone random variables and Anti-monotone risk aversion

Anscombe & Aumann Expected Utility Betting and Insurance

Fundamentals in Optimal Investments. Lecture I

Pessimistic Portfolio Allocation And Choquet Expected Utility

Ambiguity Aversion: An Axiomatic Approach Using Second Order Probabilities

Chapter 2. Decision Making under Risk. 2.1 Consequences and Lotteries

V. RANDOM VARIABLES, PROBABILITY DISTRIBUTIONS, EXPECTED VALUE

Increases in Risk Aversion and Portfolio Choice in a Complete Market

Econ 101A Midterm 2 Th 8 April 2009.

A CONCEPTUAL FOUNDATION FOR THE THEORY OF RISK AVERSION YONATAN AUMANN. Bar Ilan University Ramat Gan, Israel

The Expected Utility Model

Transitive Regret over Statistically Independent Lotteries

Microeconomic Theory III Spring 2009

Lecture 8. Applications of consumer theory. Randall Romero Aguilar, PhD I Semestre 2017 Last updated: April 27, 2017

Certainty Equivalent Representation of Binary Gambles That Are Decomposed into Risky and Sure Parts

Comments on prospect theory

Increases in Risk Aversion and the Distribution of Portfolio Payoffs

Measurable Ambiguity. with Wolfgang Pesendorfer. August 2009

arxiv: v1 [q-fin.mf] 25 Dec 2015

Skewed Noise. David Dillenberger 1 Uzi Segal 2. 1 University of Pennsylvania 2 Boston College and WBS

Choice with Menu-Dependent Rankings (Presentation Slides)

Expected Utility. Tommaso Denti. February 7, 2015

A Recourse Certainty Equivalent for Decisions Under Uncertainty

MATH 446/546 Homework 2: Due October 8th, 2014

Risk, Choquet Portfolios and Quantile Regression

Institute for Advanced Management Systems Research Department of Information Technologies Åbo Akademi University

Advanced Microeconomics I: Consumers, Firms and Markets Chapters 1+2

ECO 317 Economics of Uncertainty Fall Term 2009 Problem Set 3 Answer Key The distribution was as follows: <

Preference for Commitment

Problem Set 4 - Solution Hints

COMPARATIVE STATICS FOR RANK-DEPENDENT EXPECT- ED UTILITY THEORY

Sequential Decisions

Four notions of mean preserving increase in risk, risk attitudes and applications to the Rank-Dependent Expected Utility model

Msc Micro I exam. Lecturer: Todd Kaplan.

Economics 401 Sample questions 2

Calibration Results for Betweenness Functionals

Mathematical Preliminaries for Microeconomics: Exercises

Psychology and Economics (Lecture 3)

Toward a Systematic Approach to the Economic Effects of Risk: Characterizing Utility Functions

Second-Order Expected Utility

Decision Making Under Uncertainty. First Masterclass

Decision Theory Final Exam Last name I term: (09:50) Instructor: M. Lewandowski, PhD

Utility and rational decision-making

Explaining the harmonic sequence paradox. by Ulrich Schmidt, and Alexander Zimper

Economic Theory and Experimental Economics: Confronting Theory with Experimental Data and vice versa. Risk Preferences

Decision-making with belief functions

Separable Utility Functions in Dynamic Economic Models

Intertemporal Risk Attitude Lecture 5

MATH 56A SPRING 2008 STOCHASTIC PROCESSES

EE290O / IEOR 290 Lecture 05

Introduction to Game Theory: Simple Decisions Models

Behavioral Economics

EFFICIENT, WEAK EFFICIENT, AND PROPER EFFICIENT PORTFOLIOS

Lecture 9. Expectations of discrete random variables

Glimcher Decision Making

Economic Theory and Experimental Economics: Confronting Theory with Experimental Data and vice versa. Lecture I & II Risk preferences

Transcription:

Von Neumann Morgenstern Expected Utility I. Introduction, Definitions, and Applications Decision Theory Spring 2014

Origins Blaise Pascal, 1623 1662 Early inventor of the mechanical calculator Invented Pascal s Triangle Invented expected utility, hedging strategies, and a cynic s argument for faith in God all at once. Pascal s Wager God exists God does not exist live as if he does C + C live for yourself U U

Origins Daniel Bernoulli Mechanics Hydrodynamics Kinetic Theory of Gases Bernoulli s Principle The St. Petersburg Paradox A coin is tossed until a tails comes up. How much would you pay for a lottery ticket that paid off 2 n dollars if the first tails appears on the n th flip?

The St. Petersburg Paradox Average payoff from paying c: E = 1 2 (w c) + 1 4 (w + 2 c) + 1 (w + 4 c) + 8 = 1 2 + 1 2 + 1 2 + + w c = Bernoulli s solution: E = 1 2 log+ (w c) + 1 4 log+ (w + 2 c) + 1 8 log+ (w + 4 c) + This is finite for all w and c. (log + (x) = log max{x, 1}.)

The St. Petersburg Paradox This doesn t solve the problem. Average payoff from paying c: E = 1 2 log+ (w + exp 2 0 c) + 1 4 log+ (w + exp 2 1 c) + 1 8 log+ (w + exp 2 2 c) + = Solution: Utility bounded from above. Restrict the set of gambles.

Preferences on Lotteries X = {x 1,..., x N } A finite set of prizes. P = {p 1,..., p N } A probability distribution. P = {p 1,..., p N } p i is the probability of x i. (0, 0, 1) : x 3 (0, 1, 0) : x 2 (1, 0, 0) : x 1

Preferences on Lotteries x 3 x 2 x 1 For fixed prizes, indifference curves are linear in probabilities.

Lotteries on R A simple lottery is p = (p 1 : x 1,..., p K : x K ) where x 1,..., x K are prizes in R and p 1,..., p K are probabilities. Let L denote the set of simple lotteries. Let u : X R and V (p) = k u(x k )p(x k ). This is the expectation of the random variable u(x) when the the random variable x is described by the probability distribution p.

Lotteries on R How do we see that this is linear in lotteries? For 0 < α < 1 and lotteries p = (p 1 : x 1,..., p K : x K ) and q = (q 1 : y 1,..., q L : y L ), define { x m for m K, z m = y m K for K < m K + L. and αp (1 α)q = (r 1 : z 1,..., r K+L : z K+L ) where r m = { αp m for m K, (1 α)q m K for K < m K + L.

Lotteries on R V (αp (1 α)q) = = = α M r m u(z m ) m=1 K αp m u(x m ) + m=1 K+L m=k+1 K p k u(x k ) + (1 α) k=1 = αv (p) + (1 α)v (q). (1 α)q m K u(y m K ) L q l u(y l ) l=1

Attitudes Towards Risk V (p) = E p {u} = u(x)p(x) x supp p P = {p L : V (p) < }. Definition: An individual is risk averse iff for all p P, E p {u} U(E p {x}). He is risk-loving iff E p {u} u(e p {x}). Theorem A: A Decision-Maker is risk averse iff u is concave, and risk-loving iff u is convex. Definition: The certainty equivalent of a lottery p is the sure-thing amount which is indifferent to p: CE{p} = u 1 (V (p)). Theorem B: A DM is risk-averse iff for all p P, CE{p} E p {u}. Proofs are here.

Certainty Equivalents u(ex) Eu(x) x 1 CE Ex x 2

Measuring Risk Aversion Definition: The Arrow-Pratt coefficient of absolute risk aversion at x is r A (x) = u (x)/u (x). The coefficient of relative risk aversion is r R (x) = xr A (x). CARA utility: u(x) = exp{ αx}. 1 γ CRRA utility: u(x) = x γ, γ 1, γ 0 log x. When utility is CARA and P is the set of normal distributions, CE(F ) = µ 1 2 ασ2.

Comparing Attitudes to Risk Theorem C: The following are equivalent for two utility functions u 1 and u 2 when p P: 1. u 1 = g u 2 for some concave g; 2. CE 1 (p) CE 2 (p) for all p P; 3. r A,1 (x) r A,2 (x) for all x R. How should risk aversion vary with wealth? r A (x w) = u (x + w)/u (x + w). How would you expect this to behave as a function of w? Click for the Proof of Theorem C.

Applications A risk-averse DM has wealth w > 1 and may lose 1 with probability p. He can buy any amount of insurance he wants sat q per unit. His expected utility from buying d dollars of insurance is EU(d) = (1 p)u(w qd) + pu ( w qd (1 d) ). Under what conditions will he insure, and for how much of the loss? Definition: Insurance is actuarially fair, sub-fair, or super-fair if the expected net payout per unit, p q, is = 0, < 0, or > 0, respectively. Definition: Full insurance is d = 1.

Sub-Fair Insurance Use derivatives to locate the optimal amount of insurance. EU (d) = (1 p)u (w qd)q + pu ( w qd (1 d) ) (1 q). Suppose q > p. EU (1) = u (w q) ( (1 p)q + p(1 q) ) = u (w q)(p q) < 0 EU (0) = (1 p)u (w)q + pu (w 1)(1 q) = pu (w 1) ( (1 p)u (w) + pu (w 1) ) q > p = p(1 p) ( u (w 1) u (w) ) > 0. Why is u (w 1) u (w) > 0?

Fair Insurance Suppose q = p. EU (1) = u (w q)(p q) = u (w q)(p p)0. Full insurance is optimal.

Optimal Portfolio Choice A risk-averse DM has initial wealth w. There is a risky asset that pays off z for each dollar invested. z is drawn from a distribution with a probability function p. If he invests in α units of the asset, he gets U(α) = E p u ( w + α(z 1) ) Which is concave in α. The optimal investment α solves U (α ) = E p u ( w + α(z 1) ) (z 1) = 0.

Optimal Portfolio Choice He will invest nothing if E p {z} 1. U (0) = E p u (w)(z 1) = u (w) ( E p {z} 1 ) 0. If E p {z} > 1, then U (0) = E p u (w)(z 1) = u (w) ( E p {z} 1 ) > 0. and so he will hold some positive amount of the asset.

Optimal Portfolio Choice Theorem: More risk individuals hold less of the risky asset, other things being equal. Proof: Suppose DM 1 has concave utility u 1, and individual 2 is more risk-averse. Then u 2 = g u 1. There is no loss of generality in assuming g (u 1 ) = 1 at u 1 = u 1 (w). For every α, U 2(α) U 1(α) = E p ( g (u 1 ) 1 ) u 1( w + α(z 1) ) (z 1) Now z < 1 iff w + α(z 1) < w iff u 1 (w + α(z 1) < u 1 (w) iff g ( u 1 (w + α(z 1) ) > g ( u 1 (w), so the expression inside the integral is always negative, and so U 2 (α) < U 1 (α) for all α. In particular, when α is optimal for DM 1, U 2 (α) < 0, so the optimal α for DM 2 is less.

Comparative Statics Utility over portfolios depends upon the DM s initial wealth. U(α; w) = E p u ( w + α(z 1) ) The DM s preferences have decreasing absolute risk aversion if whenever w > w, U( ; w ) is less risk-averse then U( ; w). Theorem: If the DM has decreasing absolute risk aversion, then α increasing in w.

Risk Aversion PROOFS

Concavity and Risk Aversion Definition: A set C R k is convex if it contains the line segment connecting any two of its members. function: If x, y C and 0 α 1, αx + (1 α)y C. Definition: A function f : R k R is concave iff {(x, y) R k+1 : y f (x)} is convex. Jensen s Inequality: A function f : R k R is concave if and only if for every N-tuple of numbers λ 1,..., λ N that are non-negative numbers and sum to 1, and corresponding x 1,..., x N are vectors in R k, ( N N ) λ n f (x n ) f λ n x n. n=1 Proof: The definition of concavity is Jensen s inequality for N = 2. The result for arbitrary N follows from induction. n=1

Concavity and Risk Aversion Proof of Theorem A: For concave functions this is Jensen s inequality. A function f is convex iff f is concave. Suppose u is convex. From Jensen s inequality, u is convex iff ( λ n u(xn ) ) ( ) u λ n x n n n iff ( λ n u(xn ) ) ( ) u λ n x n, n n iff the DM is risk-loving.

Concavity and Risk Aversion Proof of Theorem B: From Theorem A, if the DM is risk-averse, then E p u(x) u(e p x). By definition, u(ce p ) = E p u(x) u(e p x), and since u is increasing, CE(p) E p x. Back

Comparing Attitudes to Risk 1 iff 2: u 2 = g u 1 if and only if for all p, E p u 2 = E p g u 1 g (Eu 1 ). Then u 2 ( CE2 (p) ) = E p u 2 = E p g u 1 g ( E p u 1 ) = g u1 ( CE1 (p) ) = u 2 ( CE1 (p) ). Since u 2 is increasing, CE 2 (p) CE 1 (p). 1 iff 3: Since u 1 and u 2 are increasing functions, there is an increasing function g such that u 2 = g u 1. The chain rule implies that r 2 = r 1 g /g, so g = (r 1 r 2 )g. Since g > 0, g 0 iff r 2 r 1. Back