Notes for Thomas Kuhn's The Structure of Scientific Revolutions Bryan W. Van Norden (version of February 25, 2015)

Similar documents
Was Ptolemy Pstupid?

Evidence that the Earth does not move: Greek Astronomy. Aristotelian Cosmology: Motions of the Planets. Ptolemy s Geocentric Model 2-1

Astronomy Notes Chapter 02.notebook April 11, 2014 Pythagoras Aristotle geocentric retrograde motion epicycles deferents Aristarchus, heliocentric

Today. Review. Momentum and Force Consider the rate of change of momentum. What is Momentum?

Announcements. Topics To Be Covered in this Lecture

Chapter 2. The Rise of Astronomy. Copyright (c) The McGraw-Hill Companies, Inc. Permission required for reproduction or display.

Ancient Cosmology: A Flat Earth. Alexandria

ASTR 1010 Spring 2016 Study Notes Dr. Magnani

Things to do today. Terminal, Astronomy is Fun. Lecture 24 The Science of Astronomy. Scientific Thinking. After this lecture, please pick up:

Planets & The Origin of Science

History of Astronomy - Part I. Ancient Astronomy. Ancient Greece. Astronomy is a science that has truly taken shape only in the last couple centuries

,.~ Readlng ~ What,~,~~ is a geocentric system? Chapter3 J 73

The History of Astronomy

The Scientific Revolution

How Astronomers Learnt that The Heavens Are Not Perfect

Chapter 2 The Science of Life in the Universe

BROCK UNIVERSITY. 1. The observation that the intervals of time between two successive quarter phases of the Moon are very nearly equal implies that

Early Models of the Universe. How we explained those big shiny lights in the sky

Claudius Ptolemaeus Second Century AD. Jan 5 7:37 AM

cosmogony geocentric heliocentric How the Greeks modeled the heavens

Chapter 4. The Origin Of Modern Astronomy. Is okay to change your phone? From ios to Android From Android to ios

What is a Revolution? A Revolution is a complete change, or an overthrow of a government, a social system, etc.

Motions of the Planets ASTR 2110 Sarazin

BROCK UNIVERSITY. 1. The observation that the intervals of time between two successive quarter phases of the Moon are very nearly equal implies that

Models of the Solar System, Gravitation and the motion of the Planets A.K.A DEAD WHITE GUYS WEEK! 1/28/14

Astronomy 100 Section 2 MWF Greg Hall. Outline. Total Lunar Eclipse Time Lapse. Homework #1 is due Friday, 11:50 a.m.!!!!!

Learning Objectives. one night? Over the course of several nights? How do true motion and retrograde motion differ?

Most of the time during full and new phases, the Moon lies above or below the Sun in the sky.

Directions: Read each slide

The Puzzle of Planetary Motion versus

Chapter 2 The Copernican Revolution

Lecture #5: Plan. The Beginnings of Modern Astronomy Kepler s Laws Galileo

Gravitation Part I. Ptolemy, Copernicus, Galileo, and Kepler

N = R * f p n e f l f i f c L

Astronomy- The Original Science

Observing the Solar System 20-1

The Birth of Astronomy. Lecture 3 1/24/2018

N = R * f p n e f l f i f c L

The following notes roughly correspond to Section 2.4 and Chapter 3 of the text by Bennett. This note focuses on the details of the transition for a

2X CLAUDIUS PTOLEMY BIOGRAPHY 1260L

January 19, notes.notebook. Claudius Ptolemaeus Second Century AD. Jan 5 7:37 AM

Test Bank for Life in the Universe, Third Edition Chapter 2: The Science of Life in the Universe

History of Astronomy. Historical People and Theories

2X CLAUDIUS PTOLEMY BIOGRAPHY 780L

The History of Astronomy. Theories, People, and Discoveries of the Past

Introduction To Modern Astronomy I

Planets & The Origin of Science

9/12/2010. The Four Fundamental Forces of Nature. 1. Gravity 2. Electromagnetism 3. The Strong Nuclear Force 4. The Weak Nuclear Force


History of Astronomy. PHYS 1411 Introduction to Astronomy. Tycho Brahe and Exploding Stars. Tycho Brahe ( ) Chapter 4. Renaissance Period

Earth Science, 13e Tarbuck & Lutgens

The Copernican System: A Detailed Synopsis

18. Kepler as a young man became the assistant to A) Nicolaus Copernicus. B) Ptolemy. C) Tycho Brahe. D) Sir Isaac Newton.

Today. Planetary Motion. Tycho Brahe s Observations. Kepler s Laws Laws of Motion. Laws of Motion

A100 Exploring the Universe: The Rise of Science. Martin D. Weinberg UMass Astronomy

A100 Exploring the Universe: The Invention of Science. Martin D. Weinberg UMass Astronomy

Teaching the Geocentric Model Dr. David H Bradstreet Distributed by Spitz, Inc

Space Notes Covers Objectives 1 & 2

Early Theories. Early astronomers believed that the sun, planets and stars orbited Earth (geocentric model) Developed by Aristotle

In so many and such important. ways, then, do the planets bear witness to the earth's mobility. Nicholas Copernicus

Review of previous concepts!! Earth s orbit: Year, seasons, observed constellations, Polaris (North star), day/night lengths, equinoxes

1. The Moon appears larger when it rises than when it is high in the sky because

Contents: -Information/Research Packet. - Jumbled Image packet. - Comic book cover page. -Comic book pages. -Example finished comic

Physics Unit 7: Circular Motion, Universal Gravitation, and Satellite Orbits. Planetary Motion

Monday, October 3, 2011

Gravitation and the Motion of the Planets

Chapter 02 The Rise of Astronomy

Gravity. Newton s Law of Gravitation Kepler s Laws of Planetary Motion Gravitational Fields

The Copernican Revolution

Practice Test DeAnza College Astronomy 04 Test 1 Spring Quarter 2009

Humanities 3 V. The Scientific Revolution

SCIENTIFIC REVOLUTION

Document Analysis Worksheet: Galileo & the Moons of Jupiter

ASTRONOMY COPYRIGHTED MATERIAL

Big Bang, Black Holes, No Math

Lecture #4: Plan. Early Ideas of the Heavens (cont d): Geocentric Universe Heliocentric Universe

The Scientific Revolution & The Age of Enlightenment. Unit 8

2.4 The Birth of Modern Astronomy

Origins of Modern Astronomy

The Scientific Revolution

Gravitation and the Waltz of the Planets

Gravitation and the Waltz of the Planets. Chapter Four

How the Greeks Used Geometry to Understand the Stars

Science. Is this course science? A. Yes B. No

Earth Science, 11e. Origin of Modern Astronomy Chapter 21. Early history of astronomy. Early history of astronomy. Early history of astronomy

Astronomy. (rěv ə-lōō shən)) The Copernican Revolution. Phys There are problems with the Ptolemaic Model. Problems with Ptolemy

Tycho Brahe and Johannes Kepler

Introduction To Modern Astronomy II

Copernican Revolution. Motions of the sky. Motions of the sky. Copernican Revolution: questions on reading assignment

Philosophical Issues of Computer Science Historical and philosophical analysis of science

The History of Astronomy

Astronomy 1 Fall 2016

What was once so mysterious about planetary motion in our sky? We see apparent retrograde motion when we pass by a planet

The History of Astronomy. Please pick up your assigned transmitter.

Today. Planetary Motion. Tycho Brahe s Observations. Kepler s Laws of Planetary Motion. Laws of Motion. in physics

Revolution and Enlightenment. The scientific revolution

PHY1033C/HIS3931/IDH 3931 : Discovering Physics: The Universe and Humanity s Place in It Fall Prof. Peter Hirschfeld, Physics

25. What is the name for a theory that describes the overall structure of the universe? A) field theory B) astrology C) cosmology D) astronomy.

Competing Models. The Ptolemaic system (Geocentric) The Copernican system (Heliocentric)

Chapter 1 The Copernican Revolution

Transcription:

Notes for Thomas Kuhn's The Structure of Scientific Revolutions Bryan W. Van Norden (version of February 25, 2015) Here are some hints and suggestions for better understanding chapters VI, VII and X of Thomas Kuhn's The Structure of Scientific Revolutions. Chapter VI Summary: "Anomalies" disrupt "normal science" and therefore lead (sometimes) to the rejection of the dominant "paradigm" in favor a new one. When we examine this process historically, we see that there is no way to sharply distinguish between observable facts and the theory that interprets them. Both "normal science" and "paradigms" have been discussed in previous chapters. (Kuhn is, in fact, responsible for making the word "paradigm" such a common term in contemporary English.) But Kuhn actually gives his clearest exposition of what he means by a scientific paradigm in the Postscript to the book, p. 175. There, he says that he uses "paradigm" primarily to mean two things: (1) the complete WORLDVIEW of a particular community, and (2) an AUTHORITATIVE EXAMPLE of how to do science. "Normal science" is science conducted by a community which has an accepted paradigm (in both senses). So normal science is science conducted when scientists agree, in broad outlines, about the way the world is and agree about what good examples of proper scientific research are. Normal science is contrasted with science during periods of scientific revolution, when there is disagreement about both the way the world is and what successful examples of research are. For example, we are currently in a period of "normal science" in astronomy, but the period of Galileo's life was a period of revolution, when the Aristotelian-Ptolemaic paradigm was collapsing, and the Copernican-Galilean paradigm was gaining adherents. "Anomalies" are things that, at the least, are not explained by the contemporary paradigm, and may even seem to be inconsistent with the contemporary paradigm. To illustrate "anomalies" that may lead to disruptions in "normal science," Kuhn gives three examples: the "discovery" of oxygen, X-rays and the Leyden jar. I assume you all know that the current theory of combustion (burning) is that it is oxygen bonding with carbon and releasing energy. Kuhn refers to "phlogiston" in connection with the discovery of oxygen. At one time, scientists believed that combustion was a process by which the substance phlogiston was released by burning objects. The ashes left after combustion were the pure, or "dephlogisticated" matter. A Leyden jar is a glass jar with a narrow neck, the inside and outside of which have been lined with conducting metal foil. An insulated stopper is put in the opening, with a conducting rod inserted through it that reaches down to the conducting foil inside the jar. If you expose the conducting rod to a charge, the Leyden jar will store the charge, so

long as the inner and outer foil (separated by the glass of the jar) are not connected by a conducting material (like metal or a human body). Scientists were led to construct Leyden jars because of the belief that electricity is some sort of fluid. (They reasoned: if electricity is a fluid, maybe we can store it in a glass jar.) Early Leyden jars had water inside them, in the hope that the electric fluid would collect in the water, but it was soon discovered that the water was unnecessary. Current scientists would say that a Leyden jar is a crude "capacitor" or "condenser," which is formed whenever two conducting materials are separated by a nonconducting material. Figure 1: Leyden Jar Cross-Section

Figure 2: Leyden Jar being Charged by Generator There is a very natural, but very mistaken, way to understand the point that Kuhn is making in this chapter. Prior to Kuhn, many people would say that anomalies are essentially observations that violate the dominant scientific theory. The proper scientific response to anomalies is to develop a new theory that explains all the old observations, along with the new observations. This new theory is superior because it keeps all the same observations and theoretical truths of the old theory, plus handles some additional observations. (On this old view, science is like building a pyramid: the original "building blocks" [observations] are kept, but new ones are added.) But Kuhn is arguing AGAINST this way of understanding science! The most important sentence in this chapter is the following: "That distinction between discovery and invention or between fact and theory will, however, immediately prove to be exceedingly artificial" (52). In order to understand this chapter, you must understand WHY Kuhn rejects the "pyramid building" model of science. Chapter VII Summary: When a paradigm encounters anomalies, it can ALWAYS be modified to account for them. However, the repeated failure of a paradigm to account for a large number of anomalies leads to a crisis, which is only resolved when a new paradigm is adopted. Kuhn discusses three examples of major theoretical upheavals to demonstrate his point: the crisis of Ptolemaic-Aristotelian astronomy (also called the "Geocentric," meaning earth-centered, view), which was replaced by Copernican-Galilean astronomy (also called the "heliocentric," or sun-centered, view), the phlogiston theory of heat, which was replaced by the oxidation theory, and the replacement of the "luminous ether" theory of light (which fit in with the Newtonian paradigm) with the Einsteinian theory. Aristotle presented a plausible paradigm, in which the earth was the center of the universe, and the Moon, Sun, planets and "fixed stars" revolve around it. Ptolemy (the

initial "p" is silent) was a later astronomy who gave a precise mathematical formulation to Aristotle's view, which allowed people to predict astronomical events with a high degree of accuracy. Copernicus revived the view of the ancient Greek Aristarchus, that the Sun was the center of the universe. Copernicus presented a mathematical model for predicting astronomical events using this model. Later, Galileo presented arguments for why it was physically plausible that the earth both rotated on its axis and revolved around the Sun. (See below, Notes on the Geocentric and Heliocentric Worldviews. ) As Kuhn observes, the difficulty of the Ptolemaic view in dealing with an increasing number of anomalous observations led to its downfall. New observations were accommodated by modifications of the Ptolemaic view such as adding epicycles upon epicycles. (See the link above on the Copernican-Galilean universe.) These changes made the Ptolemaic theory more and more complicated, to the point that it began to seem increasingly implausible. (Why would God have designed the universe in such a complicated, inelegant way?) This was clearly a key problem. However, there is a common, but mistaken, view of why the Copernican-Galilean view replaced it. The mistaken view is that the Copernican-Galilean view was simpler and did a better job of predicting astronomical events than did the Aristotelian-Ptolemaic view. However, one of Kuhn's achievements was to demonstrate (in his book The Copernican Revolution) that the Copernican-Galilean view was neither mathematically simpler nor better at prediction than the Aristotelian-Ptolemaic system! So why did people switch to it? "Ptolemaic astronomy had failed to solve its problems; the time had come to give a competitor a chance" (Kuhn, Structure, 76). (The preceding is an important sentence and should be read carefully! If you find that sentence unsurprising, you probably do not understand it.) In other words, it was not that the Copernican system already was an elegant and accurate model of the universe. It was just that the Ptolemaic system was becoming more complex with every new observation, and did not show signs of getting any better. So the decision to opt for the Copernican system may have been rational, but it cannot be explained using the "pyramid model" (see notes on Chapter VI). Chapter X Summary: Scientists observe different things when guided by different paradigms, and so competing scientific paradigms are "incommensurable." Kuhn discusses the term "incommensurability" in more detail in chapter XII (especially pp. 148-150) and the Postscript (especially pp. 198-204). Primarily, to say that two paradigms are incommensurable is to say that there is no way to prove definitively that one paradigm is superior, because the two paradigms result in different observations (i.e., advocates of the different paradigms see different things) and they disagree over what the criteria for evaluating paradigms are. Kuhn is criticizing a view that is extremely common (even today): "Many readers will surely want to say that what changes with a paradigm is only the scientist's interpretation of observations that themselves are fixed once and for all by the nature of the

environment and of the perceptual apparatus" (120). In other words, science is a process of getting more accurate and more comprehensive explanations of observations, where observations are theory-independent, objective, and "given." If this were true, it would give an objective basis for choosing between paradigms. But Kuhn presents a variety of arguments for why this cannot be the case. To illustrate the alternative view that he favors, Kuhn makes reference to two famous visual examples from "gestalt" psychology. One is the "duck-rabbit," made famous by philosopher Ludwig Wittgenstein in his Philosophical Investigations: Figure 3: The Duck-Rabbit Drawing Notice that you can look at this drawing as either a duck or a rabbit. Kuhn uses a different example to make a similar point when he states that the person who first saw the exterior of the box from above later sees its interior from below (111). Here he has in mind the famous Necker Cube : Figure 4: The Necker Cube

(Try for yourself to switch back and forth between the two perspectives that Kuhn describes.) Now, the Gestalt school of psychology used similar examples to show that we see things as a whole. They were famous for the phrase that "the whole is more than the sum of its parts," which they took to be true both of human psychological faculties, and about how we perceive things: we do not merely see a set of lines, we see them as a duck (or as a rabbit). As Kuhn notes later in the chapter, this suggests that "two men with the same retinal impressions can see different things" (127). Kuhn applies this to science with the case of Herschel and the discovery of Uranus. One of the reasons this is so important is that Uranus was the first new planet discovered. The other six planets are the earth plus the five planets that are visible to the naked eye (i.e., without a telescope), which were known to many (perhaps all) pre-modern civilizations: Mercury, Venus, Mars, Jupiter, and Neptune. Many astronomers saw a celestial object in the sky where we now believe Uranus to be. However, they did not see it as a planet. Even Herschel saw it as a comet before he became convinced that it was a new planet. Soon after this discovery, astronomers (using equipment that had been available before) suddenly started seeing asteroids! Kuhn is suggesting that the recognition that there was at least one more planet than we realized enabled astronomers to see the same sky in a different way. Kuhn uses Galileo's theories on the motion of pendulums as an illustration at several points. A typical pendulum is a mass (called a bob ) hanging from a string. Galileo said that the "period" of a pendulum (how long it takes the bob to go from one end of its arc to the other) depends on the length of the pendulum, but is totally independent of the "amplitude" of the pendulum (the angle it starts its arc at). Figure 5: Pendulum It turns out that Galileo s claim is basically true where the initial amplitude is less than 20 degrees, but become only an approximation as the amplitude becomes greater than 20 degrees. (Cf. Kuhn, p. 124.) However, Galileo did not see this. A further illustration of

Kuhn's point is the famous story of how Galileo dropped two canon balls from the leaning Tower of Pisa. This experiment is supposed to demonstrate that, contrary to what Aristotle said, the rate of fall of objects is independent of their weight. (Heavy and light objects accelerate at the same speed, 32 feet per second, unless air resistance affects one more than another.) However, it is possible that Galileo never performed this experiment, and that the story is a myth. Galileo just theorized that it was true and left it at that. Kuhn also wants to make the point that Galileo was influenced by a variety of schools of thought (including a revival of Platonic thought and the medieval "impetus theorists") so that he had a slightly different paradigm from Aristotle. This allowed him to see pendular motion differently from the way an Aristotelian did: "To the Aristotelians, who believed that a heavy body is moved by its own nature from a higher position to a state of natural rest at a lower one, the swinging body was simply falling with difficulty.... Galileo, on the other hand, looking at the swinging body, saw a pendulum, a body that almost succeeded in repeating the same motion over and over again ad infinitum" (118-119). (Actually, as Kuhn knows, it was only with Galileo that the motion of pendulums became a paradigmatic kind of motion in modern physics. For Aristotelians, there's nothing even particularly interesting about pendulums. Aristotle probably never even mentions pendulums. This, in itself, shows the importance of paradigms.) So it seems that, in a fairly immediate and intuitive sense, people see different things under the influence of different paradigms. However, some philosophers have tried to argue that there is a more fundamental level of experience that is fixed and objective. The philosophical doctrine that all real knowledge is grounded in sensory experience is called "empiricism." Scottish philosopher David Hume (who published A Treatise of Human Nature in 1739-1740) is one of the great classical empiricist thinkers. In the early twentieth century, the empiricist tradition was carried on by the "Logical Positivists." The Logical Positivists attempted to reduce all of science to a combination of statements that were pure reports of sensory experience (like "red, here, now") plus some purely formal manipulations of these sentences by logic and mathematics. Although the Logical Empiricist program led to some very interesting philosophical results, it was ultimately a failure. It turns out that some of the greatest minds of the 20th century were unable to explain how to reduce even basic science to pure sensory reports. This is what Kuhn means when he says that "No current attempt to achieve that end [i.e., a pure observation-language] has yet come close to a generally applicable language of pure percepts" (127). Notes on the Geocentric and the Heliocentric Worldviews Figure 4, below, is an image of the universe as conceived of by Aristotle and Ptolemy. The earth is composed of four elements: Earth, Water, Fire and Air. It is in the center (notice the trees, mountains and water). In this cosmology, the earth does not revolve around anything else or rotate around its own axis. It is surrounded by ten concentric spheres made of a perfectly transparent substance known as "quintessence." These spheres revolve around the earth, carrying the other celestial bodies. As you can see, one is the sphere "of the Moon" ("Lunae"), two is Mercury

("Mercurii"), three is Venus ("Veneris"), four is the Sun ("Solis"), five is Mars ("Martis"), six is Jupiter ("Iovis"), seven is Saturn ("Saturni"), and spheres eight, nine and ten hold the "fixed stars" (so-called because they do not move relative to each other, unlike the planets, which move among the other stars). (The symbols by the names of the planets are the traditional astrological symbols for them. The symbols in spheres eight, nine and ten are for the twelve astrological constellations, Gemini, Ares, etc.) Beyond the tenth sphere is, as the words in the periphery say in Latin, "The Kingdom of Heaven, the Abode of God and of the Elect." (Contrast this with Figure 5, and see Figure 6, below.) Figure 6: The Geocentric Universe Figure 5, below, is an image of the universe as envisioned by Copernicus and Galileo. (The title says, in modern spelling, "A Perfect Description of the Celestial Orbs, according to the Most Ancient Doctrines of the Pythagoreans, and Others." This is because Aristarchus, the first to advance the heliocentric hypothesis, was a Pythagorean.) At the center of the universe is the Sun, surrounded by the globes of Mercury, Venus, "the great orb carrying this globe of mortality, its circular period determining our year" (and notice the orbit of the Moon around the Earth), then Mars, Jupiter, Saturn, and the fixed stars.

Figure 7: The Heliocentric Universe As Thomas Kuhn points out, especially in his book The Copernican Revolution, the Aristotelian-Ptolemaic system was remarkably plausible and powerful as a scientific theory. It intuitively explained our observations: the Earth does NOT seem to revolve or rotate, while the moon, the Sun, and the "fixed stars" seem to be revolving around us. With some minor adjustments, this theory could also account for the puzzling phenomenon of "retrograde motion." "Planets" means "wanderers." The planets are called this because they move independently of the fixed stars. In addition, the planets sometimes seem to reverse their motion. Ptolemy explained this with "epicycles." (See Figure 6 below, and the explanation beneath the image.)

Figure 8: Example of an Epicycle "E" is the Earth. "P" is a planet. The primary orbit of the planet is the circle centered on E. But there is a secondary circle, an epicycle, whose center (A) is on a point on the primary orbit. Imagine the primary circle moving counter-clockwise around E, and the secondary circle also moving counter-clockwise around the point A. From the perspective of the Earth, it will appear that P first moves counter-clockwise (as P moves on its epicycle toward the primary orbit). Then it will seem to slow down (as P comes closer and closer to the primary orbit). Finally, P will appear to reverse its motion (as it passes through the primary orbit). (Technically speaking, whether retrograde motion occurs depends on the relative speed of the orbit and the epicycle, but Ptolemy figured out what the speeds would have to be to account for the motions we do in fact observe.) This may seem implausibly complicated to you now. But if you tried to account for the actual motion of the planets according to Newtonian dynamics, you'd find it at least as complicated (just in a different way). Furthermore, both the Aristotelian-Ptolemaic view and the Copernican-Galilean view require epicycles. Furthermore, they require just as many epicycles. There is nothing mathematically simpler about the Copernican-Galilean view!