Some Function Problems SOLUTIONS Isabel Vogt Last Edited: May 24, 2013

Similar documents
We are going to discuss what it means for a sequence to converge in three stages: First, we define what it means for a sequence to converge to zero

Selected problems from past exams

MATH 220 (all sections) Homework #12 not to be turned in posted Friday, November 24, 2017

2 Metric Spaces Definitions Exotic Examples... 3

SETS AND FUNCTIONS JOSHUA BALLEW

d(x n, x) d(x n, x nk ) + d(x nk, x) where we chose any fixed k > N

Functions Functions and Modeling A UTeach/TNT Course

Topology. Xiaolong Han. Department of Mathematics, California State University, Northridge, CA 91330, USA address:

Real Analysis. Joe Patten August 12, 2018

Problem Set 2: Solutions Math 201A: Fall 2016

FUNCTIONAL ANALYSIS CHRISTIAN REMLING

Countability. 1 Motivation. 2 Counting

MATH 202B - Problem Set 5

Analysis Finite and Infinite Sets The Real Numbers The Cantor Set

Functions. Definition 1 Let A and B be sets. A relation between A and B is any subset of A B.

Economics 204 Fall 2011 Problem Set 2 Suggested Solutions

Mid Term-1 : Practice problems

Introduction to Topology

MATH 3300 Test 1. Name: Student Id:

Math 105A HW 1 Solutions

Solutions Final Exam May. 14, 2014

Part V. 17 Introduction: What are measures and why measurable sets. Lebesgue Integration Theory

REVIEW FOR THIRD 3200 MIDTERM

Functions and cardinality (solutions) sections A and F TA: Clive Newstead 6 th May 2014

INTRODUCTION TO TOPOLOGY, MATH 141, PRACTICE PROBLEMS

Chapter 2 Metric Spaces

Discrete Mathematics for CS Spring 2007 Luca Trevisan Lecture 27

MATH 23b, SPRING 2005 THEORETICAL LINEAR ALGEBRA AND MULTIVARIABLE CALCULUS Midterm (part 1) Solutions March 21, 2005

1.2 Functions What is a Function? 1.2. FUNCTIONS 11

Topology Math Conrad Plaut

g 2 (x) (1/3)M 1 = (1/3)(2/3)M.

AN EXPLORATION OF THE METRIZABILITY OF TOPOLOGICAL SPACES

Math 341 Summer 2016 Midterm Exam 2 Solutions. 1. Complete the definitions of the following words or phrases:

Quick Tour of the Topology of R. Steven Hurder, Dave Marker, & John Wood 1

Introductory Analysis 2 Spring 2010 Exam 1 February 11, 2015

MATH 13 SAMPLE FINAL EXAM SOLUTIONS

THE INVERSE FUNCTION THEOREM

1.4 Cardinality. Tom Lewis. Fall Term Tom Lewis () 1.4 Cardinality Fall Term / 9

Final Exam Review. 2. Let A = {, { }}. What is the cardinality of A? Is

MATH 13 FINAL EXAM SOLUTIONS

Solve EACH of the exercises 1-3

Metric Space Topology (Spring 2016) Selected Homework Solutions. HW1 Q1.2. Suppose that d is a metric on a set X. Prove that the inequality d(x, y)

6 CARDINALITY OF SETS

Real Analysis Math 131AH Rudin, Chapter #1. Dominique Abdi

REVIEW OF ESSENTIAL MATH 346 TOPICS

Definition 1.2. Let p R n be a point and v R n be a non-zero vector. The line through p in direction v is the set

Differential Topology Solution Set #2

Chapter Summary. Sets (2.1) Set Operations (2.2) Functions (2.3) Sequences and Summations (2.4) Cardinality of Sets (2.5) Matrices (2.

Connectedness. Proposition 2.2. The following are equivalent for a topological space (X, T ).

Math 117: Topology of the Real Numbers

Metric spaces and metrizability

Topology, Math 581, Fall 2017 last updated: November 24, Topology 1, Math 581, Fall 2017: Notes and homework Krzysztof Chris Ciesielski

Problem 1: Compactness (12 points, 2 points each)

Math 3T03 - Topology

Lecture Notes on Metric Spaces

RED. Fall 2016 Student Submitted Sample Questions

Sets and Functions. MATH 464/506, Real Analysis. J. Robert Buchanan. Summer Department of Mathematics. J. Robert Buchanan Sets and Functions

Notes on ordinals and cardinals

MATH NEW HOMEWORK AND SOLUTIONS TO PREVIOUS HOMEWORKS AND EXAMS

Iowa State University. Instructor: Alex Roitershtein Summer Exam #1. Solutions. x u = 2 x v

Introduction to Proofs in Analysis. updated December 5, By Edoh Y. Amiran Following the outline of notes by Donald Chalice INTRODUCTION

Math 291-2: Final Exam Solutions Northwestern University, Winter 2016

One-to-one functions and onto functions

MATH 201 Solutions: TEST 3-A (in class)

Logical Connectives and Quantifiers

447 HOMEWORK SET 1 IAN FRANCIS

CHAPTER 6. Limits of Functions. 1. Basic Definitions

Chapter 1 : The language of mathematics.

MA 1124 Solutions 14 th May 2012

Topology Final Exam. Instructor: W. D. Gillam Date: January 15, 2014

Measures. Chapter Some prerequisites. 1.2 Introduction

P-adic Functions - Part 1

Problems: Section 13-1, 3, 4, 5, 6; Section 16-1, 5, 8, 9;

Name (print): Question 4. exercise 1.24 (compute the union, then the intersection of two sets)

Part A. Metric and Topological Spaces

CARDINALITY OF THE SET OF REAL FUNCTIONS WITH A GIVEN CONTINUITY SET

Math General Topology Fall 2012 Homework 6 Solutions

Notes for Math 290 using Introduction to Mathematical Proofs by Charles E. Roberts, Jr.

Many of you got these steps reversed or otherwise out of order.

Def. A topological space X is disconnected if it admits a non-trivial splitting: (We ll abbreviate disjoint union of two subsets A and B meaning A B =

Math 140A - Fall Final Exam

1 Topology Definition of a topology Basis (Base) of a topology The subspace topology & the product topology on X Y 3

Differential Topology Final Exam With Solutions

Homework for MATH 4603 (Advanced Calculus I) Fall Homework 13: Due on Tuesday 15 December. Homework 12: Due on Tuesday 8 December

Course Summary Math 211

MATH FINAL EXAM REVIEW HINTS

Analysis Comprehensive Exam Questions Fall F(x) = 1 x. f(t)dt. t 1 2. tf 2 (t)dt. and g(t, x) = 2 t. 2 t

CHAPTER 5. The Topology of R. 1. Open and Closed Sets

Analysis III Theorems, Propositions & Lemmas... Oh My!

MATH PRACTICE EXAM 1 SOLUTIONS

In N we can do addition, but in order to do subtraction we need to extend N to the integers

UMASS AMHERST MATH 300 SP 05, F. HAJIR HOMEWORK 8: (EQUIVALENCE) RELATIONS AND PARTITIONS

van Rooij, Schikhof: A Second Course on Real Functions

10. Smooth Varieties. 82 Andreas Gathmann

Math General Topology Fall 2012 Homework 1 Solutions

Chapter 1. Sets and Mappings

Cartesian Products and Relations

Functional Analysis Exercise Class

In N we can do addition, but in order to do subtraction we need to extend N to the integers

Math 300: Final Exam Practice Solutions

Transcription:

Some Function Problems SOLUTIONS Isabel Vogt Last Edited: May 24, 23 Most of these problems were written for my students in Math 23a/b at Harvard in 2/22 and 22/23. They cover basic function theory, countability, differential calculus, and point-set topology.. T/F: The function q : R R given by is nowhere continuous. q(x) = { x : x Q : x / Q FALSE This interesting function is actually continuous at! Let s see why: In order for q to be continuous at, ɛ >, δ > s.t. y R, y < δ q(y) q() < ɛ Well, q() =, so we just need an appropriate δ such that for all y < δ, q(y) < ɛ. Claim: for all ɛ let δ = ɛ. Let s check the requirements. There are two possibilities, y Q 2 and y / Q For y / Q, q(y) = < ɛ For y Q, q(y) = y < ɛ 2 So q is continuous at! < ɛ 2. T/F: The space of results of infinite coin flips (i.e. vectors where the i th position is H/T depending on the result of the flip) is countably infinite. FALSE Imagine a new coin flip vector f whose i th position is H if the i th coin flip of the i th flip vector was T and conversely T if it was H. This differs in at least one position from every counted flip vector. Thus the set is not countable - i.e. it is uncountable infinite.

3. Let f be a function f : D C. (a) We can think of the function as merely a set of ordered pairs (x, y). What set must this be a subset of? A function is merely an ordered pair (x, f(x)) where x D and f(x) C. So S f (the function f as a set) is a subset of the Cartesian product D C. (b) Let D = C = Q. And let f be any function f : D C. Thinking of f as a set, what is its cardinality? Prove your answer. By definition of being a function, f is well-defined for all x D. So this means that x D, (x, f(x)) S f, and if x = x, then f(x) = f(x ) -uniqueness. Thus we can create a bijection between the set S f and D which is merely (x, f(x)) x. This is injective and surjective by the above conditions on f. Thus S f must be of the same cardinality as D - in this case countably infinite. (c) Let D = C = Q. What is the cardinality of the set of functions f : D C. Justify your answer (it might help to think of what we call a similar set). What we are concerned with is the set of all possible sets {S f } f for functions f : Q Q. First note that we can map to any subset of Q with our function f. Thus the set P(Q) injects/imbeds into our set {S f } f (note that this is not surjective because the image does not uniquely determine the map). And the cardinality of P(Q) is uncountably infinite (Cantor proved this for P(N) and the result follows for our case). Thus our set {S f } f is uncountable. (d) Let D be an uncountable set, C = {}. How many different well-defined functions f are there? What can you say about this/these function(s) (i.e. injectivity, surjectivity, bijectivity)? There are two (trivial) subsets of {} - namely {} and φ. Thus the only possibilities for functions are the zero map f : x Q and the trivial subset (D φ) which is the empty set. However, from the definition of a function, x D, f(x) C such that f : x f(x). This is not satisfies by {}. So the only map is the zero function f. The map f is obviously necessarily surjective but not injective. (e) Let D = φ and C be a countable set. How many different well-defined functions f are there? Justify your answer based upon the your answer to part (a). If such an f exists is it injective? Surjective? In this case ({}, Q) is a function (vacuously) as there does not exist counter-example points in {} which are not mapped to the codomain. The map φ is quite interesting in 2

how many properties are vacuously true! The definition of injective is f(x ) = f(x 2 ) x = x 2. In order for f to not be injective, there must exits f(x ) = f(x 2 ) with x x 2, but there doesn t exist f(x ) or f(x 2 ) as counterexamples! But for surjectivity, the definition says y Q, x {} such that f(x) = y. In this case we can not find x {} so this is false - it is not surjective. ( ) x 4. T/F: Given a continuous function f with f : R y 2 R, if the Jacobian matrix at a R 2 exists, then f is differentiable at a, and its derivative is given by [Jf(a)]. FALSE Take the function f(x, y) = x2 y, with f(, ) =. This function is continuous at the origin, x 2 +y 2 and both partials exist, but it is not differentiable there. 5. T/F: f is continuous at x if and only if ɛ >, δ > such that f(b δ (x )) B ɛ (f(x )). TRUE This is merely a restatement of the definition of continuity, i.e. f is continuous if and only if ɛ >, δ > such that x y < δ implies that f(x ) f(y ) < ɛ. The first condition is that y is in a δ-neighborhood of x (i.e. B δ (x )) and the second condition says that this ball is mapped to an ɛ-neighborhood of f(x ). 6. T/F: If f : R 2 R 2 is differentiable and [Df()] is not invertible, then there is no differentiable function g : R 2 R 2 such that TRUE By the chain rule we know that: So at v = we have (g f)( x) = x [D(g f( x)] h = [Dg(f( x))][df( x)] h [D(g f()] h = [Dg(f())][Df()] h In order for (g f)( x) = x, we would have [D(g f()] = I. Thus: [Dg(f())][Df()] = I But by definition this would mean that [Df()] is invertible as it is square and has a left inverse. This is a contradiction, thus no such g exists and the statement is true. 7. T/F: A set F is closed implies that all points in F are accumulation points. FALSE It is tempting to say this, since the definition we are going with for a closed set is one which contains all its accumulation points, but there is a big distinction here - that does not mean that all points are accumulation points. Take F = {}. This is clearly a closed set, but F contains no other points than, so it is not an accumulation point of the set. 3

8. T/F: For f and g differentiable functions from R 2 R FALSE f g x y = f g y x This is so terribly false, I just threw it on here to make sure no one thinks about partial derivatives as fractions. As a counter example take f(x, y) = x and g(x, y) = y. Then the left product is and the right is. 9. T/F: Every convergent subsequence of a sequence {a i } defined on a compact set C converges to the same limit a C. FALSE Consider the sequence x i = cos iπ for i N. This infinite sequence lives in the compact 2 interval [, ], and it thus has a convergent subsequence. There are, however, two possible sequences - all the even terms for which x 2k = + and all the odd terms for which x 2 2k+ =. 2 They, of course, do not converge to the same limit.. Suppose g : R 2 R 3 is a function such that the directional derivatives at x along v, v 2, and v 3 are e, e 2, and e 3 respectively. What can we say about g? Prove your claim. In R 2, three vectors can t be independent. Thus { v, v 2, v 3 } must be dependent. Without loss of generality let v 3 = a v + a 2 v 2. Then, [Dg(x )] v 3 = a [Dg(x )] v + a 2 [Dg(x )] v 2 But, e 3 a e + a 2 e 2, because they are independent. Thus the derivative can not be a linear function, and g is not differentiable at x!. (a) Define the zero-locus in R 2 of the polynomial f(x, y) = y x 2 to be the set of points G f = {x, y R f(x, y ) = }. Is the set G f open or closed as a subset of R 2? Similarly to a straight line, the curve is closed as its complement is open. Alternatively, it contains all of its accumulation points, as any accumulation point necessarily satisfies the above locus equation. (b) It is one thing to claim that ( ) there is an open set, and another thing to actually construct 3 one. Given a point a =, we wish to construct the largest ball B r (a) around this point such all points in this ball are in the complement of G f - ie B r (a) R 2 C. Find an equation that will determine the maximum r of this ball in two ways: 4

2. Let i. Finding an extreme value of the distance function between the point a and the parabola A general point on the parabola will be of the form (a, a 2 ). So the distance we are looking for is [ ] 3 a a 2 To make out lives easier, we know that the distance function will achieve a maximum or a minimum at the same value of a as its square (why?), so we can choose to optimize for the square: d(a) 2 = (3 a) 2 + ( a 2 ) 2 = a 4 a 2 6a + d(d(a)) = 4a 3 2a 6 da So we are looking for solutions to the equation 2a 3 a 3 = ii. Use the concept that the shortest line between a point and a line will be a perpendicular. We can use the derivative as a linear approximation to the function locally. Thus at any point (a,[ a 2 ),] the parabola looks like a linear function described by a vector in the direction. So we take the displacement vector between our point and 2a [ ] 3 a this arbitrary point on the parabola to be a 2. The shortest distance is going to be when these two are perpendicular, i.e. when the dot product is. In other words: [ ] [ ] 3 a 2a a 2 = 3 a + 2a 2a 3 = Or simply 2a 3 a 3 = - the same equation as defined above! f is defined to be at ( ). f ( ) x = x3 y 2 + x 4 y. y x 4 + y 4 (a) Using the definition of continuity, prove that f is continuous at ( ). 5

( ) (b) Show that both partial derivatives are zero at but that the function is not differentiable there. Note: You must work from the definition of differentiable. D f(, ) = lim (f( + h, ) f(, )) = lim h h h h = D 2 f(, ) = lim (f(, + h) f(, )) = lim h h h h = But for the directional derivative h = (h, h): [Df(, )] h = lim h h (h5 h ) = 4 As we know, +, so it is not linear and the derivative does not exist. 3. The topological definition of a continuous function is as follows: f : D R C R is continuous open sets A C, f (A) is open in D Using the standard metric topology of open sets with which you are familiar, show that this definition is equivalent to the ɛ-δ definition with which you are familiar (Hint: you may want to use the formulation given in a true/false question above). Why does this not contradict the counter-examples you found on HW 7 - i.e. the open sets that are not mapped to open sets? First we show that the standard definition implies the topological definition. So we assume that for a given continuous function f, for all x This is equivalent to saying that ɛ >, δ > such that x y < δ f(x) f(y) < ɛ ɛ >, δ >, f(b δ (x)) B ɛ (f(x)) Given any A open set in C, we want to show that f (A) D is open. Or more precisely, given any y A, as A is open, we know that B γ (y) A. So we want to show that f (B γ (y)) is open in D. It suffices for us to show that given any x f (B γ (y)) there exists a r such that B r (x) f (B γ (y)). 6

We simply find an ɛ > such that B ɛ (f(x)) B γ (y). This implies that there exists δ > such that f(b δ (x)) B ɛ (f(x)) B γ (y) B δ (x) f (B ɛ (f(x)) f (B γ (y)) let r = δ, B r (x) f (B γ (y) which completes the proof. Now we prove that the topological definition implies the standard definition. For a given x C, and ɛ >, we know an open set in C - namely B ɛ (f(x)). For f continuous, we know this means that f (B ɛ (f(x))) is open in D. Thus for x f (B ɛ (f(x))), r > such that B r (x) f (B ɛ (f(x))). Now we simply let δ = r, and derive which completes the proof. B δ (x) f (B ɛ (f(x))) f(b δ (x)) B ɛ (f(x)) 4. T/F: Let X and Y be sets with A, A 2 X. For all functions f : X Y as subsets of Y. And for B, B 2 Y, as subsets of X. FALSE f(a A 2 ) = f(a ) f(a 2 ) f (B B 2 ) = f (B ) f (B 2 ) The first of these statements is false, while the second is true (one of the reasons why inverses images are considerably nicer to work with). The true statement is f(a A 2 ) f(a ) f(a 2 ) When this fails to be equality, it will be because f isn t injective. A counter-example for the inclusion in both directions is the following function f : S S for S := {, 2, 3} defined by f() = 2, f(2 = 2), f(3) = 3. We can form 2 sets A = {, 3} and A 2 = {2, 3}. Then A A 2 = {3} and f(a A 2 ) = {3}. But f(a ) = {2, 3} and f(a 2 ) = {2, 3} so f(a ) f(a 2 ) = {2, 3}. Clearly these are not equal. x ( ) 5. T/F: Let h y x = 2 y y z 2. By the implicit function theorem, at the point we have z a continuously differentiable function i locally expressing x and z in terms of y to give the 7

locus of points whose image under h is ( ). FALSE The point is not in the zero-locus of h. 6. T/F: If a : N R is a sequence converging to, then for any b : N R, the sequence (a i b i ), for i N converges to FALSE This would be true if b i were bounded. Out-with-a-bang counter example: a i = i, b i = e i Subtle counter example: a i = i, b i = i 7. Give an example of a continuous function f : R R such that the restriction of the domain of f to Z R is a continuous map, or prove that one does not exist. EXAMPLE Perhaps continuous functions on Z make you uncomfortable (rightly so) but think about this, what you really need for continuity, is to be able to zoom in in the codomain. This is you ɛ > part. However, if this doesn t actually force you to squish in on values in the domain, no problem. As an example, take the zero map. 8. Give an example of a function g : R R that has a local inverse at every point, but for which no global inverse exists, or prove that one does not exist. NO EXAMPLE If there is a local inverse at every point then g is never zero, meaning g is monotonic. Thus there is a global inverse. 9. For F,..., F n... closed sets such that F i R 2, let F = i F i Give an example of a function f : F R which is differentiable, or prove that one does not exist. NO EXAMPLE No differentiable functions on closed sets, and the infinite intersection of closed sets is closed. 8

2. Give an example of a sequence of vectors v, v 2,... R n which is convergent but the length of each vector is not uniformly bounded by some M, or prove that one does not exist. NO EXAMPLE Every such sequence will be uniformly bounded. To be convergent to v we need which means that for any v n with n > N: ɛ >, N > s.t. n > N, v n v < ɛ v n = v n v + v v n v + v < ɛ + v And we only have finitely many vectors less than v N so we simply take the max: M = max{ v i } i<n And then M = max{ v, M } +. This must work as the length condition is for all epsilon. So surely > ɛ. 2. Give an example of a surjective map g : Q R which injects into its image, or prove that one does not exist. NO EXAMPLE Nope, that would mean g was bijective, but Q and R don t have the same cardinality. 22. The Inverse and Implicit Function Theorems (a) As I am sure you can imagine, the implicit function theorem has many important practical applications. Here is a somewhat whimsical one: The school district s curriculum committee has accurately calculated that if they provide x units of instruction in test-geared material and y units of instruction in academic exploration they achieve test scores S and student happiness H given by the function ( ) S H = f ( ) x y ( ) x = 3 + xy /2 y 2 4x /2 Currently the curriculum is dictating educational time such that x = 4, y =, S = 68, H = 7. Fearing trouble with reelection due to student unhappiness, the committee wants to moderately increase H to -2 and only decrease S to 63. Use the inverse function theorem to determine appropriate values of x and y that will approximate their desired output. How accurate is your answer? Why? The final answer is ( ) x = y ( ) 3.8 3.4 9

(b) Call X the space of linear transformationsa : R 2 R 2 with determinant +. Show that locally you can parameterize the passive variable(s) of X in terms of the active variable(s). X is the locus of the function F : R 4 R given by F : A det(a) The Jacobian is given by [DF (A)] = [ d c b a ] This is onto except for a = b c = d =, which is not even in X, so we are good! (c) Call Y the space of linear transformations B : R 3 R 3 such that B B T = I (B is known as a orthogonal matrix). How would you apply the implicit function theorem to locally parameterize Y? i. Using the following statement: All matrices A Y satisfy the equation AA T I =, thus I have a function F : R 9 R 9 given by F : A AA T I for which Y is the locus. Is the matrix [DF ] ever onto? As written, no, because Y is not 9-dimensional and thus can not span R 9. ii. How do you resolve this? Think about what you know about AA T. Because AA T is symmetric we only need to consider the upper triangle. Our space Y is the locus of the function G : R 9 R 6 given by this comparison. In this case, if you work out the Jacobian, you find that it is everywhere onto.