Proofs of Claims Leading to the Intermediate Value Theorem Stephen M. Walk, St. Cloud State University, 2011

Similar documents
1.10 Continuity Brian E. Veitch

1 Lecture 25: Extreme values

V. Graph Sketching and Max-Min Problems

Direct Proof MAT231. Fall Transition to Higher Mathematics. MAT231 (Transition to Higher Math) Direct Proof Fall / 24

Describing the Real Numbers

4.1 Real-valued functions of a real variable

Absolute and Local Extrema

x y More precisely, this equation means that given any ε > 0, there exists some δ > 0 such that

Intermediate Value Theorem

Calculus of One Real Variable Prof. Joydeep Dutta Department of Economic Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Kanpur

Continuity. Chapter 4

HOW TO WRITE PROOFS. Dr. Min Ru, University of Houston

PEANO AXIOMS FOR THE NATURAL NUMBERS AND PROOFS BY INDUCTION. The Peano axioms

(a) For an accumulation point a of S, the number l is the limit of f(x) as x approaches a, or lim x a f(x) = l, iff

Chapter One. The Real Number System

Supremum and Infimum

Economics 204 Summer/Fall 2011 Lecture 2 Tuesday July 26, 2011 N Now, on the main diagonal, change all the 0s to 1s and vice versa:

Section 4.2: The Mean Value Theorem

DR.RUPNATHJI( DR.RUPAK NATH )

Reductions in Computability Theory

Section 3.3 Maximum and Minimum Values

f(x) f(c) is the limit of numbers less than or equal to 0 and therefore can t be positive. It follows that

Consequences of Continuity and Differentiability

Answers for Calculus Review (Extrema and Concavity)

Econ Lecture 2. Outline

In N we can do addition, but in order to do subtraction we need to extend N to the integers

Study skills for mathematicians

Taylor Series: Notes for CSCI3656

Well-foundedness of Countable Ordinals and the Hydra Game

The Mean Value Inequality (without the Mean Value Theorem)

Functions. Chapter Continuous Functions

Properties of Arithmetic

Continuity and One-Sided Limits. By Tuesday J. Johnson

Section Summary. Definition of a Function.

Math 10850, Honors Calculus 1

Discrete Mathematics for CS Fall 2003 Wagner Lecture 3. Strong induction

WORKSHEET ON NUMBERS, MATH 215 FALL. We start our study of numbers with the integers: N = {1, 2, 3,...}

Structure of R. Chapter Algebraic and Order Properties of R

Continuity. Chapter 4

Economics 204 Summer/Fall 2017 Lecture 7 Tuesday July 25, 2017

MATH 131A: REAL ANALYSIS (BIG IDEAS)

MATH 409 Advanced Calculus I Lecture 10: Continuity. Properties of continuous functions.

2.3 Some Properties of Continuous Functions

1.3 Limits and Continuity

Connectedness. Proposition 2.2. The following are equivalent for a topological space (X, T ).

TAYLOR POLYNOMIALS DARYL DEFORD

Ask. Don t Tell. Annotated Examples

MT804 Analysis Homework II

Limits and Continuity

APPLICATIONS OF DIFFERENTIATION

Infinite Limits. Infinite Limits. Infinite Limits. Previously, we discussed the limits of rational functions with the indeterminate form 0/0.

Lecture 11: Extrema. Nathan Pflueger. 2 October 2013

Summary of Derivative Tests

On equivalent characterizations of convexity of functions

One-to-one functions and onto functions

Chapter 1 Review of Equations and Inequalities

The Intermediate Value Theorem If a function f (x) is continuous in the closed interval [ a,b] then [ ]

5.5 Deeper Properties of Continuous Functions

Quick Tour of the Topology of R. Steven Hurder, Dave Marker, & John Wood 1

Important Properties of R

Chapter Five Notes N P U2C5

Calculus I. When the following condition holds: if and only if

Lecture 3: Sizes of Infinity

M155 Exam 2 Concept Review

2. Two binary operations (addition, denoted + and multiplication, denoted

CH 59 SQUARE ROOTS. Every positive number has two square roots. Ch 59 Square Roots. Introduction

Bob Brown Math 251 Calculus 1 Chapter 4, Section 1 Completed 1 CCBC Dundalk

Lecture 4: Constructing the Integers, Rationals and Reals

We have been going places in the car of calculus for years, but this analysis course is about how the car actually works.

Undergraduate Notes in Mathematics. Arkansas Tech University Department of Mathematics

Handout 2 (Correction of Handout 1 plus continued discussion/hw) Comments and Homework in Chapter 1

Section 0.6: Factoring from Precalculus Prerequisites a.k.a. Chapter 0 by Carl Stitz, PhD, and Jeff Zeager, PhD, is available under a Creative

MATH 61-02: PRACTICE PROBLEMS FOR FINAL EXAM

Homework for Section 1.4, Continuity and One sided Limits. Study 1.4, # 1 21, 27, 31, 37 41, 45 53, 61, 69, 87, 91, 93. Class Notes: Prof. G.

Commutative Rings and Fields

14 Increasing and decreasing functions

Sign of derivative test: when does a function decreases or increases:

LECTURE 16: TENSOR PRODUCTS

Numerical Integration

MATH 13100/58 Class 6

Sets and Logic Linear Algebra, Spring 2012

Theorem. For every positive integer n, the sum of the positive integers from 1 to n is n(n+1)

Solution Set 2. Problem 1. [a] + [b] = [a + b] = [b + a] = [b] + [a] ([a] + [b]) + [c] = [a + b] + [c] = [a + b + c] = [a] + [b + c] = [a] + ([b + c])

MA131 - Analysis 1. Workbook 6 Completeness II

INTERMEDIATE VALUE THEOREM

Fixed Point Theorems

Math 151a week 1 discussion notes

6.2 Deeper Properties of Continuous Functions

The paradox of knowability, the knower, and the believer

Mathematics-I Prof. S.K. Ray Department of Mathematics and Statistics Indian Institute of Technology, Kanpur. Lecture 1 Real Numbers

I know this time s homework is hard... So I ll do as much detail as I can.

Math 111: Calculus. David Perkinson

Rolle s Theorem. The theorem states that if f (a) = f (b), then there is at least one number c between a and b at which f ' (c) = 0.

appstats27.notebook April 06, 2017

Math 112 Group Activity: The Vertical Speed of a Shell

And, even if it is square, we may not be able to use EROs to get to the identity matrix. Consider

In N we can do addition, but in order to do subtraction we need to extend N to the integers

3.5: Issues in Curve Sketching

Continuity. To handle complicated functions, particularly those for which we have a reasonable formula or formulas, we need a more precise definition.

MAT115A-21 COMPLETE LECTURE NOTES

Transcription:

Proofs of Claims Leading to the Intermediate Value Theorem Stephen M. Walk, St. Cloud State University, 2011 This supplement contains proofs of theorems stated in the article The Intermediate Value Theorem Is NOT Obvious and I Am Going to Prove It to You, College Mathematics Journal 42 (2011) 254 259, doi:10.4169/college.math.j.42.4.254. We use the sequence version of the completeness axiom and the definition of real number as stated in that paper, and we also invoke propositions proved early on in that paper. The proofs are presented here with an eye toward their use in a Calculus One classroom. We aim to introduce students to a mathematically correct idea of real number and also get them to practice thinking mathematically rather than simply adopting propositions because they feel right. On the other hand, while we do want to expose students to a mild level of rigor, we don t want to overwhelm them with it. We allow as given all of the usual facts about the natural numbers (including at least an intuitive understanding of the wellordering principle) and the rationals, saving the rigor for the truly new idea, that of real number. And to further avoid belaboring the point, we won t worry about details such as just when two rational sequences yield the same real number, or bother to verify basic properties of reals such as commutativity, associativity, and trichotomy. Those issues can still be examined outside of class time if there are questions from exceptionally curious students. 1

Proposition. Every sequence of REAL numbers that has a [REAL] ceiling must have a perfect ceiling. Proof: Each real number in the given sequence is, by definition, the perfect ceiling of a sequence of rational numbers. Let s call these short sequences: We dovetail these short sequences to create a new sequence of rationals, which we ll call the long sequence: The long sequence has a real ceiling and hence a rational ceiling (by the earlier proposition that for every positive real number, there is a rational number that 2

is bigger), so by the completeness axiom, the long sequence has a perfect ceiling s. Then (we claim) s turns out also to be the perfect ceiling for the original sequence of real numbers. It seems wisest to stop here in class. We re not truly done until we prove the claim just stated, of course; but by now, students have already seen the unfurling of the sequence of reals, the dovetailing of the resulting rational sequences, the application of the completeness axiom to find s, and the statement of the claim. The point is to have students think about why the proposition is correct not to mention reviewing the definition of real number and this has already been accomplished. It would overload most students to see the proof of the claim right away. This is not to say that we can t come back to it later or answer questions after class, of course, so here goes: The number s is a ceiling for the original sequence of reals. Because s is a ceiling for the long sequence, it is also a ceiling for each of the short sequences, and hence it is at least as great as the perfect ceiling of each of the short sequences. In other words, s is at least as great as each of the reals in the original sequence. The number s is the perfect ceiling for the original sequence of reals. Any number less than s must fail to be a ceiling for the long sequence of rationals, hence must be less than at least one number in the long sequence; thus it must be less than that same number in one of the short sequences and, therefore, cannot be a ceiling for that particular short sequence. And since such a number cannot be a ceiling for that short sequence, it must be less than the perfect ceiling for that short sequence that is, it must be less than the real number spawned by that short sequence of rationals. To sum up: Any number less than s must be less than some number in the original sequence of reals and, thus, must fail to be a ceiling for that original sequence. So s itself is the smallest ceiling, i.e. the perfect ceiling, for that original sequence. The capture theorem. If s is the perfect ceiling or the perfect floor of a sequence, then any open interval containing s also contains some element of the sequence. The flipping-huge theorem. If a sequence of positive real numbers has 0 as its perfect floor, then there is no ceiling for the reciprocals of the terms of the sequence; and conversely. 3

Proof: Because it was suggested in the article that these be assigned as homework, we ll refrain from posting the proofs on the Internet! Proposition. The doubling sequence 2, 4,,... has no ceiling. Proof: First, we note that the doubling sequence cannot have any naturalnumber ceiling. For suppose it did. (This is where we use the well-ordering principle, though we don t need to tell students that.) Let n be the smallest natural-number ceiling for the doubling sequence. (Clearly n > 2.) Then n 1 would not be a ceiling for the doubling sequence and, hence, would be less than some number 2 k from the sequence. Since n 1 < 2 k, it would follow that 2(n 1) < 2 k+1. But n < 2(n 1) since n > 2, so we would have n < 2 k+1, contradicting the choice of n. Next, we note that the doubling sequence cannot have any rational ceiling. For suppose it did have some rational ceiling m (where m and n were both n natural numbers); then ( m ) m = n m n n, so that m would be a natural-number ceiling for the sequence contradicting what we just proved. Finally, the doubling sequence cannot have any real ceiling at all. For suppose it did; then, by the earlier result that for every positive real number, there is a rational number that is bigger, the doubling sequence would have a rational ceiling, contradicting what we just proved. Corollary: To halve, and have naught. The perfect floor of the sequence 1 2, 1 4, 1,... is 0. In fact, if d is ANY positive real number, then the perfect floor of the sequence d 2, d 4, d,... is 0. Proof: For the first part of the corollary, because the sequence 2, 4,,... has no ceiling, the sequence of reciprocals 1 2, 1 4, 1,... has 0 for a perfect floor by the flipping-huge theorem. For the second part, if there were a positive perfect floor t for the sequence d 2, d 4, d,..., then the positive real number t d sequence 1 2, 1 4, 1,..., which would contradict the first part. would be a floor for the 4

The aura theorem. Suppose that f is continuous at s. If f(s) is positive, then there is an open interval containing s such that f is positive on the entire interval. If f(s) is negative, then there is an open interval containing s such that f is negative on the entire interval. Proof: Briefly, let ε be f(s) /2 and use continuity of f at s. More precisely, because f is continuous at s, there is a δ > 0 such that that is, for every x, if x s < δ, then f(x) f(s) < ε, for every x in (s δ, s + δ), we have f(s) f(s) 2 < f(x) < f(s) + f(s). 2 It is easy to verify (and makes a good exercise to review the definition of absolute value) that these bounds on f(x) both have the same sign as f(s); thus, so does f(x) for every x in (s δ, s + δ). The intermediate value theorem (clarified). The mathematical definition of continuity captures an important aspect of the informal concept of, to wit, if f is continuous on [a, b], and p is any number such that f(a) < p < f(b) or f(b) < p < f(a), then there is some c in the interval (a, b) such that f(c) = p. Proof: The underlying argument is as given in Simpson s reverse mathematics text [3, p. 7] and Mansfield s real analysis text [1, pp. 109 111] and presumably a dozen other sources. Though it is the kind of argument students rarely see outside a real analysis course, a dash of showmanship makes it appropriate for the calculus classroom especially if we add a splash of color: Class, I m thinking of a function f that is continuous on the closed interval [0, 1]. I won t show you the graph of the function, but I will tell you that it s positive at x = 0 and negative at x = 1. I ll represent this on the x-axis by coloring 0 cyan (for positive ) and 1 red (for negative ): Now, do you believe that the function f ever takes the value 0 on this interval?... You do? Then let s play a game. You, as a class, will guess an x where you think f(x) might be equal to 0. If you re right, you win. If you re wrong, I color that x cyan or red, and you guess again. And so on. 5

The good news is that you may have as many guesses as you want. The bad news is that I don t guarantee the function EVER takes the value 0, so you may be guessing forever. Have at it! Students hit upon the most natural approach almost immediately: Guess 1 2 first, then 1 4 or 3 4 depending on what color 1 2 was, and so on: Three things can happen: 1. There is a greatest cyan number, but there is no smallest red number. 2. There is a smallest red number, but there is no greatest cyan number. 3. There is neither a greatest cyan number nor a smallest red number. It is worthwhile to illustrate the cases and ask the students to compare, for each case, the perfect ceiling of the cyans and the perfect floor of the reds. They seem always to be the same. Can we prove such a claim? Proof of the claim. First, the perfect ceiling of the cyans (call it c ) cannot be greater than the perfect floor of the reds (call it r ). If it were, then we could look in the open interval (r, c) and find, in its right half, at least one cyan number (otherwise c would not be the perfect ceiling of the cyans) and, in its left half, at least one red number (otherwise r would not be the perfect floor of the reds). Then that particular cyan would be greater than that particular red, contrary to how we constructed the sequence. Next, we cannot have c < r either: because at every stage of the construction we distinguished a new interval with a cyan left endpoint and a red right endpoint, and the interval (c, r) would have to lie within all of those intervals and its 6

length, a positive number, would have to be less than the lengths of all of them. The lengths of those intervals are 1 2, 1 4, 1,..., and there is no positive number less than all of those; we have halved, and have naught. This is a contradiction. The only possibility left is that c and r are the same, and the claim is settled. The proof of the claim just given, with its emphasis on halving, is reminiscent of Bolzano s own treatment of the intermediate value theorem [2, Section 12]. All that remains is to show that f(c) = 0. If f(c) were positive, then c would have a positive aura that would nonetheless capture a red number a contradiction. And if f(c) were negative, then c would have a negative aura that would nonetheless capture a cyan number also a contradiction. So f(c) must indeed be 0. This takes care of a special case. For the general case, students need to make two observations. First, the endpoints of the interval do not matter, because the halve-and-have-naught corollary applies for any starting interval length d and because, by propositions already proved here and in the article, the sequence of cyans (resp. reds) must have a perfect ceiling (resp. floor) even if its terms are not rational. Second, the desired value p does not have to be 0 but can be any number between f(a) and f(b), because cyan and red can simply mean more than p and less than p, or vice versa. This proves the IVT. References 1. M. J. Mansfield, Introduction to Real Analysis, Prindle, Weber & Schmidt, Incorporated, Boston, 1969. 2. S. B. Russ, A translation of Bolzano s paper on the intermediate value theorem, Historia Mathematica, (2) 7 (May 190) 156 15. 3. S. G. Simpson, Subsystems of Second Order Arithmetic, Springer, Berlin, 1999. 7