Monotone equilibria in nonatomic supermodular games. A comment

Similar documents
A Qualitative Theory of Large Games with Strategic Complementarities

A qualitative theory of large games with strategic complementarities

6.254 : Game Theory with Engineering Applications Lecture 8: Supermodular and Potential Games

Tijmen Daniëls Universiteit van Amsterdam. Abstract

1.A Topological spaces The initial topology is called topology generated by (f i ) i I.

EXISTENCE OF PURE EQUILIBRIA IN GAMES WITH NONATOMIC SPACE OF PLAYERS. Agnieszka Wiszniewska Matyszkiel. 1. Introduction

A SHORT AND CONSTRUCTIVE PROOF OF TARSKI S FIXED-POINT THEOREM

6.254 : Game Theory with Engineering Applications Lecture 7: Supermodular Games

3 COUNTABILITY AND CONNECTEDNESS AXIOMS

Axioms of separation

B 1 = {B(x, r) x = (x 1, x 2 ) H, 0 < r < x 2 }. (a) Show that B = B 1 B 2 is a basis for a topology on X.

van Rooij, Schikhof: A Second Course on Real Functions

Differential information in large games with strategic complementarities

4 Countability axioms

Robust Comparative Statics in Large Static Games

Robust Comparative Statics for Non-monotone Shocks in Large Aggregative Games

A Characterization of Strategic Complementarities

g 2 (x) (1/3)M 1 = (1/3)(2/3)M.

REAL AND COMPLEX ANALYSIS

Supermodular Games. Ichiro Obara. February 6, 2012 UCLA. Obara (UCLA) Supermodular Games February 6, / 21

Volume 30, Issue 3. Monotone comparative statics with separable objective functions. Christian Ewerhart University of Zurich

A NEW CHARACTERIZATION OF COMPLETE HEYTING AND CO-HEYTING ALGEBRAS

Pseudo-Potential Games

Solutions to Tutorial 8 (Week 9)

Homework in Topology, Spring 2009.

1 Topology Definition of a topology Basis (Base) of a topology The subspace topology & the product topology on X Y 3

Robust comparative statics in large static games

Analysis III Theorems, Propositions & Lemmas... Oh My!

Topology. Xiaolong Han. Department of Mathematics, California State University, Northridge, CA 91330, USA address:

On the existence of monotone selections

Fragmentability and σ-fragmentability

WHY SATURATED PROBABILITY SPACES ARE NECESSARY

Chapter 2 Metric Spaces

On the existence of monotone selections

Aliprantis, Border: Infinite-dimensional Analysis A Hitchhiker s Guide

arxiv: v1 [math.gn] 27 Oct 2018

A SECOND COURSE IN GENERAL TOPOLOGY

Essential equilibria in normal-form games

Well-Ordered Sets, Ordinals and Cardinals Ali Nesin 1 July 2001

Theorems. Theorem 1.11: Greatest-Lower-Bound Property. Theorem 1.20: The Archimedean property of. Theorem 1.21: -th Root of Real Numbers

On minimal models of the Region Connection Calculus

Preference and Utility

1 Lattices and Tarski s Theorem

x 0 + f(x), exist as extended real numbers. Show that f is upper semicontinuous This shows ( ɛ, ɛ) B α. Thus

AN INTRODUCTION TO MATHEMATICAL ANALYSIS ECONOMIC THEORY AND ECONOMETRICS

Acta Mathematica Academiae Paedagogicae Nyíregyháziensis 21 (2005), ISSN

Mathematical Economics - PhD in Economics

Order on Types based on Monotone Comparative Statics

S. Mrówka introduced a topological space ψ whose underlying set is the. natural numbers together with an infinite maximal almost disjoint family(madf)

Chapter 1 : The language of mathematics.

Spring -07 TOPOLOGY III. Conventions

Equilibria in Games with Weak Payoff Externalities

Part V. 17 Introduction: What are measures and why measurable sets. Lebesgue Integration Theory

Abstract Measure Theory

7 Complete metric spaces and function spaces

MH 7500 THEOREMS. (iii) A = A; (iv) A B = A B. Theorem 5. If {A α : α Λ} is any collection of subsets of a space X, then

3 Hausdorff and Connected Spaces

Multimarket Oligopolies with Restricted Market Access

A Constructive Study of Markov Equilibria in Stochastic Games with Strategic Complementarities

Spring 2014 Advanced Probability Overview. Lecture Notes Set 1: Course Overview, σ-fields, and Measures

Measure and Category. Marianna Csörnyei. ucahmcs

Introduction to Topology

An introduction to OCA

Department of Economics Working Paper Series

Part II. Logic and Set Theory. Year

Markov Stationary Equilibria in Stochastic Supermodular Games with Imperfect Private and Public Information

INTRODUCTION TO TOPOLOGY, MATH 141, PRACTICE PROBLEMS

Existence of Equilibria in Games with Arbitrary Strategy Spaces and Preferences: A Full Characterization

Problems - Section 17-2, 4, 6c, 9, 10, 13, 14; Section 18-1, 3, 4, 6, 8, 10; Section 19-1, 3, 5, 7, 8, 9;

REVIEW OF ESSENTIAL MATH 346 TOPICS

ω-stable Theories: Introduction

Uniquely Universal Sets

THE CANTOR GAME: WINNING STRATEGIES AND DETERMINACY. by arxiv: v1 [math.ca] 29 Jan 2017 MAGNUS D. LADUE

NAME: Mathematics 205A, Fall 2008, Final Examination. Answer Key

4 Choice axioms and Baire category theorem

Introductory Analysis I Fall 2014 Homework #5 Solutions

5 Set Operations, Functions, and Counting

CHODOUNSKY, DAVID, M.A. Relative Topological Properties. (2006) Directed by Dr. Jerry Vaughan. 48pp.

AN EXPLORATION OF THE METRIZABILITY OF TOPOLOGICAL SPACES

Sets, Models and Proofs. I. Moerdijk and J. van Oosten Department of Mathematics Utrecht University

The Kolmogorov extension theorem

Whitney topology and spaces of preference relations. Abstract

E.7 Alaoglu s Theorem

Open Sequential Equilibria of Multi-Stage Games with Infinite Sets of Types and Actions

Reminder Notes for the Course on Measures on Topological Spaces

PROPER FORCING REMASTERED

Events Concerning Knowledge

Computing Equilibria by Incorporating Qualitative Models 1

Math 426 Homework 4 Due 3 November 2017

On Kusuoka Representation of Law Invariant Risk Measures

Topological properties

Homogeneous spaces and Wadge theory

Lattices, closure operators, and Galois connections.

CERTAIN WEAKLY GENERATED NONCOMPACT, PSEUDO-COMPACT TOPOLOGIES ON TYCHONOFF CUBES. Leonard R. Rubin University of Oklahoma, USA

Notes on Supermodularity and Increasing Differences. in Expected Utility

Part III. 10 Topological Space Basics. Topological Spaces

DEPARTMENT OF ECONOMICS DISCUSSION PAPER SERIES

MATHS 730 FC Lecture Notes March 5, Introduction

THEOREMS, ETC., FOR MATH 515

A BOREL SOLUTION TO THE HORN-TARSKI PROBLEM. MSC 2000: 03E05, 03E20, 06A10 Keywords: Chain Conditions, Boolean Algebras.

Transcription:

Monotone equilibria in nonatomic supermodular games. A comment Lukasz Balbus Kevin Reffett Lukasz Woźny April 2014 Abstract Recently Yang and Qi (2013) stated an interesting theorem on existence of complete lattice of equilibria in a particular class of large nonatomics supermodular games for general action and types spaces. Unfortunately, their result is incorrect. In this note, we detail the nature of the problem with the stated theorem, provide a counterexample, and then correct the result under additional assumptions. We also provide a number of new results per existence of equilibria in more general classes of games of strategic complementarities that are monotone in players types, as well as provide a class of constructive methods for computing monotone equilibrium comparative statics. keywords: large games, supermodular games, games with strategic complementarities, distributional equilibria, JEL codes: C72 1 Introduction We follow the notation in Yang and Qi (2013) in this note. A semi-anonymous game with an ordered set of player types is a tuple Γ = (T, p, S, f), where T is a partially ordered We thank Amanda Fridenberg and Ali Khan for very helpful discussions on various issues related to this paper. Lukasz Balbus and Lukasz Woźny also thanks the NCN grant No.UMO- 2012/07/D/HS4/01393 allowing to finance our visit at the Department of Economics, Arizona State University in February 2014. All the usual caveats apply. Faculty of Mathematics, Computer Sciences and Econometrics, University of Zielona Góra, Poland. Department of Economics, Arizona State University, USA. Department of Quantitative Economics, Warsaw School of Economics, Warsaw, Poland. Address: al. Niepodleg lości 162, 02-554 Warszawa, Poland. E-mail: lukasz.wozny@sgh.waw.pl. 1

set (a poset) of players types, p P(T ) a probability distribution on the measurable space (T, B(T )) where B(T ) is a Borel σ field generated by the interval topology, S is the action space of the players, f : S P(T S) T R is a payoff function where f(s, r, θ) denotes the payoff for player θ T, using action s S, while facing a joint type-action distribution given by r P(T S). Denote by M(T, S) the set of Borel measurable functions from T to S endowed with the pointwise order, i T the identity mapping. Then a Nash equilibrium of the game Γ is given by measure x M(T, S) that satisfies the following: θ T, s S we have f(x(θ), p (i T, x) 1, θ) f(s, p (i T, x) 1, θ), (1) where p (i T, x) 1 is a joint type-action distribution on T S implied by x. In Yang and Qi (2013), they assume that T is a complete chain 1 and S a complete lattice. Endow P(T S) with the first stochastic dominance order. The assumptions Yang and Qi (2013) impose are the following: Assumption 1 Assume: s f(s, r, θ) is order upper semi-continuous for each θ T and r P(T S), s f(s, r, θ) is supermodular for each θ T and r P(T S), f has increasing differences with s and (θ, r). The main existence result of Yang and Qi (2013) states that under assumption (1), the set of monotone Nash equilibria in M(T, S) of the game Γ is a nonempty complete lattice. This result in obtained essentially as an application of the fixed point results in Veinott (1992) or Zhou (1994) (which in turn are generalizations of Tarski (1955) fixed point theorem) for strong set order ascending best response correspondences that map the set I(T, S) M(T, S) to itself, where I(T, S) denote the set of monotone (measurable) mappings from T to S. To prove their main theorem, and apply these well-known tools, Yang and Qi (2013) claim the following key lemma is true: Lemma 1 Suppose T is a complete chain and S is a complete lattice, then I(T, S) M(T, S). 1 We say a poset X is a complete chain if X is a chain and for all C X we have C X and C X. 2

This lemma is critical for the existence result in Yang and Qi (2013), it claims that any monotone increasing function on the complete chain is measurable. In fact, if correct, them lemma implies that the set of monotone and measurable functions: I(T, S) M(T, S) is a complete lattice under pointwise partial orders. Therefore, if additionally the best response correspondence transforms the space I(T, S) M(T, S) into I(T, S), then it necessarily maps into I(T, S) M(T, S). Unfortunately, lemma 1 is not correct, and as a consequence, the main existence theorem in the paper is incorrect as well. Specifically, and related to this issues raised in a recent paper Balbus, Dziewulski, Reffett, and Woźny (2014), not only is the proof of the existence in this game via an simple application of Veinott (1992) or Zhou (1994) generally nappropriate; it is in fact wrong (as the best response correspondence could map outside the set of measurable functions). In the remainder of paper, we present a counterexample to lemma 1 in the next section of the paper in theorem 1. In the next section of the paper, we discuss sufficient conditions for existence of equilibrium in a version of the actual game considering in Yang and Qi (2013). In the final section of the paper, we consider the question of monotone equilibria in a more general class of large games with strategic complementarities. 2 A counterexample Consider some interval I of ordinal numbers 2, and let ω 1 by the least number of the set {x I : #([0, x]) ℵ 1 }. Clearly every initial segment of the subset [0, ω 1 ) is countable but Ω := [0, ω 1 ] has cardinality ℵ 1. Let T be a topology generated by open intervals. We claim that Lemma 2 σ({[0, x) (y, ω 1 ], x, y Ω}) σ(t ). Proof: Let A := {A Ω : (#A ℵ 0 ) (#A c ℵ 0 )}. That is A is a set of all countable or co-countable sets. Clearly it is a σ-field. Moreover each initial segment [0, x) is countable if x < ω 1, and [0, ω 1 ) is co-countable since its complement is {ω 1 }. Moreover, (x, ω 1 ] is co-countable since its complement is [0, x). As a result A = σ ( {A 2 Ω : (A = [0, x)) (A = (x, ω 1 ]) for some x Ω} ). 2 Our construction in this section is similar to that presented in Theorem 1.14 page 19 and Example 12.9 page 439 in Aliprantis and Border (2006). 3

We will construct an open set outside A. Observe that successors set S is equinumerous as Ω. Let φ : Ω Ω be defined as follows: φ(ω 1 ) = 0 and φ(x) = x + 1 for x < ω 1. Clearly φ is bijection between Ω and S {0}. As a result Ω is equinumerous as S, hence S is uncountable. But S T since S = (x 1, x + 1) T. Clearly by Theorem 1.14, x S page 19 in Aliprantis and Border (2006) L = S c is uncountable because is closed and contains {ω 1 }. Hence S / A. Definition 1 A set A Ω is big if A {ω 1 } includes an uncountable and T -closed set. A set is small if its complement is big. Lemma 3 There exists a no-borel set D. That is there exists D / σ(t ). Proof: Observe that σ(t ) is a collection of the sets including big and small sets only. To construct non-borel set, we know it needs to be neither big nor small. Let F be a collection of closed uncountable sets. Clearly for all F F, ω 1 F. Let F 0 = F. Obviously ω 1 F 0 and F 0 is closed. Applying Theorem 1.14 in Aliprantis F F and Border (2006) F 0 is uncountable. Let D be uncountable proper subset of F 0. We claim that D is neither big nor small. To show D is not big let us take any F D and F F. Then F must be countable. Hence D is not big. On a contrary suppose D is small. Then D c is big. Then F 0 D c. Since also D F 0, hence D D c. This contradiction proves D is not small. Consequently D is not Borel set. Theorem 1 There exists an increasing function f : Ω Ω that is unmeasurable in σ(t ). Proof: From Lemma 3 there is a set D Ω such that D is not σ(t ) measurable. Without loss of generality assume D does not contain ω 1. Define f(ω) = ω + 1 for ω [0, ω 1 ) and f(ω 1 ) = ω 1. Clearly f maps into S {ω 1 }. Clearly S is an open set and all subsets of S are open. Then D + 1 := {x + 1 : x D} S, hence it is open. Then f 1 (D + 1) = D. Hence f is no Borel. Theorem 1 shows that Lemma 1 in Yang and Qi (2013) is false. The point is the authors show measurability of all isotone function f : (X, ) (Y, ), but for Y equipped with σ field generated by intervals only. As we have shown in Lemma 2 the σ-field generated by open (or closed) intervals may be different from the σ-field generated by topology generated by open intervals. 4

3 Discussion and corrected result There are various ways the lemma 1 (and hence the existence result of Yang and Qi (2013)) can be corrected by adding the additional assumptions, and/or changing the definition of the game. We discuss a few of them at this stage. First, observe the counterexample is based on the uncountability of the complete chain Ω := [0, ω 1 ]. In fact, the statement of lemma 1 remains valid under the additional assumption for the type space T, the interval topology is second-countable. That is, in the case of a countable basis, σ-field generated by the open (or closed) intervals coincides with those generated by open intervals (and hence, coincides with its interval topology). Then, in fact, every monotone increasing function on such a complete chain will be (Borel) measurable (and hence, if the best response correspondence transforms the space I(T, S) M(T, S) into I(T, S), it also maps into I(T, S) M(T, S), where I(T, S) M(T, S) is a complete lattice. Then, the existence result follows from a standard application of Veinott (1992) or Zhou (1994). This shows that the strength of Yang and Qi (2013) theorem is limited to type-spaces can be embedded in Hilbert cube 3 (See Theorem 4 in Appendix). In fact, order topology need not be embedded in real line (See Theorem 5 in Appendix) This limitation is significant, as recently many theoretical and applied papers in the literature of large games have assumed a saturated measure space of players types/traits (which clearly is not second-countable). For example, assumption that players types space is saturated is a necessary one if one wants to use the large game in a context of a Bayesian information game and apply the Law of Large Numbers (see Sun, 2006). Second, using very different methods, Balbus, Dziewulski, Reffett, and Woźny (2014) prove the existence of a distributional equilibrium in a class of large games with strategic complementarities (which includes large superrmodular games) using Markowsky (1976) fixed point theorem 4. That is, under similar assumptions as as those in Yang and Qi (2013), but allowing for more general spaces of agents types/traits, they manage to establish conditions under which that set of distributional equilibria possess the greatest and the least Nash equilibria where players use only monotone strategies (and equilibria are not necessarily monotone in types). 5 Interestingly, the set of distributional equilibria is 3 Hilbert cube is [0, 1] N endowed with product topology. Clearly it is metrizable with metric d(x, y) := 1 x 2 k k y k where x = (x k ) k N, and y = (y k ) k N k=1 4 Markowsky (1976) presents the following theorem (see theorem 9 in his paper). Let F : X X be increasing, and X a chain complete poset. Then, the set of fixed points of F is a chain complete poset. Moreover, we have {x : x F (x)} the greatest fixed point, and {x : x F (x)} the least fixed point of F. 5 That is, importantly, neither monotonicity of strategies, nor increasing differences between the action 5

not a complete lattice. This is due to the fact that the set of probability distributions on T S order first order stochastic dominance is in general not even a lattice (let alone a complete lattice). Third, another way to re-establish a result on a complete lattice of Nash equilibria in a large supermodular game is to use the definition of equilibria in a large game due to Schmeidler (1973), where in his definition of Cournot-Nash equilibrium, players only a.e. optimize. This construction is also presented in Balbus, Dziewulski, Reffett, and Woźny (2014), where authors analyze the set of equivalence classes of measurable functions and apply Veinott (1992) fixed point result to a best response correspondence mapping such equivalence classes of measurable functions. To apply it to the Yang and Qi (2013) setting, one needs to modify their Nash equilibrium definition requiring Nash equilibrium definition 1 be satisfied for a.e. θ Θ. For more results along these lines but in the context of Bayesian games, see Vives (1990). Clearly, in such cases, the special case of monotone equilibrium can be established when suitable added restrictions are placed on the game. 4 General existence results We now present in detail some additional results on monotone equilibrium existence using the construction found in Balbus, Dziewulski, Reffett, and Woźny (2014). Let T be a compact metric space of players characteristics/traits. Endow T with σ-field T, as well as a positive nonatomic σ-finite measure p. Mathematically, (T, T, p) is a measure space. Let S R M (m N) be the player s action space endowed with its natural product order and Euclidean topology. Endow the product space T S with an order p. Assume this order satisfies an implication (θ, s ) p (θ, s) s s. In what follows, we make an additional assumption. Assumption 2 Assume: s f(s, r, θ) is order continuous for each θ T and r P(T S), θ f(s, r, θ) is measurable for each s S and r P(T S). and types are required in the construction of Balbus, Dziewulski, Reffett, and Woźny (2014). This is important as monotonicity in names is often a very restrictive form of equilibria to seek. Still, using their methods, results on equilibria that are monotone in types/names can be obtained if one assumes increasing differences between the action and types (as Yang and Qi (2013) do in their paper). We discuss this in the next section of the paper. 6

Theorem 2 Assume 1 and 2, then the set of monotone Nash equilibria of Γ is nonempty and possesses a greatest and least element. Proof: By theorem 3.1. of Balbus, Dziewulski, Reffett, and Woźny (2014), the set P(T S) is a chain complete poset. Moreover, the greatest best response operator m(θ, r) = arg max s S f(s, r, θ) is monotone by Topkis theorem. We next show that the θ m(θ, r) is measurable. As f is a Carathéodory for all r, by Theorem 18.19 in Aliprantis and Border (2006), we have R r (θ) := max f(s, r, θ) s S measurable, and the arg max correspondence m(θ, r) also measurable. As m(, r) maps a measurable space into metrizable space, it is weakly measurable (see Aliprantis and Border, 2006, Theorem 18.2). Further, observe that m(θ, r) = (ŝ 1,..., ŝ m ), where ŝ i = max P roj i(s) and P roj i denotes a projection of a vector on its i th coordinate. 6 Since a s m(θ,r) projection is a continuous function in this context, by the Measurable Maximum Theorem (see Aliprantis and Border (2006), Theorem 18.19), θ m(θ, r) is p-measurable function. Next, consider an operator B(r)(G) = p({θ : (θ, m(θ, r)) G}) that maps P(T S) into P(T S). Clearly, B is monotone in the sense of first order stochastic dominance.as P(T S) is chain complete, by Markowsky (1976) fixed point theorem, B possesses the greatest fixed point theorem, say r, for which we construct the greatest Nash equilibrium x with x (θ) = m(θ, r ). The existence of a least Nash equilibrium follows from a similar construction. Few comments in this result are in order. First, this result establishes the existence of the greatest and the least Nash equilibrium of F in monotone strategies. In fact, if we drop increasing differencs between (s, θ) in our assumptions, our result still states existence of the greatest and the least Nash equilibrium of F. So, as opposed to Yang and Qi (2013), we obtain our result for general type spaces T, but at the cost of restricting S R M. This latter restriction is necessary in our current construction to obtain measurability of the best response selector. Moreover, similar to corollary 3.1 in Balbus, Dziewulski, Reffett, and Woźny (2014) or theorem 2 in Yang and Qi (2013), we can establish the monotone comparative statics results. Finally, our result does not claim the set of Nash equilibria is a complete lattice; rather, at best, it is merely a chain complete poset. This happens, in particular, if B = B (i.e, when the best reply map is a function). 6 For s i R M by max we denote a max of all coordinates. 7

Next, to re-establish complete lattice of Nash equilibria, we need to slightly modify the definition of the Nash equilibrium to be in line with that found in Schmeidler (1973): i.e., for p a.e. θ T, s S we have f(x(θ), p (i T, x) 1, θ) f(s, p (i T, x) 1, θ), (2) Now, endow the set M(T, S) with the following order for x, x M(T, S) we say x x iff x (θ) x(θ) p a.e. θ. We can then we state the following result: Theorem 3 Assume 1 and 2. Then, the set of monotone Schmeidler-Nash equilibria of the game Γ is a nonempty complete lattice. Proof: By a result in Vives (1990), the set (M(T, S), ) is a complete lattice; hence, as I(T, S) subcomplete in (M(T, S), ), M(T, S) I(T, S) a complete lattice. We, next consider the operator B(x) = {x M(T, S) I(T, S) : x (θ) = arg max s S f(s, p (i T, x) 1, θ) p a.e. θ}. Clearly, B(x) is nonempty (by the argument analogous to that in the proof of theorem 2). Moreover, B is monotone and maps M(T, S) I(T, S) into itself. Therefore, by the theorems of Veinott (1992) or Zhou (1994), the game Γ has a complete lattice of fixed points, and hence Schmeidler-Nash equilibria. 5 Appendix In this appendix, we provide an answer to the question of what properties of type space T are sufficient for the key lemma in Yang and Qi (2013) to be correct. In particular, we discuss the case that of type spaces where the interval topology is second countable. Having this additional condition in place, lemma 1 will be correct. We begin with the following theorem: Theorem 4 Suppose T is a complete chain and order topology T is second countable. Then, T is separable metric space and can be embedded in a Hilbert cube. Proof: We first claim the base can be formed from countable union of open intervals (θ k, θ k ) k N for some dense collection {θ k, θ k : k R}, where θ k < θ k (and, indeed, the 8

collection of the unions of intervals are closed for finite intersections). uncountable set T, N t (θ t i, θ t i). t T i=1 Take for any where for each t T {θ t i : i N} {θ i : i N} and {θ t i : i N} {θ i : i N}. Hence, we have possibly uncountable union of the sets (θ t i, θ t i); but for each i, there is index k i such that θ t i = θ ki for all but countably many t. By a similar argument, we have for θ t i. Hence this union is in fact countable. Hence, the base is built from countably many intervals. Now, we show T is a regular topology. Let x F 1. Then, take neighbourhood of x, say E x E, disjoint with F 2. Put G 1 := F1 c E x. For all y F 2, we construct x F 1 neighbourhood of D y E to be disjoint with G 1. Set ξ y := {x F 2 : x < y} and η y := {x F 2 : x > y}. Clearly ξ y, η y F 2. By definition E ξy and E ηy do not include y. Set D y = ( E ξy, E ηy ). Then, we set G2 := F o 2 y F 2 D y. Clearly, G 1 G 2 =. Hence, T is regular and Hausdorff. As a result by Urysohn Metrization Theorem (see Theorem 3.40 in Aliprantis and Border (2006)) (Θ, T ) is metrizable space and can be embedded a in Hilbert cube. Define Θ := Q [0, 1] with Q as rational numbers. Define as lexicographical order i.e. (a, b) (x, y) (a < x) (a = x, b y). Let T be its order topology. Clearly base of T is second countable with base sets B q,i := {q} I, where I [0, 1] is interval with rational center and rational length. By Theorem 4, Θ can be embedded in Hilbert cube. For all nets {(x α, y α ) : α D}, we write (x α, y α ) (x, y) to denote that (x, y) is limit of (x α, y α ) in topology T. As we show in next Theorem, it is not embedded in R. Theorem 5 There exists a complete chain T such that its order topology is second countable, and T is not embedded in R. Proof: Put T := Θ with its order topology. On a contrary, suppose u : T R is continuous function. We show that it is not injection. For all y [0, 1], define f(x) = u(x, y) u(x, 0). Then, f is continuous as well. Let x α x be some net, α D and D is some directed set. Suppose x α is not eventually constant. We show that (x α, y) (x, 0). 9

Set (x, y ) (x, 0). If x α is not eventually constant. Then x < x α eventually and consequently (x, y ) (x α, y) (x, 0). As a result net (x α, y) (x, 0). Hence f(x α ) = (x α, y) u(x α, 0) 0 for all y [0, 1]. Since f is continuous, hence f(x α ) f(x), as a result f(x) 0. Consequently u(x, y) = u(x, 0) for all y [0, 1]. As a result u can not be injection, and T is not embedded in R. References Aliprantis, C. D., and K. C. Border (2006): Infinite Dimentional Analysis. A Hitchhiker s Guide. Springer Verlag: Heilbelberg, 3rd edn. Balbus, L., P. Dziewulski, K. Reffett, and L. Woźny (2014): A qualititive theory of large games with strategic complementarities, Mimeo. Markowsky, G. (1976): Chain-complete posets and directed sets with applications, Algebra Universitae, 6, 53 68. Schmeidler, D. (1973): Equilibrium points of nonatomic games, Journal of Statisitical Physics, 17(4), 295 300. Sun, Y. (2006): The exact law of large numbers via Fubini extension and characterization of insurable risks, Journal of Economic Theory, 126(1), 31 69. Tarski, A. (1955): A lattice-theoretical fixpoint theorem and its applications, Pacific Journal of Mathematics, 5, 285 309. Veinott (1992): Lattice programming: qualitative optimization and equilibria. MS Standford. Vives, X. (1990): Nash equilibrium with strategic complementarites, Journal of Mathematical Economics, 19, 305 321. Yang, J., and X. Qi (2013): The nonatomic supermodular game, Games and Economic Behavior, 82(C), 609 620. Zhou, L. (1994): The set of Nash equilibria of a supermodular game is a complete lattice, Games and Economic Behavior, 7, 295 300. 10