Preference and Utility

Similar documents
Exercise 1.2. Suppose R, Q are two binary relations on X. Prove that, given our notation, the following are equivalent:

Monotone comparative statics Finite Data and GARP

Structural Properties of Utility Functions Walrasian Demand

Solution Homework 1 - EconS 501

Definitions: A binary relation R on a set X is (a) reflexive if x X : xrx; (f) asymmetric if x, x X : [x Rx xr c x ]

Spring 2014 Advanced Probability Overview. Lecture Notes Set 1: Course Overview, σ-fields, and Measures

Revealed Preferences and Utility Functions

g 2 (x) (1/3)M 1 = (1/3)(2/3)M.

Chapter 1 - Preference and choice

Lecture 1. Econ 2001: Introduction to Mathematical Methods (a.k.a. Math Camp) 2015 August 10

Hicksian Demand and Expenditure Function Duality, Slutsky Equation

Connectedness. Proposition 2.2. The following are equivalent for a topological space (X, T ).

5 Set Operations, Functions, and Counting

Technical Results on Regular Preferences and Demand

Student s Guide Chapter 1: Choice, Preference, and Utility

First Welfare Theorem

Properties of Walrasian Demand

Midterm 1. Every element of the set of functions is continuous

ABSTRACT INTEGRATION CHAPTER ONE

Introductory Analysis I Fall 2014 Homework #5 Solutions

M17 MAT25-21 HOMEWORK 6

Solution Homework 1 - EconS 501

Lecture 2. Econ August 11

2. Prime and Maximal Ideals

Walker Ray Econ 204 Problem Set 3 Suggested Solutions August 6, 2015

Economics 204 Summer/Fall 2017 Lecture 7 Tuesday July 25, 2017

Sets, Functions and Metric Spaces

Individual decision-making under certainty

Strictly monotonic preferences on continuum of goods commodity spaces

Important Properties of R

Mid Term-1 : Practice problems

Math 421, Homework #6 Solutions. (1) Let E R n Show that = (E c ) o, i.e. the complement of the closure is the interior of the complement.

Lecture 5 - Hausdorff and Gromov-Hausdorff Distance

Homework 1 (revised) Solutions

Lecture 8: Basic convex analysis

Theorems. Theorem 1.11: Greatest-Lower-Bound Property. Theorem 1.20: The Archimedean property of. Theorem 1.21: -th Root of Real Numbers

x 1 1 and p 1 1 Two points if you just talk about monotonicity (u (c) > 0).

a + b = b + a and a b = b a. (a + b) + c = a + (b + c) and (a b) c = a (b c). a (b + c) = a b + a c and (a + b) c = a c + b c.

Properties of the Integers

MA651 Topology. Lecture 9. Compactness 2.

Basic set-theoretic techniques in logic Part II, Counting beyond infinity: Ordinal numbers

First In-Class Exam Solutions Math 410, Professor David Levermore Monday, 1 October 2018

MAT 570 REAL ANALYSIS LECTURE NOTES. Contents. 1. Sets Functions Countability Axiom of choice Equivalence relations 9

Econ Lecture 2. Outline

Anscombe & Aumann Expected Utility Betting and Insurance

Discrete Mathematics for CS Spring 2007 Luca Trevisan Lecture 27

1 Topology Definition of a topology Basis (Base) of a topology The subspace topology & the product topology on X Y 3

Second Welfare Theorem

Exercises for Unit VI (Infinite constructions in set theory)

In N we can do addition, but in order to do subtraction we need to extend N to the integers

Axioms of separation

GARP and Afriat s Theorem Production

DO FIVE OUT OF SIX ON EACH SET PROBLEM SET

Preference identification

In N we can do addition, but in order to do subtraction we need to extend N to the integers

Lebesgue Measure on R n

Choice, Preference, and Utility

CONSUMER DEMAND. Consumer Demand

Week 2: Sequences and Series

MATH 521, WEEK 2: Rational and Real Numbers, Ordered Sets, Countable Sets

Abstract Measure Theory

Problem Set 2: Solutions Math 201A: Fall 2016

Utility Representation of Lower Separable Preferences

Solutions to Tutorial 8 (Week 9)

µ (X) := inf l(i k ) where X k=1 I k, I k an open interval Notice that is a map from subsets of R to non-negative number together with infinity

6.2 Deeper Properties of Continuous Functions

Assignment #2 COMP 3200 Spring 2012 Prof. Stucki

Part V. 17 Introduction: What are measures and why measurable sets. Lebesgue Integration Theory

Section 2: Classes of Sets

Lebesgue measure on R is just one of many important measures in mathematics. In these notes we introduce the general framework for measures.

Solutions for Homework Assignment 2

1 Selected Homework Solutions

Math 3361-Modern Algebra Lecture 08 9/26/ Cardinality

MORE ON CONTINUOUS FUNCTIONS AND SETS

Real Analysis - Notes and After Notes Fall 2008

We are going to discuss what it means for a sequence to converge in three stages: First, we define what it means for a sequence to converge to zero

1. (B) The union of sets A and B is the set whose elements belong to at least one of A

Numerical representations of binary relations with thresholds: A brief survey 1

1. Is the set {f a,b (x) = ax + b a Q and b Q} of all linear functions with rational coefficients countable or uncountable?

Bases in Banach spaces

REAL AND COMPLEX ANALYSIS

Set, functions and Euclidean space. Seungjin Han

{x : P (x)} P (x) = x is a cat

Uniqueness, Stability, and Gross Substitutes

6.254 : Game Theory with Engineering Applications Lecture 7: Supermodular Games

Final Exam Review. 2. Let A = {, { }}. What is the cardinality of A? Is

Part III. 10 Topological Space Basics. Topological Spaces

1. Supremum and Infimum Remark: In this sections, all the subsets of R are assumed to be nonempty.

Notes on ordinals and cardinals

MATH 409 Advanced Calculus I Lecture 7: Monotone sequences. The Bolzano-Weierstrass theorem.

Lecture Notes in Real Analysis Anant R. Shastri Department of Mathematics Indian Institute of Technology Bombay

Choice, Preferences and Utility

Problem 2: ii) Completeness of implies that for any x X we have x x and thus x x. Thus x I(x).

van Rooij, Schikhof: A Second Course on Real Functions

Well-Ordered Sets, Ordinals and Cardinals Ali Nesin 1 July 2001

CSE 20 DISCRETE MATH. Fall

Maths 212: Homework Solutions

The Real Number System

Math 105A HW 1 Solutions

Transcription:

Preference and Utility Econ 2100 Fall 2017 Lecture 3, 5 September Problem Set 1 is due in Kelly s mailbox by 5pm today Outline 1 Existence of Utility Functions 2 Continuous Preferences 3 Debreu s Representation Theorem

Definitions From Last Week A binary relation on X is a preference relation if it is a weak order, i.e. complete and transitive. The upper contour set of x is (x) = {y X : y x}. The lower contour set of x is (x) = {y X : x y}. The utility function u : X R represents the binary relation on X if x y u(x) u(y). Question: Under what assumptions can a preference relation be represented by a utility function? We know we need transitivity and continuity. Are they enough?

Existence of a Utility: Alternative Definition The following provides an alternative way to show that that a preference is represented by some function (very useful). Question 1, Problem Set 2 (due Tuesday September 12). Let be a preference relation. Prove that u : X R represents if and only if: x y u(x) u(y); and x y u(x) > u(y). This result is useful as it makes it (sometimes) easier to show some utility function represents.

Existence of a Utility Function When X is Finite Theorem Suppose X is finite. Then is a preference relation if and only if there exists some utility function u : X R that represents. When the consumption set is finite finding a utility function that represents any given preferences is easy. The proof is constructive: a function that works is the one that counts the number of elements that are not as good as the one in question. This function is well defined since the are only finitely many items that can be worse than something. In other words, the utility function is u(x) = (x) where (x) = {y X : x y} is the lower contour set of x, and denotes the cardinality of. Notice that we only need to prove that this function represents (x) because from a previous result we know that if that is the case then is a preference relation.

Existence of a Utility Function When X is Finite If X is finite and is a preference relation u : X R that represents. Proof. Let u(x) = (x). Since X is finite, u(x) is finite and therefore well defined. Suppose x y. I claim this implies u(x) u(y). Let z (y), i.e. y z. By transitivity, x z, i.e. z (x). Thus (y) (x). Therefore (y) (x). By definition, this means u(y) u(x). Now suppose x y. I claim this implies u(x) > u(y). x y implies x y, so the argument above implies (y) (x). x x by completeness, so x (x). Also, x y implies x / (y). Hence (y) and {x} are disjoint, and both subsets of (x). Then (y) {x} (x) (y) {x} (x) (y) + {x} (x) u (y) + 1 u (x) u (y) < u (x) This proves x y u(x) u(y) x y u(x) > u(y) and thus we are done.

Utility Function for a Countable Space Existence of a utility function can also be proven for a countable space. Theorem Suppose X is countable. Then is a preference relation if and only if there exists some utility function u : X R that represents. Proof. Question 2, Problem Set 2 Notice that the previous construction cannot be applied directly here because the cardinality of the lower contour sets can be infinite. You will have to come up with a trick that works.

Lexicographic Preferences We want conditions on a preference relation which guarantee the existence of a utility function representing those preferences even if X is uncountable. Typically, we assume that X lives in R n, but ideally we would want as few restrictions on X as we can get away with. We know that without completeness and transitivity a utility function does not exist, so we cannot dispense of those. Exercise What else is needed? Next, a counterexample of the existence of a representation. Show that the lexicographic ordering on R 2 defined by x 1 > y 1 (x 1, x 2 ) (y 1, y 2 ) or x 1 = y 1 and x 2 y 2 is complete, transitive, and antisymmetric (i.e. if x y and y x, then x = y). The lexicographic ordering is a preference relation (it is complete and transitive), yet admits no utility representation.

The Lexicographic Ordering in R 2 admits no utility representation x 1 > y 1 Let X = R 2 and define by (x 1, x 2 ) (y 1, y 2 ) or x 1 = y 1 and x 2 y 2 Suppose there exists a utility function u representing (find a contradiction). For any x 1 R, (x 1, 1) (x 1, 0) and thus u(x 1, 1) > u(x 1, 0) since u represents. The rational numbers are dense in the real line (for any open interval (a, b), there exists a rational number r such that r (a, b)); hence, there exists a rational number r(x 1 ) R such that: u(x 1, 1) > r(x 1 ) > u(x 1, 0) Define r : R R by selecting r(x 1 ) to satisfy u(x 1, 1) > r(x 1 ) > u(x 1, 0). CLAIM: r( ) is a one-to-one function. Suppose x 1 x 1; and without loss of generality assume x 1 > x 1. Then: by (A) since (x 1,0) (x 1 {}}{,1) by (A) {}}{{}}{ r(x 1) > u(x 1, 0) > u(x 1, 1) > r(x 1) Thus r( ) is an a one-to-one function from the real numbers to the rational numbers, which contradicts the fact the real line is uncountable. (A)

Continuous Preferences Continuity will get rid of this example. Definition A binary relation on the metric space X is continuous if, for all x X, the upper and lower contour sets, {y X : y x} and {y X : x y}, are closed. Examples Define by (x 1, x 2 ) (y 1, y 2 ) x 1 > y 1 or x 1 = y 1 and x 2 y 2 Draw the upper contour set of (1, 1); this preference on R 2 is not continuous. x 1 y 1 Define by (x 1, x 2 ) (y 1, y 2 ) and x 2 y 2 Draw the upper contour set of (1, 1); this preference on R 2 is continuous.

Continuous Preferences Definition A binary relation on the metric space X is continuous if, for all x X, the upper and lower contour sets, {y X : y x} and {y X : x y}, are closed. Proposition A binary relation is continuous if and only if: 1 If x n y for all n and x n x, then x y; and 2 If x y n for all n and y n y, then x y. Proof. This follows from the fact that a set is closed if and only if it contains all of its limit points.

Debreu s Representation Theorem The main result of today is due to Gerard Debreu, and it provides necessary and suffi cient conditions for the existence of a continuous utility function. Theorem (Debreu) Suppose X R n. The binary relation on X is complete, transitive, and continuous if and only if there exists a continuous utility representation u : X R. We will prove suffi ciency next (under a couple of simplifying assumptions, but you should ckeck what happens without those). You will do necessity as homework. Question 4, Problem Set 2. Suppose X R n. Prove that if u : X R is a continuous utility function representing, then is a complete, transitive, and continuous preference relation.

Debreu s Representation Theorem Theorem (Debreu) Suppose X R n. The binary relation on X is complete, transitive, and continuous if and only if there exists a continuous utility representation u : X R. Two simplifying assumptions: X = R n ; and is strictly monotone, (i.e. if x i y i for all i and x y, then x y). When strict monotonicity holds we have α β αe βe. where e = (1, 1,..., 1) (make sure you check this). (mon) To prove: if is a continuous and strictly monotone preference relation on R n, then there exists a continuous utility representation of. How do we find a utility function? Look at the point on the 45 o line that is indifferent: u(x) = α (x) where α (x) is the real number α such that α e x The proof is in 3 steps.

Proof. Step 1: There exists a unique α (x) such that α e x. Let B = {β R : βe x} R and define α = inf {β R : βe x}. }{{} B Oviously, (max i x i )e x, so by strict monotonicity (max i x i )e x which implies B is nonempty and α is well-defined. Now show that α e x and α e x, so that α e x. Since α is the infimum of B, there exists a sequence β n B s.t. β n α. Then β n e α e (in R n ) and β n e x because β B. By continuity, one gets: α e x as desired. Since α is a lower bound of B, if α B α α. Using the contrapositive: α < α αe x. (A) Let α n = α 1. By (A), αne x, so αne x. n Also, α ne α e (in R n ). Hence, by continuity, α e x as desired. To prove uniqueness, suppose ˆαe x. By transitivity, ˆαe α e. Then, by (mon), ˆα = α.

Step 2: The u(x) that represents is defined as follows: Proof. u(x) = α (x) where α (x) is the unique α such that α e x. Show that u(x) represents. Suppose x y. By construction of α, we have: x α (x)e and α (y)e y By transitivity, we have: x α (x)e α (y)e y By (mon) this is equivalent to α (x) α (y) Repeat the same argument to show that x y implies α (x) > α (y). Since we have shown that x y u(x) u(y) x y u(x) > u(y) we are done.

Proof. u(x) = α (x) Step 3: The defined u(x) is continuous. where α (x) is the unique α such that α e x To prove that a function f : R n R is continuous, it suffi ces to show that f 1 ((a, b)) is open for all a, b R. Since ae ae, we have u(ae) = α (ae) = a for any a R. Notice that u 1 ((a, b)) = u 1 ((a, ) (, b)) = u 1 ((a, )) u 1 ((, b)). But u(ae) = a, so u 1 ((a, )) = u 1 ((u(ae), )) = {x R n : x ae}, this is open because the strict upper contour set of ae is open whenever is complete and continuous (why?). An entirely symmetric argument proves that u 1 ((, b)) is the strict lower contour set of be, hence it is also an open set. Since u 1 ((a, b)) is the intersection of two open sets, it is open.

Debreu s Representation Theorem Back to the theorem Theorem (Debreu) Suppose X R n. The binary relation on X is complete, transitive, and continuous if and only if there exists a continuous utility representation u : X R. Conclusion When her preference relation is complete, transitive, and continuous the consumer s taste is entirely described by some continuous utility function that represents that preference relation. The theorem asserts that one of the utility representations for must be continuous, not that all of the utility representations must be continuous. Continuity is a cardinal feature of the utility function, not an ordinal feature, since it is not robust to strictly increasing transformations. Exercise Construct a preference relation on R that is not continuous, but admits a utility representation.

Choice Rules and Utility Functions The induced choice rule for is C (A) = {x A : x y for all y A} Proposition If is a continuous preference relation and A R n is nonempty and compact, then C (A) is nonempty and compact. Proof. Suppose is continuous. By Debreu s Theorem, there exists some continuous function u representing the preferences. One can show (do it as exercise) that C (A) = arg max x A u(x). Nonemptiness then follows from continuity of u and the Extreme Value Theorem. Compactness follows from the fact u 1 ( ) is bounded (it is a subset of the bounded set A), and closed (since the inverse image of a closed set under a continuous function is closed).

Structural Properties of Utilify Function Structural Properties of Utility Functions The main idea is to understand the connection between properties of preferences and characteristics of the utility function that represents them. NOTATION: From now on, assume X = R n. Remember the notation for vectors: if x i y i for each i, we write x y.

Monotonicity Monotonicity says more is better. Definitions A preference relation is weakly monotone if x y implies x y. A preference relation is strictly monotone if x y and x y imply x y. In our notation, x y and x y imply x i > y i for some i. Question What does monotonicity imply for the utility function representing?

Monotonicity: An Example Example Suppose is the preference relation on R 2 defined by x y if and only if x 1 y 1 is weakly monotone, because if x y, then x 1 y 1. It is not strictly monotone, because (1, 1) (1, 0) and (1, 1) (1, 0) but not [(1, 1) (1, 0)] since (1, 0) (1, 1).

Strict Monotonicity: An Example The lexicographic preference on R 2 is strictly monotone Proof: Suppose x y and x y. Then there are two possibilities: (a) : x 1 > y 1 and x 2 y 2 or (b) : x 1 y 1 and x 2 > y 2. If (a) holds, then x y because x 1 y 1, and not (y x) because neither y 1 > x 1 (excluded by x 1 > y 1) nor y 1 = x 1 (also excluded by x 1 > y 1). If (b) holds, then x y because either x 1 > y 1 or x 1 = y 1 and x 2 y 2, and not (y x) because not (y 1 > x 1) (excluded by x 1 y 1) and not (y 2 x 2) (excluded by x 2 > y 2). In both cases, x y and not (y x) thus x y.

Monotonicity and Utility Functions Definitions A function f : R n R is nondecreasing if x y implies f (x) f (y); strictly increasing if x y and x y imply f (x) > f (y). Monotonicity is equivalent to the corresponding utility function being nondecreasing or increasing. Proposition If u represents, then: 1 is weakly monotone if and only if u is nondecreasing; 2 is strictly monotone if and only if u is strictly increasing. Proof. Question 5a. Problem Set 2.