First Welfare Theorem

Similar documents
Second Welfare Theorem

Competitive Equilibrium

Differentiable Welfare Theorems Existence of a Competitive Equilibrium: Preliminaries

The Ohio State University Department of Economics. Homework Set Questions and Answers

Introduction to General Equilibrium: Framework.

Notes on General Equilibrium

Notes IV General Equilibrium and Welfare Properties

1 General Equilibrium

4 Lecture Applications

Introduction to General Equilibrium

The Consumer, the Firm, and an Economy

Market Equilibrium and the Core

EC487 Advanced Microeconomics, Part I: Lecture 5

General Equilibrium. General Equilibrium, Berardino. Cesi, MSc Tor Vergata

Equilibrium and Pareto Efficiency in an exchange economy

Fundamental Theorems of Welfare Economics

In the Name of God. Sharif University of Technology. Microeconomics 1. Graduate School of Management and Economics. Dr. S.

Department of Economics The Ohio State University Final Exam Questions and Answers Econ 8712

The Fundamental Welfare Theorems

Question 1. (p p) (x(p, w ) x(p, w)) 0. with strict inequality if x(p, w) x(p, w ).

Microeconomic Theory -1- Introduction

Walrasian Equilibrium in an exchange economy

Structural Properties of Utility Functions Walrasian Demand

Uniqueness, Stability, and Gross Substitutes

The Debreu-Scarf Theorem: The Core Converges to the Walrasian Allocations

Problem Set Suggested Answers

Microeconomics, Block I Part 2

ECONOMICS 001 Microeconomic Theory Summer Mid-semester Exam 2. There are two questions. Answer both. Marks are given in parentheses.

Microeconomics II. MOSEC, LUISS Guido Carli Problem Set n 3

ANSWERS TO ODD NUMBERED EXERCISES IN CHAPTER 3

Economic Growth: Lectures 5-7, Neoclassical Growth

0 Aims of this course

Lecture #3. General equilibrium

; p. p y p y p y. Production Set: We have 2 constraints on production - demand for each factor of production must be less than its endowment

3. THE EXCHANGE ECONOMY

Economic Growth: Lecture 8, Overlapping Generations

Positive Theory of Equilibrium: Existence, Uniqueness, and Stability

Alp Simsek (MIT) Recitation Notes: 1. Gorman s Aggregation Th eorem2. Normative Representative November 9, Household Theorem / 16

Welfare Economics: Lecture 12

EconS Microeconomic Theory II Homework #9 - Answer key

Economics 501B Final Exam Fall 2017 Solutions

General Equilibrium with Production

Core equivalence and welfare properties without divisible goods

Lecture 1. History of general equilibrium theory

Ph.D. Preliminary Examination MICROECONOMIC THEORY Applied Economics Graduate Program May 2012

Problem Set 1 Welfare Economics

Core. Ichiro Obara. December 3, 2008 UCLA. Obara (UCLA) Core December 3, / 22

Monotone comparative statics Finite Data and GARP

General Equilibrium and Welfare

Foundations of Neoclassical Growth

Ph.D. Preliminary Examination MICROECONOMIC THEORY Applied Economics Graduate Program June 2016

Adding Production to the Theory

Market Outcomes: Efficient or Fair?

Advanced Microeconomic Theory. Chapter 6: Partial and General Equilibrium

General equilibrium with externalities and tradable licenses

3.2 THE FUNDAMENTAL WELFARE THEOREMS

Economics 101. Lecture 2 - The Walrasian Model and Consumer Choice

Economics 201b Spring 2010 Solutions to Problem Set 1 John Zhu

The Fundamental Welfare Theorems

Department of Economics The Ohio State University Midterm Answers Econ 805

Lecture Notes October 18, Reading assignment for this lecture: Syllabus, section I.

Essential Microeconomics : EQUILIBRIUM AND EFFICIENCY WITH PRODUCTION Key ideas: Walrasian equilibrium, first and second welfare theorems

Revealed Preferences and Utility Functions

Economic Core, Fair Allocations, and Social Choice Theory

Microeconomics II Lecture 4. Marshallian and Hicksian demands for goods with an endowment (Labour supply)

Lecture 7: General Equilibrium - Existence, Uniqueness, Stability

Final Examination with Answers: Economics 210A

Short correct answers are sufficient and get full credit. Including irrelevant (though correct) information in an answer will not increase the score.

Econ 201: Problem Set 3 Answers

1 Second Welfare Theorem

Last Revised: :19: (Fri, 12 Jan 2007)(Revision:

Pareto Efficiency (also called Pareto Optimality)

Hicksian Demand and Expenditure Function Duality, Slutsky Equation

Advanced Microeconomics Problem Set 1

Econ 401A: Economic Theory Mid-term. Answers

Discussion Papers in Economics

Economics 604: Microeconomics Deborah Minehart & Rachel Kranton

Economics 200A part 2 UCSD Fall quarter 2011 Prof. R. Starr Mr. Troy Kravitz1 FINAL EXAMINATION SUGGESTED ANSWERS

x 1 1 and p 1 1 Two points if you just talk about monotonicity (u (c) > 0).

Short correct answers are sufficient and get full credit. Including irrelevant (though correct) information in an answer will not increase the score.

EconS 501 Final Exam - December 10th, 2018

Economic Growth: Lecture 7, Overlapping Generations

Lectures on General Equilibrium Theory. Revealed preference tests of utility maximization and general equilibrium

Simon Fraser University, Department of Economics, Econ 201, Prof. Karaivanov FINAL EXAM Answer key

Microeconomics. Joana Pais. Fall Joana Pais

5.1 THE ROBINSON CRUSOE ECONOMY

Duality. for The New Palgrave Dictionary of Economics, 2nd ed. Lawrence E. Blume

E 600 Chapter 4: Optimization

Economics 201B Second Half. Lecture 12-4/22/10. Core is the most commonly used. The core is the set of all allocations such that no coalition (set of

Rice University. Answer Key to Mid-Semester Examination Fall ECON 501: Advanced Microeconomic Theory. Part A

Firms and returns to scale -1- John Riley


PhD Qualifier Examination

Intro to Economic analysis

Competitive Market Mechanisms as Social Choice Procedures

Note on social choice allocation in exchange economies with Cobb-Douglas preferences

Advanced Microeconomics

Noncooperative Games, Couplings Constraints, and Partial Effi ciency

3/1/2016. Intermediate Microeconomics W3211. Lecture 3: Preferences and Choice. Today s Aims. The Story So Far. A Short Diversion: Proofs

Unlinked Allocations in an Exchange Economy with One Good and One Bad

Transcription:

First Welfare Theorem Econ 2100 Fall 2017 Lecture 17, October 31 Outline 1 First Welfare Theorem 2 Preliminaries to Second Welfare Theorem

Past Definitions A feasible allocation (ˆx, ŷ) is Pareto optimal if there is no other feasible allocation (x, y) such that x i i ˆx i for all i and x i i ˆx i for some i. An allocation (x, y ) and a price vector p R L + form a competitive equilibrium if 1 for each j = 1,..., J: p y j p yj for all y j Y j ; 2 for each i = 1,..., I : xi i x i for all x i {x i X i : p x i p ω i + ( j θij p yj 3 i x i i ωi + j y j ) } ; and and if I x li < I ω li + J y lj then pl = 0. What is the relationship between competitive equilibrium and Pareto effi ciency? Is any competitive equilibirum Pareto effi cient? First Welfare Theorem. This is about excluding something can Pareto dominate the equilibrium allocation. Is any Pareto effi cient allocation (part of) a competitive equilibrium? Second Welfare Theorem. This is about finding prices that make the effi cient allocation an equilibirum.

How do we rule examples like this out? Need consumers preferences to be locally non satiated (there is always something nearby that makes the consumer better off). First Welfare Theorem: Counterexample An Edgeworth Box Economy Consider a two-person, two-good exchange economy. a s has utility function U a (x 1a, x 2a ) = 7; b s utility function U b (x 1b, x 2b ) = x 1b x 2b. The initial endowments are ω a = (2, 0) and ω b = (0, 2). CLAIM: x a = (1, 1), x b = (1, 1), and prices p = (1, 1) form a competitive equilibirum. a s utility is maximized. b s utility when her income equals 2 is maximized (this is a Cobb-Douglas utility function with equal exponents, so spending half her income on each good is optimal). x a + x b = (2, 2) = ω a + ω b. Is this allocation Pareto optimal? No: ˆx a = (0, 0) and ˆx b = (2, 2) Pareto dominates xa, xb since consumer a has the same utility while consumer b s utility is higher.

Local Non Satiation Definition A preference ordering i on X i is satiated at y if there exists no x in X i such that x i y. Definition The preference relation i on X i is locally non-satiated if for every x in X i and for every ε > 0 there exists an x in X i such that x x < ε and x i x. Remark Remember: y z = two points. L l=1 (y l z l ) 2 is the Euclidean distance between If i is continuous and locally non-satiated there exist a locally non-satiated utility function; then, any closed consumption set must be unbounded (or there would be a global satiation point).

Local Non Satiation and Walrasian Demand Lemma Suppose i is locally non-satiated, and let xi be defined as: xi i x i for all x i {x i X i : p x i w i }. Then and x i i x i implies p x i w i x i i x i implies p x i > w i If a consumption vector is weakly preferred to a maximal consumption bundle (i.e. an element of the Walrasian demand correspondence), it cannot cost strictly less. If a consumption vector is strictly preferred to a maximal bundle, it must not be affordable If not the consumer would have chosen it and been better-off. Make sure you prove this as an exercise (easy, but still worth doing).

First Welfare Theorem Theorem (First Fundamental Theorem of Welfare Economics) Suppose each consumer s preferences are locally non-satiated. Then, any allocation x, y that with prices p forms a competitive equilibrium is Pareto optimal. The invisible hand is Pareto effi cient. This is true under pretty mild conditions on each utility function. Local non-satiation has bite: there is always a more desirable commodity bundle nearby. There is another assumption implicit in our framework: lack of externalities (more later).

Proof of the First Welfare Theorem (by contradiction) Suppose not: there exists a feasible allocation x, y such such that x i i xi for all i, and x i i xi for some i. x i i xi implies p x i p ω i + j By local non satiation, θ ij (p yj ) x i i xi implies p x i > p ω i + j θ ij (p yj ) Therefore, summing over consumers ( ) p x i > p ω i + θ ij (p yj ) accounting = p ω i + p yj Since each y j maximizes profits at prices p, we also have p yj p y j. Substituting this into( the previous inequality: ) ( ) p x i > p ω i + p yj p ω i + But then x, y cannot be feasible since if it were we would have x i ω i + p x i p ω + which contradicts the expression above. y j p y j p y j

Externalities: An Example An Edgeworth Box Economy Consider a two-person, two-good exchange economy. u A (x 1A, x 2A, x 1B ) = x 1A x 2A x 1B ; u B (x 1B, x 2B ) = x 1B x 2B. A suffers from B s consumption of the first good. CLAIM: x A = (1, 1), x B = (1, 1), and p = (1, 1) is a competitive equilibirum. A cannot choose x 1B so that is a constant in her utility function. Then A s utility is maximized by x A at prices p since this is a Cobb-Douglas utility function with equal exponents and spending half your income on each good is optimal. B s utility when her income equals 2 is maximized (this is a Cobb-Douglas utility function with equal exponents, so spending half her income on each good is optimal). x a + x b = (2, 2) = ω A + ω B. Is this allocation Pareto optimal? No: (ˆx A, ˆx B ) = ( ( 5 4, 2 3 ), ( 3 4, 4 3 )) is a feasible Pareto improvement: U A (ˆx A, ˆx 1B ) = 5 2 4 3 3 4 = 1 12 > U A (xa, x1b ) = 1 1 = 0 U B (ˆx B ) = 3 4 4 3 = 1 = U B (xb )

First Welfare Theorem: Externalities In the previous example, the first welfare theorem fails because A s utility depends on B s consumption. This is called a (negative) externality: the more B consumes of the good, the worse-off A becomes. Among the assumptions implicit in our definition of preferences, one is important for the first welfare theorem: there are no externalities in consumption. There can be also externalities in production. Also, externalities can also be positive.

Competitive Equilibrium and the Core Theorem Any competitive equilibrium is in the core. Proof. Homework. This is very very similar to the proof of the First Welfare Theorem. A converse can be established in cases in which the economy is large, that is, it contains many individuals. That is called the core convergence theorem and I do not think we will have time for it.

Second Welfare Theorem: Preliminaries This is a converse to the First Welfare Theorem. The statement goes: under some conditions, any Pareto optimal allocation is part of a competitive equilibrium. Next, we try to understand what these conditions must be. We state and prove the theorem next class. In order to prove a Pareto optimal allocation is part of an equilibrium one needs to find the price vector that works for that allocation, since an equilibrium must specify and allocation and prices. First, we see a simple sense in which this cannot work: Pareto optimality disregards the budget constraints. This is fixed by adjusting the definition of equilibrium. Then we see two counterexamples that stress the need for convexities. These are fixed by assuming production sets and better-than sets are convex. Finally, we see an example showing that boundary issues can pose problems. This is fixed by, again, adjusting the definition of equilibrium.

Equilibrium With Transfers Definition ( ) Given an economy {X i, i, ω i } I, {Y j } J, an allocation x, y and a price vector p constitute a price equilibrium with transfers if there exists a vector of wealth levels w = (w 1, w 2,..., w I ) with w i = p ω i + p yj such that: 1 For each j = 1,..., J: p y j p y j for all y j Y j. 2 For each i = 1,..., I : xi i x i for all x i {x i X i : p x i w i } 3 xi I ω i + J yj, with p l = 0 if the inequlity is strict Aggregate wealth is divided among consumers so that the budget constrants are satisfied. How is the wealth of each consumer effected? They get a positive or negative transfer relative to the value of their endowment at the equilibrium prices. A competitive equilibrium satisfies this: set w i = p ω i + J θ ij(p yj ).

Remark Equilibrium With Transfers The income transfers (across consumers) that achieve the budget levels in the previous definition are: T i = w i p ( ω i + θ ij p yj ) Summing over consumers, we get T i = w i p ω i + i i = w i p ω + p yj = 0 θ ij ( p y j Transfers redistribute income so that the aggregate budget balances. This is important: in a general equilibirum model nothing should be outside the economy )

Definition Convexity A preference relation on X is convex if the set (x) = {y X y x} is convex for every x. If x and x are weakly preferred to x so is any convex combination. Convexity implies existence of an hyperplane that supports a consumer s better than set. Definition In an exchange economy, an allocation x is supported by a non-zero price vector p if: for each i = 1,..., I x i x i = p x p x i Convexity also yields an hyperplane that supports all producers better than set at the same time. This hyperplane is the price vector that makes a Pareto optimal allocation an equilibirum.