Ki, K2 AND RELATED MODAL SYSTEMS. A. N. PRIOR

Similar documents
A SIMPLE AXIOMATIZATION OF LUKASIEWICZ S MODAL LOGIC

In [3], Hallden in effect suggests that a modal (or other) system S 1}

On Axiomatic Rejection for the Description Logic ALC

ON THE ATOMIC FORMULA PROPERTY OF HÄRTIG S REFUTATION CALCULUS

Propositional Calculus - Hilbert system H Moonzoo Kim CS Dept. KAIST

RELATIONS BETWEEN PARACONSISTENT LOGIC AND MANY-VALUED LOGIC

ON LUKASIEWICZ'S -fc-modal SYSTEM TIMOTHY SMILEY

Axiomatizing hybrid logic using modal logic

Modal and temporal logic

Non-Analytic Tableaux for Chellas s Conditional Logic CK and Lewis s Logic of Counterfactuals VC

COUNTERFACTUALS AND SEMANTIC TABLEAUX

TABLEAUX VARIANTS OF SOME MODAL AND RELEVANT SYSTEMS

A SEQUENT SYSTEM OF THE LOGIC R FOR ROSSER SENTENCES 2. Abstract

Russell s logicism. Jeff Speaks. September 26, 2007

A CUT-FREE SIMPLE SEQUENT CALCULUS FOR MODAL LOGIC S5

GEORGE F. SCHUMM. is the smallest normal extension of L to contain A n

ON THE LOGIC OF DISTRIBUTIVE LATTICES

CHAPTER 11. Introduction to Intuitionistic Logic

On interpolation in existence logics

Mathematical Logic Prof. Arindama Singh Department of Mathematics Indian Institute of Technology, Madras. Lecture - 15 Propositional Calculus (PC)

An Introduction to Proof Theory

1. Propositional Calculus

KLEENE LOGIC AND INFERENCE

Přednáška 12. Důkazové kalkuly Kalkul Hilbertova typu. 11/29/2006 Hilbertův kalkul 1

From Syllogism to Common Sense

Implicational F -Structures and Implicational Relevance. Logics. A. Avron. Sackler Faculty of Exact Sciences. School of Mathematical Sciences

VALUATIONS FOR DIRECT PROPOSITIONAL

Semantics for Propositional Logic

An Introduction to Modal Logic III

Subminimal Logics and Relativistic Negation

02 The Axiomatic Method

Non-normal Worlds. Daniel Bonevac. February 5, 2012

Meaning and Reference INTENSIONAL AND MODAL LOGIC. Intensional Logic. Frege: Predicators (general terms) have

ONKINDSOFTEMPORALLOGICANDSOMEOFITS APPLICATIONS

Modal systems based on many-valued logics

Prefixed Tableaus and Nested Sequents

REPRESENTATION THEOREMS FOR IMPLICATION STRUCTURES

Equivalents of Mingle and Positive Paradox

Axiomatizing hybrid logic using modal logic

SHORTEST SINGLE AXIOMS FOR THE CLASSICAL EQUIVALENTIAL CALCULUS JEREMY GEORGE PETERSON

NONSTANDARD MODELS AND KRIPKE S PROOF OF THE GÖDEL THEOREM

SIMPLE DECISION PROCEDURE FOR S5 IN STANDARD CUT-FREE SEQUENT CALCULUS

Madhavan Mukund Chennai Mathematical Institute

Axiom schema of Markov s principle preserves disjunction and existence properties

An Introduction to Modal Logic V

Deductive Characterization of Logic

Introduction to Modal and Temporal Logic

Logics in Access Control: A Conditional Approach

SOME SEMANTICS FOR A LOGICAL LANGUAGE FOR THE GAME OF DOMINOES

Dynamic Semantics. Dynamic Semantics. Operational Semantics Axiomatic Semantics Denotational Semantic. Operational Semantics

AN AXIOMATIZATION OF HERZBERGER'S 2-DIMENSIONAL PRESUPPOSITIONAL SEMANTICS JOHN N. MARTIN

BETWEEN THE LOGIC OF PARMENIDES AND THE LOGIC OF LIAR

Inducing syntactic cut-elimination for indexed nested sequents

Systems of modal logic

Handout on Logic, Axiomatic Methods, and Proofs MATH Spring David C. Royster UNC Charlotte

Propositions and Proofs

First-Degree Entailment

References A CONSTRUCTIVE INTRODUCTION TO FIRST ORDER LOGIC. The Starting Point. Goals of foundational programmes for logic:

Multi-valued Semantics: Why and How

Proving Completeness for Nested Sequent Calculi 1

Formal Epistemology: Lecture Notes. Horacio Arló-Costa Carnegie Mellon University

On Urquhart s C Logic

Logics for Compact Hausdorff Spaces via de Vries Duality

Piotr Kulicki The Use of Axiomatic Rejection

Many-Valued Modal Logics

1. Algebra H-B-M-S- <A, 0, 1,,,,,, >

Axiomatisation of Hybrid Logic

Completeness through Flatness in Two-Dimensional Temporal Logic

1. Propositional Calculus

Propositional Logic Arguments (5A) Young W. Lim 11/8/16

DEFINITE DESCRIPTIONS: LANGUAGE, LOGIC, AND ELIMINATION

Applied Logic. Lecture 1 - Propositional logic. Marcin Szczuka. Institute of Informatics, The University of Warsaw

5-valued Non-deterministic Semantics for The Basic Paraconsistent Logic mci

Logic: Propositional Logic (Part I)

AN INTRODUCTION TO SEPARATION LOGIC. 2. Assertions

A proof of topological completeness for S4 in (0,1)

Epistemic Modals and Informational Consequence

Principles of Knowledge Representation and Reasoning

Canonical models for normal logics (Completeness via canonicity)

Propositional Logics and their Algebraic Equivalents

Introduction to Metalogic

Existence and Predication in Free Logics. Secretaria de Estado de Educação do Distrito Federal, Brasil

Lecture Notes on Kripke Semantics for Validity

Propositional Calculus - Hilbert system H Moonzoo Kim CS Division of EECS Dept. KAIST

Mathematical Logic. Introduction to Reasoning and Automated Reasoning. Hilbert-style Propositional Reasoning. Chiara Ghidini. FBK-IRST, Trento, Italy

The Modal Logic of Pure Provability

Yablo s Paradox and the Omitting Types Theorem for Propositional Languages

Philosophy 244: #14 Existence and Identity

Socratic Proofs for Some Temporal Logics RESEARCH REPORT

Introduction to Temporal Logic. The purpose of temporal logics is to specify properties of dynamic systems. These can be either

First-Order Logic First-Order Theories. Roopsha Samanta. Partly based on slides by Aaron Bradley and Isil Dillig

Modal logics: an introduction

Artificial Intelligence

Proof Theoretical Studies on Semilattice Relevant Logics

Symbolic Logic II Philosophy 520 Prof. Brandon Look. Final Exam

LOGIC OF CLASSICAL REFUTABILITY AND CLASS OF EXTENSIONS OF MINIMAL LOGIC

Chapter 11: Automated Proof Systems

First Order Logic: Syntax and Semantics

What if Every "If Only" Statement Were True?: The Logic of Counterfactuals

4 Kosta Do»sen models the modal relation will be as general as possible, and hence HK± 0 will be in the same position as the modal logic K based on th

Transcription:

Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic Volume V, Number 4, October 1964 299 Ki, K2 AND RELATED MODAL SYSTEMS. A. N. PRIOR 1. Sobociήski refers in [5] to two systems which he calls Kl and K2. If S4 is axiomatised with the rule to infer \~La, from \-a, these systems are axiomatisable by adding CLMpMLp and ELMpMLp respectively to S4. It is obvious that Kl is a subsystem of K2, since ELMpMLp is equivalent to CLMpMLp plus its converse CMLpLMp; Sobocinski, in conclusion, raises the question whether it is a "proper" subsystem. This question is equivalent to the question whether, given S4, CMLpLMp is independent of CLMpMLp. That it is, may be established by the following matrix: C\l 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 \N\ M\ L * 1 1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 8 1 1 2 1 1 3 3 5 5 7 7 7 2 6 3 1 2 1 2 5 6 5 6 6 3 7 4 1 1 1 1 5 5 5 5 5 4 8 5 1 2 3 4 1 2 3 4 4 1 5 6 1 1 3 3 1 1 3 3 3 2 6 7 1 2 1 2 1 2 1 2 2 3 7 8 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 8 8 This verifies S4 and CLMpMLp, but falsifies CMLpLMp when p = 2, 3, 6 or 7. The history of this matrix is worth giving, as it suggests solutions to certain connected problems. 2. In [3], [4] and other papers an interpretation is given for modal functors which may be re-stated, more in the spirit of [2], as follows: Use p, q, r, etc. for propositional variables and a, b, c, etc. for "worlds" or total states of affairs. Let U represent a certain relation between worlds, and write Tap for "It is the case in world a that/>". Assume, beside quantification theory and identity theory, the following: 1. ETANpNTap 2. ETaCpqCTapTaq 3. ETaLpUbCUabTbp From these, given Mp as short for NLNp, it is easy to deduce 4. ETaMpΣbKUabTbp Received September 25, 1964

300 A. N. PRIOR It is useful also to have a "world" -constant O (the "actual" world) such that 5. ETOpp. In a U-system, nothing but 3 is assumed for L, but there may be added to the above basis various special axioms for U, e.g. that it is reflexive (Uaa), that it is symmetrical {CUabUba), that it is transitive (CUabCUbcUac), that it is connected (CNUabUba). The effects of weakening certain of these special axioms in various ways are considered in [6]; and some effects of weakening the basic axioms 1 and 2 (e.g. the invalidation of the proof of 4 from 3), in [2]. To many ordinary modal calculi there correspond U-systems such that a formula 0 is a thesis of the modal calculus if and only if Taφ is a thesis of the corresponding U-system. Well-known results in this field (most of them obvious by-products of Kripke's [l]) are that the U-system in which the only special assumption about U is its reflexiveness corresponds to the modal system T; that that in which reflexiveness and transitiveness alone are assumed corresponds to S4; that in which reflexiveness and symmetry alone are assumed, to the "Brouwersche" system B (i.e. T plus CpLMp); reflexiveness, symmetry and transitiveness give S5; and transitiveness and connexity, S4.3. Sobociήski has noted (in [5], 3.3 and 4) that the distinctive axiom CMLpLMp of S4.2 is derivable in both S4.3 and B; this means, in view of the foregoing, that its U-counterpart should be provable equally from the symmetry and from the connexity of U. The proof from connexity is given in [3]; that from symmetry we give below. TaCMLpLMp expands to CΣbKUabUcCϋbcTcpUbCUabΣcKUbcTcp, which quantification theory equates to Π bdckuabkucc Ubc Tcp UadΣeKUde Tep, and this may be proved, assuming the symmetry of ϋ 9 as follows: TJbdCK (1) Uab K (2) UcCUbcTcp (3) Uad K (4) Uda [3; Symm] [1; Symm] K (5) Uba K (6) Tap [2; 5] (7) ΣeKUdeTep [4; 6]. Sobociήski's result, incidentally, shows that although the addition of LCMLpLMp to S3 results in the same system (S4.2) as its addition to S4, its addition to T, or the equivalent addition to T, (axiomatized with the rule to infer \-Lot from \-a) of CMLpLMp, does not yield S4.2 but a weaker system. For this system is contained in B, which does not contain S4. Whether the addition of the S4.3 formula A LCLpqLCLqp to T yields S4.3 or a weaker system will be considered below. 3. Returning to Kl and K2, what assumption about U would yield the U-counterpart of their distinctive formula CLMpMLpΊ One approach to this problem is via tense-logic. If we take the "worlds-variables α, δ, c,

Kl, K2 AND RELATED MODAL SYSTEMS 301 etc. to represent total states of the world at given moments of time, and Uab to mean that state b either is identical with state a or is one of its temporal successors, the difference between MLp and LMp will be that TaMLp means that, at a, it either is or will be the case that it is and always will be the case that p, while TaLMp means that, at a, it is and always will be the case that it either is or will be the case that/). If p is something which will for ever be the case intermittently (being the case for a time and then not being the case for a time), the second of these will be true but not the first. If, however, there is a last moment of time, both TaMLp and TaLMp will be true if and only if p is the case at that last moment, and so will be equivalent. We will therefore verify CLMpMLp as well as its converse if we assume time to have an end. With this intuitive background, it was shown in [3] that the U-counterpart of the system which Sobociήski names K2 (or of this at least; in fact we get K3 also this way) will be obtained if we assume for U, beside reflexiveness, transitiveness and connexity, the axiom "Fin", i.e. ΣbΠcCUbcIbc, "For some moment b, if any moment c is either identical with c or after it, it is identical with it", i.e. there is a moment which has no other moment after it. TaCLMpMLp was, however, only proved from Fin by assuming the connexity of U as well. With the time-series this is a plausible assumption but it is clear that this use of Fin will not help us to distinguish between Sobociήski's Kl and K2, since connexity also gives us TaCMLpLMp (and, indeed, TaALCLpqLCLqp ). If the U-system is not connected but has diverging branches, Fin only asserts that at least one branch has an end, and to prove TaCLMpMLp in a non-connected system, we must replace Fin by an assumption that will guarantee that every branch has an end, e.g. the assumption ΠaΣbKUabΠcCUbcIbc, "For all a, there is some b which is after abut has nothing else after it". And from this assumption, with transitiveness, we can prove TaCLMpMLp without using either symmetry or connexity, and without verifying the converse. A simple system embodying the required assumptions would be one represented by < where the arrows plus identity represent the U relation (i.e. the true elementary U-propositions are Uaa, Ubb, Ucc, Uab, Uac). If p is true at b only, MLp is true at a (because Lp is true at b) and LMp false there (because Mp is false at c). To show that this system verifies everything in Kl, we translate it into a matrix by representing the possible truth-values of p at α, 6, and c by the eight triads

302 A. N. PRIOR 1 1 0 0 1 1 0 0 1 1 1 1 0 0 0 0 1, 0, 1, 0, 1, 0, 1, 0, and working out the values of Mp, Lp, LMp y etc. from these, Mp having I at a given point if and only Mp has 1 either there or at a point to the right of it, and Lp having 0 at a given point if and only if p has 0 either there or at a point to the right of it. If we number the triads 1 to 8, we have the matrix used at the beginning. 4. Similar methods may be used to show that the addition of ALCLpqLCLqp to T instead of to S4 does not yield S4.3 but a weaker system. The problem here is to show that the connexity of?7does not prove its transitiveness. A non-transitive but connected system would be <! (i.e. we have Uab, Ubc, and Uca beside Uaa, Ubb and Ucc). So we use the same 8 triads as elements of our matrix, but specify Mp as having a 1 at a given point if and only if p has a 1 either at that point or at the next point clockwise round, and similarly with Lp and 0. This, when the triads are numbered in the same order as before, gives us the following valuations for M and L (C and Nbeing as before): p : 1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 Mp: 1 1 1 3 1 2 5 8 Lp: 1 4 7 8 6 8 8 8 The matrix verifies ALCLpqLCLqp (and, of course, the postulates of T) but falsifies CLpLLp where p = 2, 3 or 5. 5. Dummett and Lemmon's original axiom for S4.3 was ALCLpLqLCLqLp, the Dl of Sobocinski's [5]. That ALCLpqLCLqp, the D2 of [5], is equivalent given S4, to Dl, was first pointed out, so far as I know, by P. T. Geach in the late 1950's. (See [4], p. 139). At about the same time (this is also reported in [4]) yet another axiom was considered by Hintikka and shown to be equivalent, given S4, to D2; namely HI. CKMpMqAMKpMqMKqMp. Though longer than D2, this axiom, in its tense-logical interpretation, reflects more directly the connexity of the time-series. We show now that it is not only equivalent to D2 given S4, but also given the system T. In the first place it is equivalent, by simple transpositions and substitutions, to H2. CLCpLqCLCMpqCMpLq. From this we may prove D2 as follows:

Kl, K2 AND RELATED MODAL SYSTEMS 303 1. LCLpLCqp [T] 2. LCKLpNqLCLqp [l q/lq; LCKpqp] 3. LCKLqNpLCLpq [2p/Nq,q/p] 4. LCNLCLpqNKLqNp [3] 5. LCMKLpNqCLqp [4] 6. CMKLpNqLCLqp [H2 p/klpnq, q/clpq; 2; 5] Zλ2. ALCLpqLCLqp [6] Conversely, Iλ2is equivalent by simple transpositions and substitutions to what we may call D5. ALCpMqLCqMp, from which HI is derivable as follows: 1. CLCpMqLCpKpMq [T] 2. CLCpKpMqCMpMKpMq [T] 3. CLCpMqCMpMKpMq [1; 2] 4. CLCqMpCMqMKpMq [3p/q,q/p] HI. CKMpMqAMKpMqMKqMp [D5; 3; 4; P.C.] #i or #2 may therefore replace D2 not only in axiomatising S4.3 but also in axiomatising the system, which we may call T.3, which was shown in the last section to be a proper subsystem of S4.3. Using H2 9 it is easy to show that T.3 enriched with the "Brouwersche" axiom CpLMp (which with the rule of T to infer \-La from \-a is equivalent to LCpLMp) is equivalent, like S4 with the same enrichment, to S5. For if in H2 we put q/mp, its first antecedent becomes LCpLMp, its second LCMpMp, and its consequent CMpLMp. In the U-system, correspondingly, connexity and symmetry together (i.e. CNUabUba and CUabUba) turn U into an equivalence relation, since they turn it into the universal relation. 6. E. J. Lemmon has communicated to me a solution to a further problem raised by Sobocinski, namely whether K2 contains a further system in which it is certainly contained, namely K3, in which CLMpMLp is added not to S4.2 but to S4.3. This amounts to the question whether the formula ALCLpqLCLqp is independent of the postulates of K2. Lemmon points out that a postulate for U which (added to reflexiveness and transitiveness) will verify S4.3 but not S4.2 is that U is ''convergent," i.e. that even if the U- lines diverge at some point they eventually come together. The formula expressing this condition would be CKUabUacΣdKUbdUcd. The proof of CMLpLMp from this (for the preliminaries, see its proof from Symm in Section 2) would be UbdCK (1) Uab K (2) UcCUbcTcp (3) Uad ΣeK (4) Ube [l, Conv.] K (5) Ude [3, Conv.] K (6) Tep [2, 4] (Ί)KUdeTep [5,6].

304 A. N. PRIOR transitive, convergent and has an end- A simple system that is reflexive, point would be a< >d (where the true elementary U-formulae are Uaa, Ubb, Ucc, Udd, Uab, Ubd, Ucd, Uad). This suggests a 16-valued matrix in which the elements are such tetrads as 1 0 1 1 1 1 0 1 and Mp has a 1 where p has a 1 either there or at some point to the right, and L/>has a 0 where p has a 0 either there or at some point to the right. If p and q are respectively assigned the two values just used as illustrations, ALCLpqLCLqp takes the value 0 at the extreme left position* REFERENCES [l] S. A. Kripke, "Semantical Analysis of Modal Logic I", Zeitschrift fur mathematische Logik und Grundlagen der Mathematik, Vol. 9 (1963), pp. 67-96. [2] A. N. Prior, Time and Modality (Oxford, 1957). [3] A. N. Prior, "Possible Worlds", Philosophical Quarterly, January 1962, pp. 36-43. [4] A. N. Prior, "Tense-Logic and the Continuity of Time", Stadia Logica, Vol. 13 (1962), pp. 133-151. [5] B. Sobociήski, "Remarks about Axiom atiz at ions of Certain Modal Systems", Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic, Vol. 5, No. 1 (January 1964), pp. 71-80. [6] I. Thomas, "Ten Modal Models", The Journal of Symbolic Logic, Vol. 29, No. 3 (September 1964), pp. 125-128. Manchester University Manchester, England