CHAPTER 3. Sequences. 1. Basic Properties

Similar documents
CHAPTER 4. Series. 1. What is a Series?

Sequences. Chapter 3. n + 1 3n + 2 sin n n. 3. lim (ln(n + 1) ln n) 1. lim. 2. lim. 4. lim (1 + n)1/n. Answers: 1. 1/3; 2. 0; 3. 0; 4. 1.

We are going to discuss what it means for a sequence to converge in three stages: First, we define what it means for a sequence to converge to zero

CHAPTER 5. The Topology of R. 1. Open and Closed Sets

Limits and Continuity

CHAPTER 6. Limits of Functions. 1. Basic Definitions

Infinite Sequences of Real Numbers (AKA ordered lists) DEF. An infinite sequence of real numbers is a function f : N R.

MATH 409 Advanced Calculus I Lecture 7: Monotone sequences. The Bolzano-Weierstrass theorem.

MATH 117 LECTURE NOTES

Sequences of Real Numbers

Homework 4, 5, 6 Solutions. > 0, and so a n 0 = n + 1 n = ( n+1 n)( n+1+ n) 1 if n is odd 1/n if n is even diverges.

2.1 Convergence of Sequences

Math 324 Summer 2012 Elementary Number Theory Notes on Mathematical Induction

Math 117: Topology of the Real Numbers

Copyright 2010 Pearson Education, Inc. Publishing as Prentice Hall.

Math LM (24543) Lectures 01

MATH31011/MATH41011/MATH61011: FOURIER ANALYSIS AND LEBESGUE INTEGRATION. Chapter 2: Countability and Cantor Sets

An analogy from Calculus: limits

Continuity. Chapter 4

MA103 Introduction to Abstract Mathematics Second part, Analysis and Algebra

Limit and Continuity

Chapter 1 The Real Numbers

Logical Connectives and Quantifiers

A LITTLE REAL ANALYSIS AND TOPOLOGY

We have been going places in the car of calculus for years, but this analysis course is about how the car actually works.

Numerical Sequences and Series

Some Background Material

MATH 324 Summer 2011 Elementary Number Theory. Notes on Mathematical Induction. Recall the following axiom for the set of integers.

Chapter 11 - Sequences and Series

Continuity. Chapter 4

Math 117: Infinite Sequences

Real Analysis - Notes and After Notes Fall 2008

Undergraduate Notes in Mathematics. Arkansas Tech University Department of Mathematics

Algorithms: Lecture 2

MATH 301 INTRO TO ANALYSIS FALL 2016

M17 MAT25-21 HOMEWORK 6

Calculus (Real Analysis I)

Notes for Math 290 using Introduction to Mathematical Proofs by Charles E. Roberts, Jr.

1. Supremum and Infimum Remark: In this sections, all the subsets of R are assumed to be nonempty.

Contents Ordered Fields... 2 Ordered sets and fields... 2 Construction of the Reals 1: Dedekind Cuts... 2 Metric Spaces... 3

1. Theorem. (Archimedean Property) Let x be any real number. There exists a positive integer n greater than x.

Introductory Analysis I Fall 2014 Homework #9 Due: Wednesday, November 19

Solutions to Homework Assignment 2

INTRODUCTION TO REAL ANALYSIS II MATH 4332 BLECHER NOTES

Similar to sequence, note that a series converges if and only if its tail converges, that is, r 1 r ( 1 < r < 1), ( 1) k k. r k =

Subsequences and the Bolzano-Weierstrass Theorem

CHAPTER 8: EXPLORING R

MAT115A-21 COMPLETE LECTURE NOTES

Seunghee Ye Ma 8: Week 2 Oct 6

INFINITE SEQUENCES AND SERIES

Proof Techniques (Review of Math 271)

Week 2: Sequences and Series

Math 101: Course Summary

MATH 101, FALL 2018: SUPPLEMENTARY NOTES ON THE REAL LINE

Writing proofs for MATH 51H Section 2: Set theory, proofs of existential statements, proofs of uniqueness statements, proof by cases

MA131 - Analysis 1. Workbook 6 Completeness II

5 Set Operations, Functions, and Counting

Building Infinite Processes from Finite-Dimensional Distributions

Introduction to Real Analysis

Section 4.1: Sequences and Series

Warm-up Quantifiers and the harmonic series Sets Second warmup Induction Bijections. Writing more proofs. Misha Lavrov

REVIEW OF ESSENTIAL MATH 346 TOPICS

4.3 Limit of a Sequence: Theorems

Mathematics 242 Principles of Analysis Solutions for Problem Set 5 Due: March 15, 2013

. Get closed expressions for the following subsequences and decide if they converge. (1) a n+1 = (2) a 2n = (3) a 2n+1 = (4) a n 2 = (5) b n+1 =

Sequence convergence, the weak T-axioms, and first countability

Advanced Calculus: MATH 410 Real Numbers Professor David Levermore 5 December 2010

Lecture 3 - Tuesday July 5th

means is a subset of. So we say A B for sets A and B if x A we have x B holds. BY CONTRAST, a S means that a is a member of S.

Sequences and infinite series

4.4 Uniform Convergence of Sequences of Functions and the Derivative

a 2n = . On the other hand, the subsequence a 2n+1 =

Sequences. Limits of Sequences. Definition. A real-valued sequence s is any function s : N R.

Read carefully the instructions on the answer book and make sure that the particulars required are entered on each answer book.

Chapter 11: Sequences; Indeterminate Forms; Improper Integrals

Construction of a general measure structure

Higher-Order Equations: Extending First-Order Concepts

Sequences CHAPTER 3. Definition. A sequence is a function f : N R.

We are now going to go back to the concept of sequences, and look at some properties of sequences in R

Quick Tour of the Topology of R. Steven Hurder, Dave Marker, & John Wood 1

Connectedness. Proposition 2.2. The following are equivalent for a topological space (X, T ).

EECS 1028 M: Discrete Mathematics for Engineers

MATH1050 Greatest/least element, upper/lower bound

MATH3283W LECTURE NOTES: WEEK 6 = 5 13, = 2 5, 1 13

Mini-Course on Limits and Sequences. Peter Kwadwo Asante. B.S., Kwame Nkrumah University of Science and Technology, Ghana, 2014 A REPORT

ADVANCED CALCULUS - MTH433 LECTURE 4 - FINITE AND INFINITE SETS

8.5 Taylor Polynomials and Taylor Series

3 Integration and Expectation

SECTION 9.2: ARITHMETIC SEQUENCES and PARTIAL SUMS

Definitions & Theorems

Mathematical induction. Limits of sequences

Spaces of continuous functions

5.4 Continuity: Preliminary Notions

Analysis Finite and Infinite Sets The Real Numbers The Cantor Set

CSCE 222 Discrete Structures for Computing. Dr. Hyunyoung Lee

Homework 1 Solutions

Notes on arithmetic. 1. Representation in base B

1 The topology of metric spaces

106 CHAPTER 3. TOPOLOGY OF THE REAL LINE. 2. The set of limit points of a set S is denoted L (S)

Principle of Mathematical Induction

Transcription:

CHAPTER 3 Sequences We begin our study of analysis with sequences. There are several reasons for starting here. First, sequences are the simplest way to introduce limits, the central idea of calculus. Second, sequences are a direct route to the topology of the real numbers. The combination of limits and topology provides the tools to finally prove the theorems you ve already used in your calculus course.. Basic Properties DEFINITION 3.. A sequence is a function a : N! R. Instead of using the standard function notation of a(n) for sequences, it is usually more convenient to write the argument of the function as a subscript, a n. EXAMPLE 3.. Let the sequence a n = /n. The first three elements are a = 0, a 2 = /2, a 3 = 2/3, etc. EXAMPLE 3.2. Let the sequence b n = 2 n. Then b = 2, b 2 = 4, b 3 = 8, etc. EXAMPLE 3.3. Let the sequence c n = 00 5n so c = 95, c 2 = 90, c 3 = 85, etc. EXAMPLE 3.4. If a and r are constants, then a sequence given by c = a, c 2 = ar, c 3 = ar 2 and in general c n = ar n is called a geometric sequence. The number r is called the ratio of the sequence. Staying away from the trivial cases where a = 0 or r = 0, a geometric sequence can always be recognized by noticing that c n+ c n = r for all n 2 N. Example 3.2 is a geometric sequence with a = r = 2. EXAMPLE 3.5. If a and d are constants, then a sequence of the form d n = a + (n )d is called an arithmetic sequence. Another way of looking at this is that d n is an arithmetic sequence if d n+ d n = d for all n 2 N. Example 3.3 is an arithmetic sequence with a = 95 and d = 5. EXAMPLE 3.6. Some sequences are not defined by an explicit formula, but are defined recursively. This is an inductive method of definition in which successive terms of the sequence are defined by using other terms of the sequence. The most famous of these is the Fibonacci sequence. To define the Fibonacci sequence, f n, let f = 0, f 2 = and for n > 2, let f n = f n 2 + f n. The first few terms are 0,,,2,3,5,8,... There actually is a simple formula that directly gives f n, and its derivation is Exercise 3.6. 3-

3-2 CHAPTER 3. SEQUENCES EXAMPLE 3.7. These simple definitions can lead to complex problems. One famous case is a hailstone sequence. Let h be any natural number. For n >, recursively define ( 3hn +, if h n is odd h n = h n /2, if h n is even. Lothar Collatz conjectured in 937 that any hailstone sequence eventually settles down to repeating the pattern,4,2,,4,2,. Many people have tried to prove this and all have failed. It s often inconvenient for the domain of a sequence to be N, as required by Definition 3.. For example, the sequence beginning, 2, 4, 8,... can be written 2 0,2,2 2,2 3,... Written this way, it s natural to let the sequence function be 2 n with domain!. As long as there is a simple substitution to write the sequence function in the form of Definition 3., there s no reason to adhere to the letter of the law. In general, the domain of a sequence can be any set of the form {n 2 Z : n N} for some N 2 Z. DEFINITION 3.2. A sequence a n is bounded if {a n : n 2 N} is a bounded set. This definition is extended in the obvious way to bounded above and bounded below. The sequence of Example 3. is bounded, but the sequence of Example 3.2 is not, although it is bounded below. DEFINITION 3.3. A sequence a n converges to L 2 R if for all " > 0 there exists an N 2 N such that whenever n N, then a n L <". If a sequence does not converge, then it is said to diverge. When a n converges to L, we write lim n! a n = L, or often, more simply, a n! L. EXAMPLE 3.8. Let a n = /n be as in Example 3.. We claim a n!. To see this, let " > 0 and choose N 2 N such that /N < ". Then, if n N so a n!. a n = ( /n) =/n /N < ", EXAMPLE 3.9. The sequence b n = 2 n of Example 3.2 diverges. To see this, suppose not. Then there is an L 2 R such that b n! L. If" =, there must be an N 2 N such that b n L <" whenever n N. Choose n N. L 2 n < implies L < 2 n +. But, then b n+ L = 2 n+ L > 2 n+ (2 n + ) = 2 n = ". This violates the condition on N. We conclude that for every L 2 R there exists an " > 0 such that for no N 2 N is it true that whenever n N, then b n L <". Therefore, b n diverges. DEFINITION 3.4. A sequence a n diverges to if for every B > 0 there is an N 2 N such that n N implies a n > B. The sequence a n is said to diverge to if a n diverges to.

. BASIC PROPERTIES 3-3 When a n diverges to, we write lim n! a n =, or often, more simply, a n!. A common mistake is to forget that a n!actually means the sequence diverges in a particular way. Don t be fooled by the suggestive notation into treating as a number! EXAMPLE 3.0. It is easy to prove that the sequence a n = 2 n of Example 3.2 diverges to. THEOREM 3.5. If a n! L, then L is unique. PROOF. Suppose a n! L and a n! L 2. Let " > 0. According to Definition 3.2, there exist N, N 2 2 N such that n N implies a n L <"/2 and n N 2 implies a n L 2 <"/2. Set N = max{n, N 2 }. If n N, then L L 2 = L a n + a n L 2 L a n + a n L 2 <"/2 + "/2 = ". Since " is an arbitrary positive number an application of Exercise 2.2 shows L = L 2. THEOREM 3.6. a n! L iff for all " > 0, the set {n : a n (L ",L + ")} is finite. PROOF. ()) Let " > 0. According to Definition 3.2, there is an N 2 N such that {a n : n N} Ω (L ",L + "). Then {n : a n (L ",L + ")} Ω {,2,...,N }, which is finite. (() Let " > 0. By assumption {n : a n (L ",L +")} is finite, so let N = max{n : a n (L ",L+")}+. If n N, then a n 2 (L ",L+"). By Definition 3.2, a n! L. COROLLARY 3.7. If a n converges, then a n is bounded. PROOF. Suppose a n! L. According to Theorem 3.6 there are a finite number of terms of the sequence lying outside (L,L+). Since any finite set is bounded, the conclusion follows. The converse of this theorem is not true. For example, a n = ( ) n is bounded, but does not converge. The main use of Corollary 3.7 is as a quick first check to see whether a sequence might converge. It s usually pretty easy to determine whether a sequence is bounded. If it isn t, it must diverge. The following theorem lets us analyze some complicated sequences by breaking them down into combinations of simpler sequences. THEOREM 3.8. Let a n and b n be sequences such that a n! A and b n! B. Then (a) a n + b n! A + B, (b) a n b n! AB, and (c) a n /b n! A/B as long as b n 6= 0 for all n 2 N and B 6= 0. PROOF. (a) Let " > 0. There are N, N 2 2 N such that n N implies a n A <"/2 and n N 2 implies b n B <"/2. Define N = max{n, N 2 }. If n N, then (a n + b n ) (A + B) a n A + b n B <"/2 + "/2 = ".

3-4 CHAPTER 3. SEQUENCES Therefore a n + b n! A + B. (b) Let " > 0 and Æ > 0 be an upper bound for a n. Choose N, N 2 2 N such that n N =) a n A <"/2( B +) and n N 2 =) b n B <"/2Æ. If n N = max{n, N 2 }, then a n b n AB = a n b n a n B + a n B AB a n b n a n B + a n B AB = a n b n B + B a n A < Æ " 2Æ + B " 2( B +) < "/2 + "/2 = ". (c) First, notice that it suffices to show that /b n! /B, because part (b) of this theorem can be used to achieve the full result. Let " > 0. Choose N 2 N so that the following two conditions are satisfied: n N =) b n > B /2 and b n B <B 2 "/2. Then, when n N, Ø Ø Ø ØØØ b n B Ø = B b n ØØØ b n B Ø < B 2 "/2 (B/2)B Ø = ". Therefore /b n! /B. If you re not careful, you can easily read too much into the previous theorem and try to use its converse. Consider the sequences a n = ( ) n and b n = a n. Their sum, a n + b n = 0, product a n b n = and quotient a n /b n = all converge, but the original sequences diverge. It is often easier to prove that a sequence converges by comparing it with a known sequence than it is to analyze it directly. For example, a sequence such as a n = sin 2 n/n 3 can easily be seen to converge to 0 because it is dominated by /n 3. The following theorem makes this idea more precise. It s called the Sandwich Theorem here, but is also called the Squeeze, Pinching, Pliers or Comparison Theorem in different texts. THEOREM 3.9 (Sandwich Theorem). Suppose a n, b n and c n are sequences such that a n b n c n for all n 2 N. (a) If a n! L and c n! L, then b n! L. (b) If b n!, then c n!. (c) If b n!, then a n!. (a) Let " > 0. There is an N 2 N large enough so that when n N, then L " < a n and c n < L + ". These inequalities imply L " < a n b n c n < L + ". Theorem 3.6 shows b n! L. (b) Let B > 0 and choose N 2 N so that n N =) b n > B. Then c n b n > B whenever n N. This shows c n!. (c) This is essentially the same as part (b). PROOF.

2. MONOTONE SEQUENCES 3-5 2. Monotone Sequences One of the problems with using the definition of convergence to prove a given sequence converges is the limit of the sequence must be known in order to verify the sequence converges. This gives rise in the best cases to a chicken and egg problem of somehow determining the limit before you even know the sequence converges. In the worst case, there is no nice representation of the limit to use, so you don t even have a target to shoot at. The next few sections are ultimately concerned with removing this deficiency from Definition 3.2, but some interesting side-issues are explored along the way. Not surprisingly, we begin with the simplest case. DEFINITION 3.0. A sequence a n is increasing, if a n+ a n for all n 2 N. It is strictly increasing if a n+ > a n for all n 2 N. A sequence a n is decreasing, if a n+ a n for all n 2 N. It is strictly decreasing if a n+ < a n for all n 2 N. If a n is any of the four types listed above, then it is said to be a monotone sequence. Notice the and in the definitions of increasing and decreasing sequences, respectively. Many calculus texts use strict inequalities because they seem to better match the intuitive idea of what an increasing or decreasing sequence should do. For us, the non-strict inequalities are more convenient. THEOREM 3.. A bounded monotone sequence converges. PROOF. Suppose a n is a bounded increasing sequence, L = lub{a n : n 2 N} and " > 0. Clearly, a n L for all n 2 N. According to Theorem 2.9, there exists an N 2 N such that a N > L ". Because the sequence is increasing, L a n a N > L " for all n N. This shows a n! L. If a n is decreasing, let b n = a n and apply the preceding argument. The key idea of this proof is the existence of the least upper bound of the sequence when the range of the sequence is viewed as a set of numbers. This means the Completeness Axiom implies Theorem 3.. In fact, it isn t hard to prove Theorem 3. also implies the Completeness Axiom, showing they are equivalent statements. Because of this, Theorem 3. is often used as the Completeness Axiom on R instead of the least upper bound property we used in Axiom 8. EXAMPLE 3.. The sequence e n = + n n converges. Looking at the first few terms of this sequence, e = 2, e 2 = 2.25, e 3 º 2.37, e 4 º 2.44, it seems to be increasing. To show this is indeed the case, fix n 2 N and use the binomial theorem to expand the product as! nx n (3.) e n = k k=0 n k

3-6 CHAPTER 3. SEQUENCES and (3.2) e n+ = n+ X k=0 For k n, the kth term of (3.) is! n + k (n + ) k.! n n(n )(n 2) (n (k )) = k nk k!n k = n n 2 n k + k! n n n = µ µ 2 µ k k! n n n < µ µ 2 µ k k! n + n + n + = n µ µ n n + (k ) k! n + n + n + (n + )n(n )(n 2) (n + (k )) = k!(n + )! k n + = k (n + ) k, which is the kth term of (3.2). Since (3.2) also has one more positive term in the sum, it follows that e n < e n+, and the sequence e n is increasing. Noting that /k! /2 k for k 2 N, we can bound the kth term of (3.).! n k n k = n! k!(n k)! n k = n n 2 n k + n n n < k! 2 k. Substituting this into (3.) yields! nx n e n = k so e n is bounded. k=0 n k < + + 2 + 4 + + 2 n = + 2 n < 3, 2 k!

3. SUBSEQUENCES AND THE BOLZANO-WEIERSTRASS THEOREM 3-7 Since e n is increasing and bounded, Theorem 3. implies e n converges. Of course, you probably remember from your calculus course that e n! e º 2.7828. THEOREM 3.2. An unbounded monotone sequence diverges to or, depending on whether it is increasing or decreasing, respectively. PROOF. Suppose a n is increasing and unbounded. If B > 0, the fact that a n is unbounded yields an N 2 N such that a N > B. Since a n is increasing, a n a N > B for all n N. This shows a n!. The proof when the sequence decreases is similar. 3. Subsequences and the Bolzano-Weierstrass Theorem DEFINITION 3.3. Let a n be a sequence and æ : N! N be a function such that m < n implies æ(m) < æ(n); i.e., æ is a strictly increasing sequence of natural numbers. Then b n = a ± æ(n) = a æ(n) is a subsequence of a n. The idea here is that the subsequence b n is a new sequence formed from an old sequence a n by possibly leaving terms out of a n. In other words, all the terms of b n must also appear in a n, and they must appear in the same order. EXAMPLE 3.2. Let æ(n) = 3n and a n be a sequence. Then the subsequence a æ(n) looks like a 3, a 6, a 9,...,a 3n,... The subsequence has every third term of the original sequence. EXAMPLE 3.3. If a n = sin(nº/2), then some possible subsequences are b n = a 4n+ =) b n =, and c n = a 2n =) c n = 0, d n = a n 2 =) d n = ( + ( ) n+ )/2. THEOREM 3.4. a n! L iff every subsequence of a n converges to L. PROOF. ()) Suppose æ : N! N is strictly increasing, as in the preceding definition. With a simple induction argument, it can be seen that æ(n) n for all n. (See Exercise 3.8.) Now, suppose a n! L and b n = a æ(n) is a subsequence of a n.if" > 0, there is an N 2 N such that n N implies a n 2 (L ",L + "). From the preceding paragraph, it follows that when n N, then b n = a æ(n) = a m for some m n. So, b n 2 (L ",L + ") and b n! L. (() Since a n is a subsequence of itself, it is obvious that a n! L. The main use of Theorem 3.4 is not to show that sequences converge, but, rather to show they diverge. It gives two strategies for doing this: find two subsequences converging to different limits, or find a divergent subsequence. In Example 3.3, the subsequences b n and c n demonstrate the first strategy, while d n demonstrates the second.

3-8 CHAPTER 3. SEQUENCES Even if a given sequence is badly behaved, it is possible there are well-behaved subsequences. For example, consider the divergent sequence a n = ( ) n. In this case, a n diverges, but the two subsequences a 2n = and a 2n+ = are constant sequences, so they converge. THEOREM 3.5. Every sequence has a monotone subsequence. PROOF. Let a n be a sequence and T = {n 2 N : m > n =) a m a n }. There are two cases to consider, depending on whether T is finite. First, assume T is infinite. Define æ() = mint and assuming æ(n) is defined, set æ(n + ) = mint \{æ(),æ(2),...,æ(n)}. This inductively defines a strictly increasing function æ : N! N. The definition of T guarantees a æ(n) is an increasing subsequence of a n. Now, assume T is finite. Let æ() = max T +. If æ(n) has been chosen for some n > maxt, then the definition of T implies there is an m > æ(n) such that a m a æ(n). Set æ(n + ) = m. This inductively defines the strictly increasing function æ : N! N such that a æ(n) is a decreasing subsequence of a n. If the sequence in Theorem 3.5 is bounded, then the corresponding monotone subsequence is also bounded. Recalling Theorem 3., we arrive at the following famous theorem. THEOREM 3.6 (Bolzano-Weierstrass). Every bounded sequence has a convergent subsequence. 4. Lower and Upper Limits of a Sequence There are an uncountable number of strictly increasing functions æ : N! N, so every sequence a n has an uncountable number of subsequences. If a n converges, then Theorem 3.4 shows all of these subsequences converge to the same limit. It s also apparent that when a n!or a n!, then all its subsequences diverge in the same way. When a n does not converge or diverge to ±, the situation is a bit more difficult because some subsequences may converge and others may diverge. EXAMPLE 3.4. Let Q = {q n : n 2 N} and Æ 2 R. Since every interval contains an infinite number of rational numbers, it is possible to choose æ() = min{k : q k Æ <}. In general, assuming æ(n) has been chosen, choose æ(n + ) = min{k > æ(n): q k Æ </n}. Such a choice is always possible because Q \ (Æ /n,æ+/n)\{q k : k æ(n)} is infinite. This induction yields a subsequence q æ(n) of q n converging to Æ. If a n is a sequence and b n is a convergent subsequence of a n with b n! L, then L is called an accumulation point of a n. A convergent sequence has only one accumulation point, but a divergent sequence may have many accumulation points. As seen in Example 3.4, a sequence may have all of R as its set of accumulation points.

4. LOWER AND UPPER LIMITS OF A SEQUENCE 3-9 To make some sense out of this, suppose a n is a bounded sequence, and T n = {a k : k n}. Define `n = glbt n and µ n = lubt n. Because T n æ T n+, it follows that for all n 2 N, (3.3) ` `n `n+ µ n+ µ n µ. This shows `n is an increasing sequence bounded above by µ and µ n is a decreasing sequence bounded below by `. Theorem 3. implies both `n and µ n converge. If `n! ` and µ n! µ,(3.3) shows for all n, (3.4) `n ` µ µ n. Suppose b n! Ø is any convergent subsequence of a n. From the definitions of `n and µ n, it is seen that `n b n µ n for all n. Now(3.4) shows ` Ø µ. The normal terminology for ` and µ is given by the following definition. DEFINITION 3.7. Let a n be a sequence. If a n is bounded below, then the lower limit of a n is liminf a n = lim n! glb{a k : k n}. If a n is bounded above, then the upper limit of a n is limsup a n = lim n! lub{a k : k n}. When a n is unbounded, the lower and upper limits are set to appropriate infinite values, while recalling the familiar warnings about not being a number. Then and So, EXAMPLE 3.5. Define a n = µ n = lub{a k : k n} = `n = glb{a k : k n} = ( 2 + /n, n odd /n, n even. ( 2 + /n, n odd 2 + /(n + ), n even # 2 ( /n, n even /(n + ), n odd ". limsup a n = 2 > = liminf a n. Suppose a n is bounded above with T n, µ n and µ as in the discussion preceding the definition. We claim there is a subsequence of a n converging to limsup a n. The subsequence will be selected by induction. Choose æ() 2 N such that a æ() > µ. Suppose æ(n) has been selected for some n 2 N. Since µ æ(n)+ = lubt æ(n)+, there must be an a m 2 T æ(n)+ such that a m > µ æ(n)+ /(n + ). Then m > æ(n) and we set æ(n + ) = m.

3-0 CHAPTER 3. SEQUENCES This inductively defines a subsequence a æ(n), where (3.5) µ æ(n) µ æ(n)+ a æ(n) > µ æ(n)+ n +. for all n. The left and right sides of (3.5) both converge to limsup a n, so the Squeeze Theorem implies a æ(n)! limsup a n. In the cases when limsup a n =and limsup a n =, it is left to the reader to show there is a subsequence b n! limsup a n. Similar arguments can be made for liminf a n. Assuming æ(n) has been chosen for some n 2 N, To summarize: If Ø is an accumulation point of a n, then liminf a n Ø limsup a n. In case a n is bounded, both liminf a n and limsup a n are accumulation points of a n and a n converges iff liminf a n = lim n! a n = limsup a n. The following theorem has been proved. THEOREM 3.8. Let a n be a sequence. (a) There are subsequences of a n converging to liminf a n and limsup a n. (b) If Æ is an accumulation point of a n, then liminf a n Æ limsup a n. (c) liminf a n = limsup a n 2 R iff a n converges. 5. The Nested Interval Theorem DEFINITION 3.9. A collection of sets {S n : n 2 N} is said to be nested, if S n+ Ω S n for all n 2 N. THEOREM 3.20 (Nested Interval Theorem). If {I n = [a n,b n ]:n 2 N} is a nested collection of closed intervals such that lim n! (b n a n ) = 0, then there is an x 2 R such that T n2n I n = {x}. PROOF. Since the intervals are nested, it s clear that a n is an increasing sequence bounded above by b and b n is a decreasing sequence bounded below by a. Applying Theorem 3. twice, we find there are Æ,Ø 2 R such that a n! Æ and b n! Ø. We claim Æ = Ø. To see this, let " > 0 and use the shrinking condition on the intervals to pick N 2 N so that b N a N < ". The nestedness of the intervals implies a N a n < b n b N for all n N. Therefore a N lub{a n : n N} = Æ b N and a N glb{b n : n N} = Ø b N. This shows Æ Ø b N a N <". Since " > 0 was chosen arbitrarily, we conclude Æ = Ø. Let x = Æ = Ø. It remains to show that T n2n I n = {x}. First, we show that x 2 T n2n I n. To do this, fix N 2 N. Since a n increases to x, it s clear that x a N. Similarly, x b N. Therefore x 2 [a N,b N ]. Because N was chosen arbitrarily, it follows that x 2 T n2n I n. Next, suppose there are x, y 2 T n2n I n and let " > 0. Choose N 2 N such that b N a N < ". Then {x, y} Ω T n2n I n Ω [a N,b N ] implies x y <". Since " was chosen arbitrarily, we see x = y. Therefore T n2n I n = {x}.

3: Cauchy Sequences 3- EXAMPLE 3.6. If I n = (0,/n] for all n 2 N, then the collection {I n : n 2 N} is nested, but T n2n I n =;. This shows the assumption that the intervals be closed in the Nested Interval Theorem is necessary. EXAMPLE 3.7. If I n = [n,) then the collection {I n : n 2 N} is nested, but T n2n I n =;. This shows the assumption that the lengths of the intervals be bounded is necessary. (It will be shown in Corollary 5. that when their lengths don t go to 0, then the intersection is nonempty, but the uniqueness of x is lost.) 6. Cauchy Sequences Often the biggest problem with showing that a sequence converges using the techniques we have seen so far is we must know ahead of time to what it converges. This is the chicken and egg problem mentioned above. An escape from this dilemma is provided by Cauchy sequences. DEFINITION 3.2. A sequence a n is a Cauchy sequence if for all " > 0 there is an N 2 N such that n,m N implies a n a m <". This definition is a bit more subtle than it might at first appear. It sort of says that all the terms of the sequence are close together from some point onward. The emphasis is on all the terms from some point onward. To stress this, first consider a negative example. EXAMPLE 3.8. Suppose a n = P n /k for n 2 N. There s a trick for showing k= the sequence a n diverges. First, note that a n is strictly increasing. For any n 2 N, consider 2X n a 2 n = > k= n X n k = X 2X j j =0 k=0 2X j j =0 k=0 n 2 j + = X 2 j + k j =0 2 = n 2! Hence, the subsequence a 2 n is unbounded and the sequence a n diverges. (To see how this works, write out the first few sums of the form a 2 n.) On the other hand, a n+ a n =/(n + )! 0 and indeed, if m is fixed, a n+m a n!0. This makes it seem as though the terms are getting close together, as in the definition of a Cauchy sequence. But, a n is not a Cauchy sequence, as shown by the following theorem. THEOREM 3.22. A sequence converges iff it is a Cauchy sequence. PROOF. ()) Suppose a n! L and " > 0. There is an N 2 N such that n N implies a n L <"/2. If m,n N, then a m a n = a m L + L a n a m L + L a m <"/2 + "/2 = ". This shows a n is a Cauchy sequence. Lee Larson (Lee.Larson@Louisville.edu)

3-2 CHAPTER 3. SEQUENCES (() Let a n be a Cauchy sequence. First, we claim that a n is bounded. To see this, let " = and choose N 2 N such that n,m N implies a n a m <. In this case, a N < a n < a N + for all n N, so {a n : n N} is a bounded set. The set {a n : n < N}, being finite, is also bounded. Since {a n : n 2 N} is the union of these two bounded sets, it too must be bounded. Because a n is a bounded sequence, Theorem 3.6 implies it has a convergent subsequence b n = a æ(n)! L. Let " > 0 and choose N 2 N so that n,m N implies a n a m <"/2 and b n L <"/2. If n N, then æ(n) n N and a n L = a n b n + b n L a n b n + b n L = a n a æ(n) + b n L < "/2 + "/2 = ". Therefore, a n! L. The fact that Cauchy sequences converge is yet another equivalent version of completeness. In fact, most advanced texts define completeness as Cauchy sequences converge. This is convenient in general spaces because the definition of a Cauchy sequence only needs the metric on the space and none of its other structure. A typical example of the usefulness of Cauchy sequences is given below. DEFINITION 3.23. A sequence x n is contractive if there is a c 2 (0,) such that x k+ x k c x k x k for all k >. c is called the contraction constant. THEOREM 3.24. If a sequence is contractive, then it converges. PROOF. Let x k be a contractive sequence with contraction constant c 2 (0,). We first claim that if n 2 N, then (3.6) x n x n+ c n x x 2. This is proved by induction. When n =, the statement is x x 2 c 0 x x 2 = x x 2, which is trivially true. Suppose that x n x n+ c n x x 2 for some n 2 N. Then, from the definition of a contractive sequence and the induction hypothesis, x n+ x n+2 c x n x n+ c c n x x 2 = c n x x 2. This shows the claim is true in the case n +. Therefore, by induction, the claim is true for all n 2 N. To show x n is a Cauchy sequence, let " > 0. Since c n! 0, we can choose N 2 N so that (3.7) c N ( c) x x 2 <".

3: Cauchy Sequences 3-3 Let n > m N. Then x n x m = x n x n + x n x n 2 + x n 2 x m+ + x m+ x m x n x n + x n x n 2 + + x m+ x m Now, use (3.6) on each of these terms. c n 2 x x 2 +c n 3 x x 2 + +c m x x 2 = x x 2 (c n 2 + c n 3 + +c m ) Apply the formula for a geometric sum. (3.8) m cn m = x x 2 c c < x x 2 cm c Use (3.7) to estimate the following. x x 2 c N c " < x x 2 x x 2 = " This shows x n is a Cauchy sequence and must converge by Theorem 3.22. EXAMPLE 3.9. Let < r < and define the sequence s n = P n k=0 r k. (You no doubt recognize this as the geometric series from your calculus course.) If r = 0, the convergence of s n is trivial. So, suppose r 6= 0. In this case, s n+ s n s n s n = r n+ Ø r n Ø = r < and s n is contractive. Theorem 3.24 implies s n converges. EXAMPLE 3.20. Suppose f (x) = 2 + /x, a = 2 and a n+ = f (a n ) for n 2 N. It is evident that a n 2 for all n. Some algebra gives Ø a n+ a n ØØØ Ø a n a Ø = f (f (a n )) f (a n ) n f (a n ) a Ø = n + 2a n 5. This shows a n is a contractive sequence and, according to Theorem 3.24, a n! L for some L 2. Since, a n+ = 2 + /a n, taking the limit as n!of both sides gives L = 2 + /L. A bit more algebra shows L = + p 2. L is called a fixed point of the function f ; i.e. f (L) = L. Many approximation techniques for solving equations involve such iterative techniques depending upon contraction to find fixed points. The calculations in the proof of Theorem 3.24 give the means to approximate the fixed point to within an allowable error. Looking at line (3.8), notice x n x m < x x 2 cm c.

3-4 CHAPTER 3. SEQUENCES Let n!in this inequality to arrive at the error estimate (3.9) L x m x x 2 cm c. In Example 3.20, a = 2, a 2 = 5/2 and c /5. Suppose we want to approximate L to 5 decimal places of accuracy. It suffices to find n satisfying a n L <5 0 6. Using (3.9), with m = 9 shows a a 2 cm c.6 0 6. Some arithmetic gives a 9 º 2.442. The calculator value of confirming our estimate. L = + p 2 º 2.4423562, 7. Exercises 3.. Let the sequence a n = 6n. Use the definition of convergence for a 3n + 2 sequence to show a n converges. 3.2. If a n is a sequence such that a 2n! L and a 2n+! L, then a n! L. 3.3. Let a n be a sequence such that a 2n! A and a 2n a 2n! 0. Then a n! A. 3.4. If a n is a sequence of positive numbers converging to 0, then p a n! 0. 3.5. Find examples of sequences a n and b n such that a n! 0 and b n!such that (a) a n b n! 0 (b) a n b n! (c) lim n! a n b n does not exist, but a n b n is bounded. (d) Given c 2 R, a n b n! c. 3.6. If x n and y n are sequences such that lim n! x n = L 6= 0 and lim n! x n y n exists, then lim n! y n exists. 3.7. Determine the limit of a n = np n!. (Hint: If n is even, then n! > (n/2) n/2.) 3.8. If æ : N! N is strictly increasing, then æ(n) n for all n 2 N. 3.9. Analyze the sequence given by a n = P 2n k=n+ /k. 3.0. Every unbounded sequence contains a monotonic subsequence. 3.. Find a sequence a n such that given x 2 [0,], there is a subsequence b n of a n such that b n! x.

7. EXERCISES 3-5 3.2. A sequence a n converges to 0 iff a n converges to 0. 3.3. Define the sequence a n = p n for n 2 N. Show that a n+ a n!0, but a n is not a Cauchy sequence. 3.4. Suppose a sequence is defined by a = 0, a = and a n+ = 2 (a n + a n ) for n 2. Prove a n converges, and determine its limit. 3.5. If the sequence a n is defined recursively by a = and a n+ = p a n +, then show a n converges and determine its limit. 3.6. Let a = 3 and a n+ = 2 /x n for n 2 N. Analyze the sequence. 3.7. If a n is a sequence such that lim n! a n+ /a n =Ω <, then a n! 0. 3.8. Prove that the sequence a n = n 3 /n! converges. 3.9. Let a n and b n be sequences. Prove that both sequences a n and b n converge iff both a n + b n and a n b n converge. 3.20. Let a n be a bounded sequence. Prove that given any " > 0, there is an interval I with length " such that {n : a n 2 I } is infinite. Is it necessary that a n be bounded? 3.2. A sequence a n converges in the mean if a n = n P n k= a k converges. Prove that if a n! L, then a n! L, but the converse is not true. 3.22. Find a sequence x n such that for all n 2 N there is a subsequence of x n converging to n. 3.23. If a n is a Cauchy sequence whose terms are integers, what can you say about the sequence? 3.24. Show a n = P n /k! is a Cauchy sequence. k=0 3.25. If a n is a sequence such that every subsequence of a n has a further subsequence converging to L, then a n! L. 3.26. If a,b 2 (0,), then show np a n + b n! max{a,b}. 3.27. If 0 < Æ < and s n is a sequence satisfying s n+ <Æ s n, then s n! 0. 3.28. If c in the definition of a contractive sequence, can the sequence converge? 3.29. If a n is a convergent sequence and b n is a sequence such that a m a n b m b n for all m,n 2 N, then b n converges.

3-6 CHAPTER 3. SEQUENCES 3.30. If a n 0 for all n 2 N and a n! L, then p a n! p L. 3.3. If a n is a Cauchy sequence and b n is a subsequence of a n such that b n! L, then a n! L. 3.32. Let x = 3 and x n+ = 2 /x n for n 2 N. Analyze the sequence. 3.33. Let a n be a sequence. a n! L iff limsup a n = L = liminf a n. 3.34. Is limsup(a n + b n ) = limsup a n + limsupb n? 3.35. If a n is a sequence of positive numbers, then /liminf a n = limsup/a n. (Interpret /=0 and /0 =) 3.36. limsup(a n + b n ) limsup a n + limsupb n 3.37. a n = /n is not contractive. 3.38. The equation x 3 4x + 2 = 0 has one real root lying between 0 and. Find a sequence of rational numbers converging to this root. Use this sequence to approximate the root to five decimal places. 3.39. Approximate a solution of x 3 5x + = 0 to within 0 4 using a Cauchy sequence. 3.40. Prove or give a counterexample: If a n! L and æ : N! N is bijective, then b n = a æ(n) converges. Note that b n might not be a subsequence of a n. (b n is called a rearrangement of a n.)