A Local System for Classical Logic

Similar documents
Atomic Cut Elimination for Classical Logic

arxiv:math/ v1 [math.lo] 27 Jan 2003

A Local System for Linear Logic

System BV without the Equalities for Unit

Locality for Classical Logic

Cut Elimination inside a Deep Inference System for Classical Predicate Logic

Propositional Logic Language

Let us distinguish two kinds of annoying trivialities that occur in CoS derivations (the situation in the sequent calculus is even worse):

Proving Completeness for Nested Sequent Calculi 1

A Deep Inference System for the Modal Logic S5

Deep Sequent Systems for Modal Logic

First-Order Logic. Chapter Overview Syntax

SUBATOMIC LOGIC Alessio Guglielmi (TU Dresden) updated on

CHAPTER 10. Gentzen Style Proof Systems for Classical Logic

Chapter 11: Automated Proof Systems (1)

Prefixed Tableaus and Nested Sequents

Classical Propositional Logic

Introduction to Intuitionistic Logic

Chapter 11: Automated Proof Systems

Structures for Multiplicative Cyclic Linear Logic: Deepness vs Cyclicity

A Local System for Intuitionistic Logic

Canonical Calculi: Invertibility, Axiom expansion and (Non)-determinism

Deep Inference and Symmetry in Classical Proofs

Display calculi in non-classical logics

Propositional and Predicate Logic. jean/gbooks/logic.html

A CUT-FREE SIMPLE SEQUENT CALCULUS FOR MODAL LOGIC S5

An Introduction to Proof Theory

A Purely Logical Account of Sequentiality in Proof Search

Linear Logic Pages. Yves Lafont (last correction in 2017)

Natural Deduction for Propositional Logic

A Non-commutative Extension of MELL

3 Propositional Logic

Lecture Notes on Cut Elimination

INTERACTION AND DEPTH AGAINST NONDETERMINISM IN PROOF SEARCH

Introduction to Metalogic

LOGIC PROPOSITIONAL REASONING

Lecture Notes on Identity and Inversion

The Consistency and Complexity of. Multiplicative Additive System Virtual

Consequence Relations and Natural Deduction

TR : Binding Modalities

AN ALTERNATIVE NATURAL DEDUCTION FOR THE INTUITIONISTIC PROPOSITIONAL LOGIC

Lecture Notes on Sequent Calculus

Nested Sequent Calculi for Normal Conditional Logics

Notes on Inference and Deduction

From Frame Properties to Hypersequent Rules in Modal Logics

Chapter 3: Propositional Calculus: Deductive Systems. September 19, 2008

Maximal Introspection of Agents

The semantics of propositional logic

Non-classical Logics: Theory, Applications and Tools

Label-free Modular Systems for Classical and Intuitionistic Modal Logics

Natural Deduction. Formal Methods in Verification of Computer Systems Jeremy Johnson

General methods in proof theory for modal logic - Lecture 1

Inducing syntactic cut-elimination for indexed nested sequents

Propositional Logic Sequent Calculus

Mathematics for linguists

Warm-Up Problem. Is the following true or false? 1/35

Harvard School of Engineering and Applied Sciences CS 152: Programming Languages

Propositional Calculus - Soundness & Completeness of H

From pre-models to models

Přednáška 12. Důkazové kalkuly Kalkul Hilbertova typu. 11/29/2006 Hilbertův kalkul 1

Propositional Logic: Part II - Syntax & Proofs 0-0

Applied Logic for Computer Scientists. Answers to Some Exercises

Mathematics 114L Spring 2018 D.A. Martin. Mathematical Logic

cis32-ai lecture # 18 mon-3-apr-2006

Lecture Notes on Cut Elimination

Propositional Logic. Fall () Propositional Logic Fall / 30

First-order resolution for CTL

Part 1: Propositional Logic

7. Propositional Logic. Wolfram Burgard and Bernhard Nebel

Lecture Notes on From Rules to Propositions

Completeness Theorems and λ-calculus

Foundations of Artificial Intelligence

Tutorial on Mathematical Induction

Description Logics. Deduction in Propositional Logic. franconi. Enrico Franconi

Computational Logic. Davide Martinenghi. Spring Free University of Bozen-Bolzano. Computational Logic Davide Martinenghi (1/30)

Critical Reading of Optimization Methods for Logical Inference [1]

17.1 Correctness of First-Order Tableaux

Propositions and Proofs

Interpolation via translations

Truth, Subderivations and the Liar. Why Should I Care about the Liar Sentence? Uses of the Truth Concept - (i) Disquotation.

Propositional Logics and their Algebraic Equivalents

Formulas for which Contraction is Admissible

Krivine s Intuitionistic Proof of Classical Completeness (for countable languages)

NONSTANDARD MODELS AND KRIPKE S PROOF OF THE GÖDEL THEOREM

Plans as Formulae with a Non-commutative Logical Operator

Fundamentals of Logic

Predicate Logic - Deductive Systems

3 The Semantics of the Propositional Calculus

Partial Collapses of the Σ 1 Complexity Hierarchy in Models for Fragments of Bounded Arithmetic

Proof complexity of the cut-free calculus of structures

Multiplicative Conjunction and an Algebraic. Meaning of Contraction and Weakening. A. Avron. School of Mathematical Sciences

Clausal Presentation of Theories in Deduction Modulo

A Tableau Calculus for Minimal Modal Model Generation

Language of Propositional Logic

First-Order Logic First-Order Theories. Roopsha Samanta. Partly based on slides by Aaron Bradley and Isil Dillig

Foundations of Artificial Intelligence

Completeness in the Monadic Predicate Calculus. We have a system of eight rules of proof. Let's list them:

Hypersequent Calculi for some Intermediate Logics with Bounded Kripke Models

This is logically equivalent to the conjunction of the positive assertion Minimal Arithmetic and Representability

Propositional Logic: Evaluating the Formulas

Transcription:

A Local ystem for Classical Logic ai Brünnler 1 and Alwen Fernanto iu 1,2 kaibruennler@inftu-dresdende and tiu@csepsuedu 1 echnische Universität Dresden, Fakultät Informatik, D - 01062 Dresden, Germany 2 he Pennsylvania tate University, Department of Computer cience and Engineering, University Park, PA 16802 UA Abstract he calculus of structures is a framework for specifying logical systems, which is similar to the one-sided sequent calculus but more general We present a system of inference rules for propositional classical logic in this new framework and prove cut elimination for it he system enjoys a decomposition theorem for derivations that is not available in the sequent calculus he main novelty of our system is that all the rules are local: contraction, in particular, is reduced to atomic form his should be interesting for distributed proof-search and also for complexity theory, since the computational cost of applying each rule is bounded 1 Introduction When implementing inference systems, in a distributed fashion especially, the need to copy formulae of unbounded size is generally considered problematic In the sequent calculus, it is caused by the contraction rule, eg in Gentzen s L [2]: Γ Φ, A, A Γ Φ, A Here, going from bottom to top in constructing a proof, a formula A of unbounded size is duplicated Whatever mechanism performs this duplication, it has to inspect all of A, soithastohaveaglobal view on A While this can be taken for granted on a single processor system, it is harder to achieve on a distributed system, where each processor has a limited amount of local memory he formula A could be spread over a number of processors In that case, no single processor has a global view on A Let us call local those inference rules that do not require such a global view on formulae of unbounded size, and non-local those rules that do Besides contraction, another example of clearly non-local behaviour is provided by the promotion rule in the sequent calculus for linear logic [3] o remove an exclamation mark from one formula, it has to check whether all formulae in the context are prefixed with a question mark he number of formulae to check is unbounded: A,?B 1,,?B n!a,?b 1,,?B n

While there are methods to solve these problems in the implementation, an interesting question is whether it is possible to solve them proof-theoretically, ie by avoiding non-local rules altogether his question is answered positively in this paper for the case of classical propositional logic he predicative case is work in progress and is sketched in the conclusion Locality is achieved by reducing the problematic rules to their atomic forms his is not entirely new: there are sequent systems for classical logic in which the identity axiom is reduced to its atomic form, ie A A is admissible for a a, where a is an atom However, we do not know of any sequent system in which contraction and weakening are admissible for their atomic forms In fact, we believe that such a system does not exist o achieve our goal, we depart from the sequent calculus and employ the recently conceived calculus of structures [5] In contrast to the sequent calculus, it does not rely on the notion of main connective and permits the application of rules anywhere deep inside a formula, exploiting the fact that implication is closed under disjunction and conjunction his ability is crucial for the rules of our system he calculus of structures has already successfully been employed in [7] to solve the problem of the non-local behaviour of the promotion rule his paper is structured as follows: first, we introduce basic notions of the calculus of structures hen we present our system, named, and argue that its rules are local We prove that it is equivalent to the Gentzen-chütte formulation of classical logic, prove cut elimination and state two decomposition theorems for derivations In the end, some open problems are identified 2 tructures and Derivations Definition 21 here are infinitely many literals Literals, positive or negative, are denoted by a, b, here are two special literals, true and false, denoted t and f hestructures of the language are generated by ::= a [,,] (,,) }{{}}{{}, >0 >0 where [ 1,, h ]isadisjunction and ( 1,, h )isaconjunction is the negation of the structure tructures are denoted by, P, Q,,, U, V and W tructures with a hole that does not appear in the scope of a negation are denoted by { } he structure is a substructure of {}, and{ } is its context We simplify the indication of context in cases where structural parentheses fill the hole exactly: for example, [, ] stands for {[, ]} tructures are considered to be syntactically equivalent modulo the relation =, which is the smallest congruence relation induced by the equations shown in Fig 1, where and stand for finite, non-empty sequences of structures

Associativity [, [ ]] = [, ] (, ( )) = (, ) Commutativity [, ]=[, ] (, )=(, ) ingleton [] = =() Constants Negation [f, ] =[] (t, ) =() t = f f = t [ 1,, h ]=( 1,, h ) ( 1,, h )=[ 1,, h ] = Fig 1 yntactic equivalence on structures tructures are somewhere between formulae and sequents hey share with formulae their tree-like shape and with sequents the built-in, decidable equivalence modulo associativity and commutativity tructures have a normal form, unique modulo commutativity, where negation only occurs in the form of negative literals and all constants that can be removed are removed In all inductive arguments to come, structures are considered to be in normal form Definition 22 An inference rule is a scheme of the kind { } ρ {}, where ρ is the name of the rule, { } is its premise and {} is its conclusion he context { }may be empty In an instance of ρ, the structure taking the place of is called redex and the structure taking the place of is called contractum A(formal) system is a set of inference rules Definition 23 A derivation in a certain formal system is a finite chain of instances of inference rules in the system: π V π ρ U ρ A derivation can consist of just one structure he topmost structure in a derivation is called the premise of the derivation, and the structure at the bottom is

called its conclusion A derivation whose premise is, whose conclusion is, and whose inference rules are in will be indicated with Aproof Π in the calculus of structures is a derivation whose premise is t It will be denoted Π by Aruleρ is strongly admissible for a system if ρ/ and for every instance of ρ there is a derivation Aruleρ permutes over a rule π (or π permutes under ρ) if for every derivation some structure V 3 ystem π ρ U there is a derivation V for ρ π ystem is shown in Fig 2 he first stands for symmetric or self-dual, meaning that for each rule its dual (or contrapositive) is also in the system he stands for klassisch as in Gentzen s L and the last means that it is a system on structures he rules ai, s, m, aw, ac are called respectively atomic identity, switch, medial, atomic weakening and atomic contraction heir dual rules carry the same name prefixed with a co-, so eg aw is called atomic co-weakening he rule ai is special, it is called atomic cut ules ai, aw, ac are called down-rules and their duals are called up-rules Note that no rule requires the duplication or the comparison of structures of unbounded size he atomic rules only need to duplicate or compare literals he two rules that involve structures of unbounded size are m and s ince they do not duplicate or compare the structures held by,, U and V, there is no need to inspect those structures at all Consider structures represented as trees in the obvious way hen the switch rule can be implemented by changing the marking of two nodes and exchanging two pointers (similarly for medial): [ ] () U ( ) [ ] U In the sequent calculus, a logical rule gives meaning to the main connective of a formula by saying that the formula is provable if certain immediate subformulae are provable During a proof-search, formulae successively get decomposed, with their main connectives disappearing

{t} ai [a, ā] (a, ā) ai {f} ([, U ],) s [(, ),U] [(, U), (,V )] m ([, ], [U, V ]) {f} aw {a} {a} aw {t} [a, a] ac {a} {a} ac (a, a) Fig 2 ystem he rules switch and medial of system do not fit into this scheme Not only are they applicable deep inside a formula (or structure, for that matter), there also is no main connective that is removed While there is a connection between the switch rule and the rule in the sequent calculus (cf the proof of heorem 42), the medial rule bears no resemblance of any sequent calculus rule Its premise is a disjunction and its conclusion a conjunction his is impossible in the sequent calculus, where the conclusion of a rule is always a disjunction (a sequent) and the premise of a rule is either also a disjunction (for single premise rules) or a conjunction (for two premise rules, since the two premises are logically in a conjunction) emark 31 When talking about derivations, taking the dual means turning them upside-down, thereby exchanging premise and conclusion, and replacing each connective and constant by its De Morgan dual For example t ai [b, b] ai ([a, ā], [b, b]) s [b, ([a, ā], b)] s [a, b, (ā, b)] is dual to (a, b, [ā, b]) s (b, [(a, ā), b]) s [(a, ā), (b, b)] ai (b, b) ai f While atomic rules are good eg from the point of view of mechanized proofsearch, they are cumbersome for a user of the system Of course, it should be possible to contract and weaken on arbitrarily large formulas, just as it should

{t} i [, ] (, ) i {f} {f} w {} {} w {t} [, ] {} c c {} (, ) Fig 3 General identity, weakening, contraction and their duals be possible to introduce arbitrarily large lemmas through the cut rule Figure 3 shows the general, ie non-atomic, versions of the atomic rules in he following theorem shows that they can be used heorem 32 General identity, weakening, contraction and their duals, ie the rules {i, i, w, w, c, c } are strongly admissible for system In particular, the rules i, w and c are strongly admissible for {ai, s}, {aw, ac } and {ac, m}, respectively Dually, the rules i, w c are strongly admissible for {ai, s}, {aw, ac } and {ac, m}, respectively Proof We will show strong admissibility of the rules {i, w, c } for the respective subsystems of he proof of strong admissibility of their co-rules is dual Given an instance of one of the following rules: {t} i [, ], {f} w {}, [, ] c {}, construct a new derivation by structural induction on : 1 is a literal: hen the instance of the general rule is also an instance of its atomic form 2 =[P, Q], where P f Q: Note that [f, f ]=f Apply the induction hypothesis respectively on {t} i [Q, Q] i ([P, P ], [Q, Q]) s [Q, ([P, P ], Q)] s, [P, Q, ( P, Q)] {f} w [f,q] w, [P, Q] [P, P, Q, Q] c [P, P, Q] c [P, Q]

3 =(P, Q), where P t Q: Apply the induction hypothesis respectively on {t} i [Q, Q] i ([P, P ], [Q, Q]) s [ Q, ([P, P ],Q)] s, [ P, Q, (P, Q)] {f} ac (f, f) w (f,q) w, (P, Q) [(P, Q), (P, Q)] m ([P, P ], [Q, Q]) c ([P, P ],Q) c (P, Q) Example 33 Here are two proofs, one using the general rules, the other one in, ie without using the general rules: t ai [ b, b] ai [ b, ([ā, a],b)] s [ā, b, (a, b)] t i [[ā, b], (a, b)] c [([ā, b], [ā, b]), (a, b)] w [([ā, b, c, d], [ā, b]), (a, b)] and ac [ā, ( b, b), (a, b)] ac [(ā, ā), ( b, b), (a, b)] m [([ā, b], [ā, b]), (a, b)] aw [([ā, b, c], [ā, b]), (a, b)] aw [([ā, b, c, d], [ā, b]), (a, b)] 4 Equivalence to Classical Logic In this section we will see translations between system and system G1p, a Gentzen-chütte formulation of classical logic [8] Derivations in G1p are translated to derivations in (without introducing cuts), and proofs in are translated to proofs in G1p (possibly introducing cuts) Cut elimination for is a consequence of these translations and cut elimination in G1p ystem G1p is shown in Figure 4 Its formulae are denoted by A and B hey contain negation only on atoms equents are denoted by Σ or by A 1,,A h, where h 0 Multisets of formulae are denoted by Φ and Ψ Derivations are Σ 1 Σ h denoted by or, where h 0, the sequents Σ 1,,Σ h are the Σ premises and Σ is the conclusion Proofs are denoted by Π

Ax A, Ā Φ, A Ψ,Ā Cut Φ, Ψ Φ, A L Φ, A B Φ, B Φ, A Φ, B Φ, A B Φ, A B Φ, A, A Φ C W Φ, A Φ, A Fig 4 G1p: classical logic in Gentzen-chütte form Definition 41 he functions and given below transform formulae in G1p into structures and vice versa: a = a, A B = [A,B ], A B = (A,B ) a = a t = a ā f = a ā [, ] =, (, ) =, where a denotes a fixed arbitrarily chosen atom he domain of is extended to sequents by = f and A 1,,A h =[A 1,,A h ], where h>0 heorem 42 For every derivation in (Σ 1,,Σ h ) Σ Proof By structural induction on Σ 1 Σ h in G1p there exists a derivation Base Cases t If = Σ, take Σ, otherwise, if = Ax then take i A, Ā [A, Ā ] Σ Inductive Cases Σ 1 Σ k Σ 1 Σ l We show the case where = he translations for Φ, A Φ, B Φ, A B other cases can be done in a similar way By inductive hypothesis, we have the

following derivations: (Σ 1,,Σ k ) 1 [Φ,A ] and (Σ 1,,Σ l ) 2 [Φ,B ] (Σ 1,,Σ k,σ 1,,Σ l ) 1; 2 ([Φ,A ], [Φ,B ]) s; s [Φ,Φ, (A,B )] c [Φ, (A,B )] Corollary 43 If A is provable in G1p then A is provable in heorem 44 If P is provable in then P is provable in G1p Π Proof Let P = {} and { } ρ {} be its proof in he proof of this theorem isbasedonaknownpropertyofg1p, thatis,if, is provable then so is {}, { } Base Cases Ax a, ā If Π = t then take L ; a ā,a ā C a ā then take the same derivation, but with a replaced by a, otherwise, if Π = t ai [a, ā] Inductive Cases We assume that { } is provable in G1p By using the cut rule, we get { } {}, { } Cut It is enough to show that {}, is provable We show the case for ρ = rules of as well, as can easily be verified Ax U, U ([U, V ],W) s he property holds for the rest of the [(U, W ),V] Ax V, V W 2 W 2 Ax U, U,V, W V, V,U, W W, W W 2 U,V, U V, W W, W,V, U V U W,V, U V, W 2 2 L ; (U W ) V, (U V ) W, (U W ) V, (U V ) W C 2 (U W ) V, (U V ) W

he rule ρ n denotes n applications of ρ Cut elimination for can be obtained by using the above translations: Given a proof Π in, we can transform it to a proof Π in G1p and eliminate all the cuts there he resulting cut-free proof in G1p can then be translated back to a proof Π in he complete case analysis of the proof of heorem 42 shows that this transformation does not produce new cuts, and hence Π is a cut-free proof in 5 Cut Elimination and Decomposition here is a very natural way of proving cut elimination for system by using semantics, using the idea employed in [8] for the system G3 he proof actually gives us something more than just cut elimination, it eliminates all up-rules and also yields a decomposition of proofs into separate phases heorem 51 (Cut Elimination, semantically) For every proof there is a proof Proof Consider the rule distribute {ai } {aw } {s,ac,m} ([, ], [, U ]) d, [, (,U)] which can be realized by a contraction and two switches: ([, ], [, U ]) s [, ([, ],U)] s [,, (,U)] c [, (,U)] and thus by heorem 32 is strongly admissible for {s, ac, m} Build a derivation {d }, by going upwards from applying d as many times as possible hen will be in conjunctive normal form, ie =([a 11,a 12,], [a 21,a 22,],,[a n1,a n2,]) is valid because there is a proof of it he rule d is invertible, so is also valid A conjunction is valid only if all its immediate substructures are valid hose

are disjunctions of atoms A disjunction of atoms is valid only if it contains an atom a together with its negation ā hus, more specifically, is of the form =([b 1, b 1,a 11,a 12,], [b 2, b 2,a 21,a 22,],,[b n, b n,a n1,a n2,]) Let =([b 1, b 1 ], [b 2, b 2 ],,[b n, b n ]) Obviously, there is a derivation {aw } and a proof {ai } Let us call system the rules shown in Fig 5 We know that for proof-search in system is sufficient: Corollary 52 For every proof there is a proof As a result of cut elimination, sequent systems fulfill the subformula property Our case is different, because our rules do not split the derivation according to the main connective of the active formula However, system satisfies the main consequence of the subformula property: no new atoms have to be introduced in proof-search, ie the branching of the search tree is finite {t} ai [a, ā] {f} aw {a} [a, a] ac {a} ([, ],U) s [(, U),] [(, ), (U, V )] m ([, U ], [,V ]) Fig 5 ystem Given that in system the identity is a rule, not an axiom as in the sequent calculus, a natural question to ask is whether the applications of the identity rule can be restricted to the top of a derivation For proofs, this question is already answered positively by heorem 51 It turns out that it is also true for derivations Because of the duality between ai and ai we can also push the cuts to the bottom of a derivation While this can be obtained in the sequent calculus (using cut elimination), it can not be done with a simple permutation argument We first reduce atomic identity and cut to shallow atomic identity and cut, the following rules: ai s (, [a, ā]) and [, (a, ā)] ai s

Lemma 53 he rule ai is strongly admissible for {ai s, s} Dually, the rule ai is strongly admissible for {ai s, s} Proof By an easy structural induction on the context { } Details are in [1] heorem 54 (Decomposition: separation of identity and cut) For every derivation there is a derivation {ai } V \{ai,ai } U {ai } Proof By Lemma 53 we can reduce atomic identities to shallow atomic identities and the same for the cuts It is easy to check that the rule ai s permutes over every rule in and the rule ai s permutes under every rule in Instances of ai s and ai s are instances of ai and ai, respectively Contraction allows the repeated use of a statement in a proof by allowing to copy it at will It should be possible to copy everything needed in the beginning, and then go on with the proof without ever having to copy again his intuition is made precise by the following theorem and holds for system Wedo not know of such a result for the sequent calculus here are sequent systems for classical propositional logic that do not have an explicit contraction rule, however, they treat the context additively, so contraction is built-in and used throughout the proof heorem 55 (Decomposition: separation of atomic contraction) For every derivation there is a derivation {ac } V \{ac,ac } U {ac } Proof he obstacles to permuting up the instances of ac and down those of ac are identity and cut, respectively he solution is to turn the derivation into a proof, eliminate the cuts, turn the proof into a derivation again (using one cut), and then permuting up or down the contractions he proof can be found in [1] 6 Conclusions and Open Problems We have presented, a system of inference rules for classical logic in the calculus of structures Its main novelty is that all rules are local and their computational cost can thus be bounded o achieve this, the greater expressivity

of the calculus of structures wrt the sequent calculus was used, in particular its ability of making deep inferences We proved cut elimination for system which makes it suitable for proof-search Actually, a subset of inference rules is already complete We have also shown properties of our system that seem not to hold for any sequent presentation of classical logic, that is, strong admissibility of cut, weakening and contraction for their atomic forms and the decomposition theorems for derivations he main open problem is a more powerful decomposition theorem o that end, let us call core those rules in the system that are necessary for decomposing the general cut into atomic cuts In, the core consists of one single rule: the switch Can we separate out, ie push above the identities or below the cuts, anything that is not core? Conjecture 61 For every derivation there is a derivation non-core U 4 U 3 {ai } U 2 core U 1 {ai } non-core his conjecture has been proved for two other systems in the calculus of structures [6] and this led to cut elimination In these cut elimination proofs, atomic cuts are seen as instances of a super atomic cut, which is then pushed up all the way through the proof until it hits an identity that makes it disappear In system, such a super atomic cut cannot be pushed up over the rules ac and m Cut elimination would be much easier to prove syntactically could we rely on Conjecture 61 hen all the problematic rules that could stand in the way of the cut are either below all the cuts already or at the top of the proof and thus trivial, since their premise is t Cut elimination is thus an easy consequence of such a decomposition theorem Note that the proof of heorem 55 falls short of simplifying a syntactical proof of cut elimination not only because instances of the rule m remain above the cuts, but also because it uses cut elimination Modularity We have proved cut elimination for system, but we have no syntactic proof inside the calculus of structures, ie without detour through the sequent calculus and without resorting to semantics We are interested in such a proof because it can be modular, contrary to cut elimination proofs in the sequent calculus, cf Girard [4] p15 his modularity stems from the fact that due to atomicity of the cut, cut elimination in the calculus of structures is not a nested induction taking into account the cut rank; instead it is based on a number of lemmas about permutability of rules wrt one another (for a rather

general notion of permutability) hose lemmas of course are not affected when new rules are added to the system Predicative logic We are currently investigating the following extension of system to predicative logic: adding quantifiers to the language in the obvious way, adding the corresponding De Morgan laws and the equation x = x = if x is not free in, and adding the rules from Fig 6 Very roughly, rules {u, u } correspond to the rule in G1 while rules {n, n } correspond to he rules {ce, ce, ca, ca } are just needed to reduce contraction to its atomic form For proofs, the up-rules {n, u, ce, ca } are admissible A nice common feature of all these rules is that their premise implies their conclusion (literally, without any added quantification) his is not true of any sequent calculus presentation known to us because of the rule We do not claim that this system is local In the rule n a term t of unbounded size is copied into an unbounded number of occurrences of x in Maybe unification could be incorporated into the system to deal with this in a local manner, but we have not explored this option he question is whether this can be done without losing the good properties, cut elimination especially { x[, ]} u [ x, x ] ( x, x ) u { x(, )} {[x t]} n { x} { x} n {[x t]} [ x, x ] { x(, )} [ x, x ] { x(, )} ce ce ca ca { x[, ]} ( x, x ) { x[, ]} ( x, x ) Fig 6 Extension to predicative logic emantics for derivations tructures are in a one-to-one correspondence with traces [5] that are graphs with colored edges satisfying certain simple properties he atom occurrences of a structure are the nodes of its trace and the colors of the edges are determined by the logical relation between the atom occurrences In [5] it is shown that the switch rule can be characterized in terms of conditions on traces hose conditions can be checked locally in the sense that they involve at most four atoms at a time he question is whether the rule m can be characterized in the same way his would be a step towards a distributed system in which proof-search is driven by pairs of complementary atoms, comparable in spirit to the connection method [9] At present, however, this question is entirely open

Hopefully, trace semantics can help in understanding derivations Given the existence of a derivation in a subset of fromaknown to an unknown, what is the relation between (the traces of) and? What can be inferred about, ie what graph-theoretic properties on traces are preserved by the inference rules? By classical semantics we know that all of them preserve truth (successful valuations) he problem is that this does not tell us much about, in particular it tells us nothing about atom occurrences, their number, and their logical relations A better understanding of this would also help in finding a decomposition theorem as sketched in Conjecture 61 Acknowledgments his work has been accomplished while the first author was supported by the DFG Graduiertenkolleg 334 We would like to thank the members of the proof theory group at Dresden for providing an inspiring environment, especially Alessio Guglielmi, who introduced us to proof theory He discovered the rules for predicative logic {u, u, n, n } and helped us with this paper in numerous ways teffen Hölldobler and Lutz traßburger carefully read preliminary versions of this paper and made helpful suggestions We are grateful to Bernhard Ganter for noting the similarity between the medial law studied in algebra and our rule m, giving it its current name eferences 1 ai Brünnler and Alwen Fernanto iu A local system for classical logic echnical eport WV-2001-02, Dresden University of echnology, 2001 On the web at: http://wwwwvinftu-dresdende/ kai/localclassicallogicpsgz 2 Gerhard Gentzen Investigations into logical deduction In M E zabo, editor, he Collected Papers of Gerhard Gentzen, pages 68 131 North-Holland, Amsterdam, 1969 3 Jean-Yves Girard Linear logic heoretical Computer cience, 50:1 102, 1987 4 Jean-Yves Girard Proof heory and Logical Complexity, Volume I, volume 1 of tudies in Proof heory Bibliopolis, Napoli, 1987 Distributed by Elsevier 5 Alessio Guglielmi A calculus of order and interaction echnical eport WV-99-04, Dresden University of echnology, 1999 Available on the web at http://wwwwvinftu-dresdende/ guglielm/esearch/gug/gugpdf 6 Alessio Guglielmi and Lutz traßburger Non-commutativity and MELL in the calculus of structures echnical eport WV-01-04, Dresden University of echnology, 2001 Accepted by the Annual Conference of the European Association for Computer cience Logic, CL 01 7 Lutz traßburger MELL in the calculus of structures echnical eport WV-2001-03, Dresden University of echnology, 2001 On the web at: http://wwwkiinftudresdende/ lutz/elspdf 8 Anne jerp roelstra and Helmut chwichtenberg Basic Proof heory Cambridge University Press, 1996 9 W Bibel On matrices with connections Journal of the Association for Computing Machinery, 28(4):633 645, 1981