SOME CALKIN ALGEBRAS HAVE OUTER AUTOMORPHISMS

Similar documents
SOME CALKIN ALGEBRAS HAVE OUTER AUTOMORPHISMS

The Proper Forcing Axiom: a tutorial

A FIVE ELEMENT BASIS FOR THE UNCOUNTABLE LINEAR ORDERS

Non-trivial automorphisms from variants of small d

PROPER FORCING REMASTERED

FORCING AXIOMS AND THE CONTINUUM HYPOTHESIS, PART II: TRANSCENDING ω 1 -SEQUENCES OF REAL NUMBERS

FORCING WITH SEQUENCES OF MODELS OF TWO TYPES

COLLAPSING FUNCTIONS

Distributivity of Quotients of Countable Products of Boolean Algebras

Topology Proceedings. COPYRIGHT c by Topology Proceedings. All rights reserved.

A DIRECT PROOF OF THE FIVE ELEMENT BASIS THEOREM

The Proper Forcing Axiom

CCC Forcing and Splitting Reals

ASYMMETRIC TIE-POINTS AND ALMOST CLOPEN SUBSETS OF N

VARIATIONS FOR SEPARATING CLUB GUESSING PRINCIPLES

THE PRECIPITOUSNESS OF TAIL CLUB GUESSING IDEALS

A NEW LINDELOF SPACE WITH POINTS G δ

C* ALGEBRAS AND THEIR REPRESENTATIONS

A five element basis for the uncountable linear orders

DENSELY k-separable COMPACTA ARE DENSELY SEPARABLE

COMPLETE NORMALITY AND COUNTABLE COMPACTNESS

SET MAPPING REFLECTION

BOUNDING THE CONSISTENCY STRENGTH OF A FIVE ELEMENT LINEAR BASIS

Chain Conditions of Horn and Tarski

MORE ABOUT SPACES WITH A SMALL DIAGONAL

An introduction to OCA

Tutorial 1.3: Combinatorial Set Theory. Jean A. Larson (University of Florida) ESSLLI in Ljubljana, Slovenia, August 4, 2011

Löwenheim-Skolem Theorems, Countable Approximations, and L ω. David W. Kueker (Lecture Notes, Fall 2007)

Appalachian Set Theory Workshop, May 31, 2008 Lectures by Justin Tatch Moore Notes taken by David Milovich

Tallness and Level by Level Equivalence and Inequivalence

Forcing Axioms and Inner Models of Set Theory

A NOTE ON THE EIGHTFOLD WAY

Set theory and C*-algebras

Forcing notions in inner models

INSEPARABLE SEQUENCES AND FORCING

A BOOLEAN ALGEBRA AND A BANACH SPACE OBTAINED BY PUSH-OUT ITERATION

THE FOURTH HEAD OF βn

GROUPS WITH UNBOUNDED POTENTIAL AUTOMORPHISM TOWER HEIGHTS

Semi-stationary reflection and weak square

20 Ordinals. Definition A set α is an ordinal iff: (i) α is transitive; and. (ii) α is linearly ordered by. Example 20.2.

COMPACT C-CLOSED SPACES NEED NOT BE SEQUENTIAL

TRANSFERING SATURATION, THE FINITE COVER PROPERTY, AND STABILITY

NAMBA FORCING, WEAK APPROXIMATION, AND GUESSING

FORCING AXIOMS AND THE CONTINUUM HYPOTHESIS

COMPACT SPACES WITH HEREDITARILY NORMAL SQUARES

Topology Proceedings. COPYRIGHT c by Topology Proceedings. All rights reserved.

NOTES ON PRODUCT SYSTEMS

Ultrafilters and Set Theory. Andreas Blass University of Michigan Ann Arbor, MI


Maharam Algebras. Equipe de Logique, Université de Paris 7, 2 Place Jussieu, Paris, France

TOPOLOGY PROCEEDINGS Volume 28, No. 1, 2004 Pages

Jónsson posets and unary Jónsson algebras

M ath. Res. Lett. 15 (2008), no. 00, NN c International Press 2008 A UNIVERSAL ARONSZAJN LINE. Justin Tatch Moore. 1.

Crossed products of irrational rotation algebras by finite subgroups of SL 2 (Z) are AF

Lusin sequences under CH and under Martin s Axiom

GREGORY TREES, THE CONTINUUM, AND MARTIN S AXIOM

Katětov and Katětov-Blass orders on F σ -ideals

ALAN DOW AND ILIJAS FARAH

THE TREE PROPERTY AND THE FAILURE OF THE SINGULAR CARDINAL HYPOTHESIS AT ℵ ω 2

Between O and Ostaszewski

Prime Properties of the Smallest Ideal of β N

INTRODUCTION TO CARDINAL NUMBERS

SHELAH S SINGULAR COMPACTNESS THEOREM

APPLICATIONS OF ANOTHER CHARACTERIZATION OF βn \ N

Lecture 5: Peak sets for operator algebras and quantum cardinals. David Blecher. December 2016

EXISTENTIALLY CLOSED II 1 FACTORS. 1. Introduction

Successive cardinals with the tree property

EXTERNAL AUTOMORPHISMS OF ULTRAPRODUCTS OF FINITE MODELS

arxiv:math.lo/ v1 28 Nov 2004

Lusin sequences under CH and under Martin s Axiom

TUKEY CLASSES OF ULTRAFILTERS ON ω

The Arkhangel skiĭ Tall problem under Martin s Axiom

PCF THEORY AND CARDINAL INVARIANTS OF THE REALS

COVERING MATRICES, SQUARES, SCALES, AND STATIONARY REFLECTION

The Ultrapower Axiom implies GCH above a supercompact cardinal

Slow P -point Ultrafilters

arxiv:math/ v4 [math.oa] 28 Dec 2005

On the Length of Borel Hierarchies

A local Ramsey theory for block sequences

A SIMPLE AF ALGEBRA NOT ISOMORPHIC TO ITS OPPOSITE

ORGANIC AND TIGHT J. CUMMINGS, M. FOREMAN, AND E. SCHIMMERLING

REALCOMPACTNESS IN MAXIMAL AND SUBMAXIMAL SPACES.

ON C*-ALGEBRAS WHICH CANNOT BE DECOMPOSED INTO TENSOR PRODUCTS WITH BOTH FACTORS INFINITE-DIMENSIONAL

ITERATING ALONG A PRIKRY SEQUENCE

SOME REMARKS ON NON-SPECIAL COHERENT ARONSZAJN TREES

Thomas Jech 1 and Saharon Shelah 2,3 The Pennsylvania State University The Hebrew University of Jerusalem and Rutgers University

STEVO TODORCEVIC AND JUSTIN TATCH MOORE

A DECOMPOSITION OF E 0 -SEMIGROUPS

Irredundant Generators

The seed order. Gabriel Goldberg. October 11, 2018

The Bounded Axiom A Forcing Axiom

A BOREL SOLUTION TO THE HORN-TARSKI PROBLEM. MSC 2000: 03E05, 03E20, 06A10 Keywords: Chain Conditions, Boolean Algebras.

CH AND THE MOORE-MROWKA PROBLEM

Lecture 11: Minimal types

March 3, The large and small in model theory: What are the amalgamation spectra of. infinitary classes? John T. Baldwin

Axioms of separation

ORGANIC AND TIGHT J. CUMMINGS, M. FOREMAN, AND E. SCHIMMERLING

Covering a bounded set of functions by an increasing chain of slaloms

A locally finite characterization of AE(0) and related classes of compacta

A simple maximality principle

Transcription:

SOME CALKIN ALGEBRAS HAVE OUTER AUTOMORPHISMS ILIJAS FARAH, PAUL MCKENNEY, AND ERNEST SCHIMMERLING Abstract. We consider various quotients of the C*-algebra of bounded operators on a nonseparable Hilbert space, and prove in some cases that, assuming some restriction of the Generalized Continuum Hypothesis, there are many outer automorphisms. 1. Introduction Let H be a Hilbert space. The Calkin algebra over H is the quotient C(H) = B(H)/K, where B(H) is the C*-algebra of bounded, linear operators on H, and K is its ideal of compact operators. Assuming the Continuum Hypothesis, Phillips and Weaver constructed 2 2ℵ0 -many automorphisms of the Calkin algebra on the Hilbert space of dimension ℵ 0 ([4]). Since there are only 2 ℵ 0 -many automorphisms of C(H) which are inner (that is, implemented by conjugation by a unitary), this implies in particular that there are many more outer automorphisms than there are inner ones, in the presence of CH. The first author proved in [2] that it is relatively consistent with ZFC that all automorphisms of the Calkin algebra on a separable Hilbert space are inner. This establishes the existence of an outer automorphism as a question independent of ZFC. The assumption made there was Todorčević s Axiom (TA), a combinatorial principle also known as the Open Coloring Axiom. TA has a number of consequences in other areas of mathematics, and follows from the Proper Forcing Axiom (PFA), which is itself well-known for its influence on certain kinds of rigidity in mathematics (see [3]). The first author extended this result to prove that all automorphisms of the Calkin algebra over any Hilbert space, separable or not, are inner, assuming PFA ([1]). The development of these results parallels those in the study of the automorphisms of the Boolean algebra P(ω)/fin. Rudin ([5]) discovered early on that, assuming CH, there are many automorphisms of P(ω)/fin that are not trivial, i.e. induced by functions e : ω ω; Shelah ([6]) much later proved the consistency of the opposite result, that all automorphisms are trivial. Shelah and Steprans then showed that all automorphisms are trivial This work was initiated at the Mittag-Leffler Institute during the authors visit in September, 2009. The first author was partially supported by NSERC. 1

2 ILIJAS FARAH, PAUL MCKENNEY, AND ERNEST SCHIMMERLING assuming PFA ([7]), and then Veličković showed using PFA that all automorphisms of P(κ)/fin are trivial, for every infinite cardinal κ (along with reducing the assumption to TA + MA ℵ1 in the original case κ = ω). One might ask for the consistency of outer automorphisms of C(H) when H is nonseparable, or nontrivial automorphisms of P(κ)/fin when κ is uncountable. The latter result is easy, though for trivial reasons, since the automorphisms of P(ω)/fin can all be extended to automorphisms of P(κ)/fin, and any extension of a nontrivial automorphism of P(ω)/fin must also be nontrivial. In the case of C(H) this is not so clear, and in fact it is not yet known whether the existence of an outer automorphism of C(H), when H is nonseparable, is consistent with ZFC. However in the case where H is nonseparable there is more than one quotient of B(H) to consider. In this note we study some of these different quotients, and offer some alternatives; Theorem 1.1. Let H be a Hilbert space of some regular, uncountable dimension κ and let J be the ideal in B(H) of operators whose range has dimension less than κ. If 2 κ = κ +, then the quotient B(H)/J has 2 κ+ - many outer automorphisms. Theorem 1.2. Let H be a Hilbert space of dimension ℵ 1, let J be the ideal of operators on H whose range has dimension < ℵ 1, and let K be the ideal of compact operators. If CH holds, then J /K has 2 ℵ 1 -many outer automorphisms. Theorem 1.1 is perhaps most striking in the case κ = ℵ 1, for in this case its only set-theoretic assumption, 2 ℵ 1 = ℵ 2, follows already from PFA. Hence in a model of PFA, there are many outer automorphisms of B(H)/J, and yet no outer automorphisms of B(H)/K. Our notation is mostly standard. All Hilbert spaces considered are complex Hilbert spaces. When H is a Hilbert space, B(H) denotes the C*-algebra of bounded linear operators from H to H, K(H) denotes the closed -ideal in B(H) given by the compact operators on H, and J (H) denotes the -ideal of operators whose range has dimension strictly less than the dimension of H. When the Hilbert space H is understood we will often drop it in our notation and just use B, K, and J. Note that when H is nonseparable, J is already norm-closed, and K J B If x B then we will use [x] K and [x] J to denote the quotients of x by K(H) and J (H) respectively. When A is a set, we will write l 2 (A) for the Hilbert space of square-summable functions ξ : A C. We will also often write B(H) = B A, J (H) = J A, and K(H) = K A when H = l 2 (A). When A B we will identify l 2 (A) with a closed subspace of l 2 (B) in the obvious way. Finally, if A is a C*-algebra and x is an element of A then Ad x : A A is the map a xax. When A has a multiplicative unit and x is a unitary element of A, i.e. x x = xx = 1 A, then Ad x is an automorphism of A.

SOME CALKIN ALGEBRAS HAVE OUTER AUTOMORPHISMS 3 2. Large ideals In this section we prove Theorem 1.1. Before beginning the proof we will need some notation; Definition 2.1. If C is club in κ, we define x D[C] α C l 2 (α) is an invariant subspace of x and x Note that D[C] is a C*-subalgebra of B κ, and in fact is a von Neumann subalgebra of B κ, though we will not use this latter fact. We also set down some convenient notation for the successor of an ordinal in a club; Definition 2.2. If C is club in κ and α C, then succ C (α) denotes the minimal element of C strictly greater than α. Note that if C is club in κ, then we have in fact x D[C] α C l 2 ([α, succ C (α))) is an invariant subspace of x Finally, if A, B κ then we write A B if and only if A \ B < κ. Lemma 2.3. For every x B κ, there is some club C in κ such that x D[C]. Proof. Let θ be large and regular, and let M α, for α < κ, be a club of elementary substructures of H(θ), each of size < κ, and with x and l 2 (κ) in M 0. Then if δ = sup(m α κ), we clearly have that l 2 (δ) is an invariant subspace of x, and such ordinals δ make up a club in κ. Lemma 2.4. If C C are clubs in κ, then D[ C] J D[C], by which we mean x D[ C] y D[C] x y J Proof. If γ < κ is such that C [γ, κ) C, then for every δ C, δ γ = [δ, succ C(δ)) [δ, succ C (δ)) Thus if x D[ C], we see that P xp D[C], where P is the projection onto the subspace l 2 ([γ, κ)). Lemma 2.5. Let C be club in κ and let u and v be unitary operators on l 2 (κ), which are diagonal with respect to the standard basis; say f, g : κ T are the diagonal values of u and v respectively. Then Ad [u] J and Ad [v] J agree on D[C]/J if and only if there is some ɛ < κ such that the map ξ f(ξ) g(ξ) = f(ξ)g(ξ) is constant on each interval of the form [δ, succ C (δ)) with δ C [ɛ, κ). Proof. Let h(ξ) = f(ξ)g(ξ) for each ξ < κ. We will write ( ) for the condition ɛ δ C δ ɛ = h is constant on the interval [δ, succ C (δ)) as in the conclusion of the lemma. Now, note that u and v are trivially in the algebra D[C]. The following are equivalent;

4 ILIJAS FARAH, PAUL MCKENNEY, AND ERNEST SCHIMMERLING (1) Ad [u] J and Ad [v] J agree on D[C]/J, (2) for each x D[C], uxu vxv is in J, (3) [v u] J is in the center of the algebra D[C]/J. We will show that condition (3) holds if and only if ( ) holds. First suppose ( ) does not hold; then there is an unbounded subset A of C, and sequences σ δ,τ δ indexed by δ A, such that for each δ A, δ σ δ < τ δ < succ C (δ) and h(σ δ ) h(τ δ ). Let x be the operator defined by e σδ α = τ δ for some δ A x(e α ) = e τδ α = σ δ for some δ A 0 otherwise Then x D[C], and for each δ A, (v ux)e σδ = h(τ δ )e τδ (xv u)e σδ = h(σ δ )e τδ It follows that v ux xv u is not in the ideal J, so condition (3) does not hold. Now suppose ( ) does hold, and choose ɛ as in this condition. If x D[C], then for all α ɛ, if α [δ, succ C (δ)) where δ C then we have (v ux)e α = h(α)xe α = (xv u)e α and it follows that P (v u)p is in the center of D[C], where P is the projection onto l 2 ([ɛ, κ)). We are now ready to prove Theorem 1.1. Proof. Let E α α lim(κ + ) enumerate the clubs in κ. We will construct a sequence of clubs C s in κ, and functions f s : κ T, indexed by s 2 <κ+, such that (1) If s t, then C t C s. (2) If s t, then there is an ɛ < κ such that for every δ C s with δ ɛ, the function f s f t is constant on the interval [δ, succ Cs (δ)). (3) For all s, C s 0 = C s 1, and for unboundedly many δ C s 0 = C s 1 = C, the function f s 0f s 1 is not constant on [δ, succ C (δ)). (4) If s has length some limit ordinal α < κ +, then C s E α. Claim 2.6. This suffices. Proof. For each s 2 <κ+, let u s be the diagonal unitary in B κ with diagonal elements given by f s. For each ζ 2 κ+, and x D[C ζ α ], define Φ ζ ([x]) = [u ζ α xu ζ α ] By (1), (2), and Lemma 2.5, Φ ζ is well-defined on the union of the algebras D[C ζ α ]/J, over α < κ + ; and by (4), and Lemma 2.3, it follows that Φ ζ is defined on all of B κ /J. Since on each D[C ζ α ], Φ ζ agrees with Ad [u ζ α ], Φ ζ is also an injective homomorphism. Similar arguments show that Φ 1 ζ is defined on all of B κ /J, and hence Φ ζ is an automorphism of this quotient algebra. Finally, if ζ and η are distinct members of 2 κ+, then by (3) and Lemma 2.5 we see that Φ ζ and Φ η are distinct automorphisms.

SOME CALKIN ALGEBRAS HAVE OUTER AUTOMORPHISMS 5 We construct C s and f s by induction on the length of s 2 <κ+. It is useful to note that all the functions f s constructed in the following actually have range contained in { 1, +1}; when proving (2) and (3), then, we will drop all mention of the conjugation. In the base case we simply set C = κ and f (α) = 1 for all α < κ. For the successor case, let s 2 <κ+ be given. Set C s 0 = C s 1 = lim(c s ), f s 0 = f s, and { fs (α) if there is δ lim(c f s 1(α) = s ) such that δ α < succ Cs (δ) +f s (α) otherwise Obviously, the function f s f s 0 = fs 2 is constant on each interval of C s (in fact it is constant on all of κ). The same holds for the function f s f s 1; if δ lim(c s ) then this function has a constant value of 1 on all of [δ, succ Cs (δ)), whereas if δ C s \lim(c s ) then it has a constant value of +1 on this interval. Hence condition (2) is satisfied in the inductive step. As for condition (3), we note that for every δ lim(c s ), the function f s 0f s 1 is not constant on the interval [δ, succ lim(cs)(δ)), since this function has a value of 1 at δ and a value of +1 at succ Cs (δ) < succ lim(cs)(δ). It remains to consider the limit case. Let s 2 <κ+ be given, and let α be the length of s. For β < α, write f β = f s β and C β = C s β. By the inductive hypothesis, for every β < γ < α there is an ɛ < κ such that δ C β δ ɛ = f β f γ is constant on the interval [δ, succ Cβ (δ)) Let ɛ γ β be the minimal ɛ C β satisfying the above. We will define f s and C s in two different ways based on the cofinality of α. First, suppose θ = cf α < κ, and let α η, for η < θ, be an increasing and continuous sequence of ordinals which is cofinal in α. Define C s = η<θ C αη E α It remains to define f s and show that condition 2 holds. Choose a uniform ultrafilter Ũ over θ, and let U α be the ultrafilter over α defined in the usual way from Ũ using the sequence α η η < θ. Now for each ξ < κ define f s (ξ) = lim β U α f β (ξ) Claim 2.7. For every β < α, f β f s is constant on each interval of a tail of intervals from C β. Proof. Fix β < α, and let ɛ = sup η<θ ɛ αη β C β. Let δ C β be given, and suppose δ ɛ, but that f β f s is not constant on [δ, succ Cβ (δ)); fix witnesses σ < τ in this interval, and say without loss of generality that f β (σ)f s (σ) = +1 but f β (τ)f s (τ) = 1. By the definition of f s, there are

6 ILIJAS FARAH, PAUL MCKENNEY, AND ERNEST SCHIMMERLING A 0, A 1 U α such that γ A 0 f β (σ)f γ (σ) = +1 γ A 1 f β (τ)f γ (τ) = 1 Then if γ A 0 A 1 is larger than β we have f β (σ)f γ (σ) = +1 and f β (τ)f γ (τ) = 1. By definition of U α we may choose such a γ with γ = α η for some η < θ. But this contradicts the choice of ɛ γ β, since δ ɛ > ɛαη β. Now consider the case where cf α = κ. Let α η, η < κ, be a continuous, increasing sequence of ordinals which is cofinal in α. Put ( ) C s = C α η<κ η E α Again, it remains only to define f s and show that condition (2) holds. For this we define, for ξ < η, and ρ η ξ = min(c α ξ \ (ξ ɛ αη α ξ )) ɛ(η) = sup ρ η ξ ξ<η Note that ɛ(η) is in C αξ for each ξ < η. Define f s (ζ) = f αη (ζ) whenever ɛ(η) ζ < ɛ(η + 1) for some η < κ, that is, f s = η<κ f αη [ɛ(η), ɛ(η + 1)) Claim 2.8. For every β < α, f β f s is constant on a tail of intervals from C β. Proof. We will first prove that f αξ f s is constant on a tail of intervals from C αξ, for each ξ < κ. Let ɛ = ɛ(ξ + 1); then if δ C αξ and δ ɛ, we have ɛ(η) δ < succ Cαξ (δ) ɛ(η + 1) for some η > ξ. Hence f s is equal to f αη on the interval [δ, succ Cαξ (δ)). Since δ ɛ(η) ɛ αη α ξ, we see that f αξ f s is constant on this interval, as required. Now let β < α be given, and choose ξ < κ such that β < α ξ. By the above, there is an ɛ 0 such that f αξ f s is constant on each interval of C αξ beyond ɛ 0. Let ɛ 1 = ɛ α ξ β, and choose an ɛ 2 such that C αξ [ɛ 2, κ) C β. It follows that with ɛ = max{ɛ 0, ɛ 1, ɛ 2 } we have δ C β δ ɛ = f β f s is constant on the interval [δ, succ Cβ (δ)) Thus we have proven condition (2) in this case, and this finishes the proof of the theorem.

SOME CALKIN ALGEBRAS HAVE OUTER AUTOMORPHISMS 7 3. Small ideals In this section we work with the Hilbert space H = l 2 (ω 1 ). Hence the ideals of B(H) are exactly 0 K J B Letting C(L) denote the usual Calkin algebra over L, i.e. B(L)/K(L), it follows that J /K = C(l 2 (α)) C(l 2 (ω 1 )) α<ω 1 We will shortly prove Theorem 1.2, in a slightly stronger form; namely, assuming CH, there is an automorphism Ψ of the quotient J /K whose restriction to each subalgebra C(l 2 (α)) is an outer automorphism. It follows also that Ψ cannot be the restriction of an inner automorphism of B/K. Before we start, we will need a special case of Lemma 4.1 from [2]. We include its proof here for completeness. Lemma 3.1. Let Φ be an automorphism of C(H), where H is any Hilbert space. Then Φ is inner if and only if it is inner on some subspace L of H of the same dimension. Proof. Let L be a subspace of H of the same dimension. Then there is an isometry U : H L; let u be its image in C(H). Suppose Φ is implemented by conjugation by v on C(L); then for any x C(H), Φ(x) = Φ(u uxu u) = Φ(u) vφ(u)xφ(u) v Φ(u) and hence Φ is implemented by conjugation by Φ(u) vφ(u) on all of C(H). Theorem 3.2. Assume CH. Then there are 2 ℵ 1 -many outer automorphisms of J /K. Moreover, each of these automorphisms is outer in a strong sense, namely each is outer when restricted to any C(l 2 (α)), α < ω 1. Proof. Let Φ be an automorphism of C(l 2 (ω)). Let f α : α ω, α < ω 1, be a sequence of injections satisfying (1) α < β < ω 1 f β α = f α for every α < β < ω 1. Set A α = ran(f α ), let U α : l 2 (α) l 2 (A α ) be the unitary operator induced by f α, and let u α be its image in C(l 2 (ω 1 )). Let Ψ be the unique automorphism of J /K such that α < ω 1 (Ad u α ) Ψ = Φ (Ad u α) Condition (1) ensures that such a Ψ exists, and verifying that Ψ is an automorphism is straightforward. Lemma 3.1 implies that if Φ is outer, then Φ is also outer on every l 2 (A α ), and hence Ψ is outer on every l 2 (α). By the main result of [4], there are 2 ℵ 1 -many outer automorphisms of C(l 2 (ω)), and hence 2 ℵ 1 -many outer automorphisms of J /K.

8 ILIJAS FARAH, PAUL MCKENNEY, AND ERNEST SCHIMMERLING References [1] Ilijas Farah, All automorphisms of all Calkin algebras, Math. Res. Lett. 18 (2011), no. 3, 489 503. MR 2802582 (2012e:03104) [2], All automorphisms of the Calkin algebra are inner, Ann. of Math. (2) 173 (2011), no. 2, 619 661. MR 2776359 (2012e:03103) [3] Justin Tatch Moore, The proper forcing axiom, Proceedings of the International Congress of Mathematicians. Volume II (New Delhi), Hindustan Book Agency, 2010, pp. 3 29. MR 2827783 (2012g:03139) [4] N. Christopher Phillips and Nik Weaver, The Calkin algebra has outer automorphisms, Duke Math. J. 139 (2007), no. 1, 185 202. MR 2322680 (2009a:46123) [5] Walter Rudin, Homogeneity problems in the theory of Čech compactifications, Duke Math. J. 23 (1956), 409 419. MR 0080902 (18,324d) [6] Saharon Shelah, Proper forcing, Lecture Notes in Mathematics, vol. 940, Springer- Verlag, Berlin, 1982. MR 675955 (84h:03002) [7] Saharon Shelah and Juris Steprāns, PFA implies all automorphisms are trivial, Proc. Amer. Math. Soc. 104 (1988), no. 4, 1220 1225. MR 935111 (89e:03080) Ilijas Farah: Department of Mathematics and Statistics, York University, 4700 Keele Street, North York, Ontario, Canada, M3J 1P3; and Matematicki Institut, Kneza Mihaila 34, Belgrade, Serbia. E-mail address: ifarah@mathstat.yorku.ca Paul McKenney: Department of Mathematical Sciences, Carnegie Mellon University, Pittsburgh, USA E-mail address: pmckenne@andrew.cmu.edu Ernest Schimmerling: Department of Mathematical Sciences, Carnegie Mellon University, Pittsburgh, USA E-mail address: eschimme@andrew.cmu.edu