S ) is wf as well. (Exercise) The main example for a wf Relation is the membership Relation = {( x, y) : x y}

Similar documents
Math 280A Fall Axioms of Set Theory

Axiomatic set theory. Chapter Why axiomatic set theory?

Foundations of Mathematics MATH 220 FALL 2017 Lecture Notes

This paper is also taken by Combined Studies Students. Optional Subject (i): Set Theory and Further Logic

MAGIC Set theory. lecture 2

This section will take the very naive point of view that a set is a collection of objects, the collection being regarded as a single object.

Chapter 2 Axiomatic Set Theory

Seminaar Abstrakte Wiskunde Seminar in Abstract Mathematics Lecture notes in progress (27 March 2010)

Zermelo-Fraenkel Set Theory

Mathematics 114L Spring 2018 D.A. Martin. Mathematical Logic

Axioms for Set Theory

Chapter 2. Assertions. An Introduction to Separation Logic c 2011 John C. Reynolds February 3, 2011

Introduction to Metalogic

EQUIVALENCE RELATIONS (NOTES FOR STUDENTS) 1. RELATIONS

A1 Logic (25 points) Using resolution or another proof technique of your stated choice, establish each of the following.

Tutorial on Axiomatic Set Theory. Javier R. Movellan

A BRIEF INTRODUCTION TO ZFC. Contents. 1. Motivation and Russel s Paradox

MATH 220C Set Theory

Math 4606, Summer 2004: Inductive sets, N, the Peano Axioms, Recursive Sequences Page 1 of 10

Informal Statement Calculus

σ-set THEORY AND THE INTEGER SPACE

Copyright c 2007 Jason Underdown Some rights reserved. statement. sentential connectives. negation. conjunction. disjunction

Part II Logic and Set Theory

Peano Arithmetic. CSC 438F/2404F Notes (S. Cook) Fall, Goals Now

Well-Ordering Principle. Axiom: Every nonempty subset of Z + has a least element. That is, if S Z + and S, then S has a smallest element.

Preliminaries to the Theory of Computation

Class A is empty if no class belongs to A, so A is empty x (x / A) x (x A). Theorem 3. If two classes are empty, then they are equal.

Complete Induction and the Well- Ordering Principle

Sets, Logic, Relations, and Functions

MATH 145 LECTURE NOTES. Zhongwei Zhao. My Lecture Notes for MATH Fall

Relational Reasoning in Natural Language

9 RELATIONS. 9.1 Reflexive, symmetric and transitive relations. MATH Foundations of Pure Mathematics

Sets, Proofs and Functions. Anton Velinov

Understanding Decimal Addition

KRIPKE S THEORY OF TRUTH 1. INTRODUCTION

SETS AND CLASSES AS MANY

Introduction to Logic and Axiomatic Set Theory

Notes for Math 601, Fall based on Introduction to Mathematical Logic by Elliott Mendelson Fifth edition, 2010, Chapman & Hall

Lecture 11: Measuring the Complexity of Proofs

Peano Arithmetic. by replacing the schematic letter R with a formula, then prefixing universal quantifiers to bind

Relations to first order logic

CHALLENGES TO PREDICATIVE FOUNDATIONS OF ARITHMETIC by Solomon Feferman 1 and Geoffrey Hellman

More on Finite Automata and Regular Languages. (NTU EE) Regular Languages Fall / 41

AN INTRODUCTION TO SEPARATION LOGIC. 2. Assertions

Lecture Notes on Discrete Mathematics. October 15, 2018 DRAFT

SOME TRANSFINITE INDUCTION DEDUCTIONS

1 Initial Notation and Definitions

Chapter One. The Real Number System

Set Theory. P.D. Welch. September 6, 2017

Chapter 1. Sets and Numbers

Mathematical Preliminaries. Sipser pages 1-28

Predicate Calculus - Semantics 1/4

CHAPTER 10. Gentzen Style Proof Systems for Classical Logic

ADVANCED CALCULUS - MTH433 LECTURE 4 - FINITE AND INFINITE SETS

Contents Propositional Logic: Proofs from Axioms and Inference Rules

Now, with all the definitions we ve made, we re ready see where all the math stuff we took for granted, like numbers, come from.

Axioms as definitions: revisiting Hilbert

Descriptive Set theory

TRUTH-THEORIES FOR FRAGMENTS OF PA

5 Set Operations, Functions, and Counting

(1.3.1) and in English one says a is an element of M. The statement that a is not an element of M is written as a M

PREDICATE LOGIC: UNDECIDABILITY AND INCOMPLETENESS HUTH AND RYAN 2.5, SUPPLEMENTARY NOTES 2

Review CHAPTER. 2.1 Definitions in Chapter Sample Exam Questions. 2.1 Set; Element; Member; Universal Set Partition. 2.

Foundations of Mathematics

Homework #2 Solutions Due: September 5, for all n N n 3 = n2 (n + 1) 2 4

PART II QUANTIFICATIONAL LOGIC

MAGIC Set theory. lecture 6

Chapter 1. Logic and Proof

Přednáška 12. Důkazové kalkuly Kalkul Hilbertova typu. 11/29/2006 Hilbertův kalkul 1

The natural numbers. Definition. Let X be any inductive set. We define the set of natural numbers as N = C(X).

Herbrand Theorem, Equality, and Compactness

The constructible universe

Russell s logicism. Jeff Speaks. September 26, 2007

MAGIC Set theory. lecture 1

0.Axioms for the Integers 1

CSE 1400 Applied Discrete Mathematics Proofs

POL502: Foundations. Kosuke Imai Department of Politics, Princeton University. October 10, 2005

From Constructibility and Absoluteness to Computability and Domain Independence

Any Wizard of Oz fans? Discrete Math Basics. Outline. Sets. Set Operations. Sets. Dorothy: How does one get to the Emerald City?

Lecture Notes 1 Basic Concepts of Mathematics MATH 352

Foundations of Mathematics Worksheet 2

NATURAL NUMBERS. James T. Smith San Francisco State University

Propositional Logic: Syntax

CHAPTER 2. FIRST ORDER LOGIC

The theory of numbers

03 Review of First-Order Logic

Mathematical Logic Part Three

Zermelo-Fraenkel Set Theory

Computability Crib Sheet

Introduction to Automata

uring Reducibility Dept. of Computer Sc. & Engg., IIT Kharagpur 1 Turing Reducibility

Analysis 1. Lecture Notes 2013/2014. The original version of these Notes was written by. Vitali Liskevich

Section 2.2 Set Operations. Propositional calculus and set theory are both instances of an algebraic system called a. Boolean Algebra.

HW 4 SOLUTIONS. , x + x x 1 ) 2

Topics in Logic, Set Theory and Computability

Cardinal and Ordinal Numbers Math Klaus Kaiser

Well-Ordered Sets, Ordinals and Cardinals Ali Nesin 1 July 2001

Restricted truth predicates in first-order logic

4 The semantics of full first-order logic

Appendix to Lecture Notes on Linear Algebra I

Transcription:

(October 14/2010) 1 Well-foundedness Let R be a Relation on the class X ( R X X ) We say that the structure ( X, R ) is well-founded (wf) if the following holds true: Y X { x X [ y( yrx y Y) x Y]} Y = X In words: call a subclass Y of X inductive (with respect to the relation R ) if the clause in { } holds: x X [ y( yrx y Y) x Y] R is wf if the only inductive class is X itself [11] Suppose that ( X, R ) is wf Let S be any sub-relation (subclass) of any class such that S Z Z Then ( Z, S ) is wf as well (Exercise) R, and Z The main example for a wf Relation is the membership Relation = {( x, y) : x y} on the class of pure sets Indeed, Y being an inductive subclass of means that Y is a subclass of that is closed under set-formation Since is a subclass of any class closed under set-formation, an inductive subclass of must equal Suppose that ( X, R ) is wf, and let Y be a subclass of X ; Y bottomless (with respect to R ) if the following holds: X Let us call Y x( x Y y( y Y yrx)) [12] If ( X, R ) is wf, then every ( R -)bottomless class is empty Proof Consider the complement of the bottomless Y in X : Y = { x X : x Y} Y is inductive: assume y( yrx y Y ), (21) to see x Y : if we had x Y, then, by bottomlessness, y( y Y yrx), contradicting (1) Therefore, Y = X, which is to say that Y is empty [13] If ( X, R ) is wf, then xrx for all x X ; ( xry yrx) for all x, y X 1

Proof If xrx, then the class { x } is bottomless: contradiction If xry yrx, then the class { x, y } is bottomless 2 The natural numbers We ine 0 = = { x : } (the empty set), Sx ( ) = x {} x We ine the class as = { x : X{[(0 X y( y X Sy X)] x X} The elements of are called (von-neumann) natural numbers Later on, we will adopt the axiom of infinity: is a set At this point, however, we do not need this axiom The letters mnp,, range over natural numbers This means that the quantified expression np( n) is to be read as x( x P( x)) and np( n) as x( x P( x)) The principle of mathematical induction: P(0) npn ( ( ) PSn ( )) npn ( ) is a direct consequence of the inition: take X = { n: P( n)} in the inition of [21] (1) Every natural number is a pure set: (exercise; hint: use mathematical induction for the predicate Pn ( ) n ) (2) Every natural number is a transitive set (a class X is transitive if x y(( y x x X) y X) ) (3) Sn 0 (obvious) (4) Sm = Sn m = n Proof Suppose that Sm = Sn This means m { m} = n { n} Therefore, both of the following are true: (1) either m n or m= n (by m n { n} ), and (2) either n m or n = m Hence, either ( m n and n m), or m= n However, by (1) and [13], m n and n m is impossible Therefore, m= n follows Remark: (2) and (3) are (some of the) so-called Peano axioms 2

(5) m= 0 nm =Sn (obvious by induction) The order-relation < on is given by: m< n m n [22] (1) < is transitive: m< n < p implies that m< p (follows from [212]) (2) m< S n m< n m= n (obvious from the initions) 3 A summary of the axioms Y is a set Z Y Z Y = { x: x= x } Lower-case variables range over sets Class comprehension schema: For any predicate PXY (, ), we have Y Z x( x Z P( X, Y)) By extensionality, Z is unique; we write Z = { x: P( X, Y)} The set-existence axioms are: Axiom of subset: x Y x Y is a set (a subclass of a set is a set) Define = { x : } Axiom of the empty set: is a set For sets x and y, ine {, x y} = { u: u = x u = y} Axiom of the pair-set: x y { x, y } is a set For a set x, ine x = { u: y u y y x} Axiom of the union set: x x is a set For a set x, ine P ( x ) = { y: z( z y z x)} Axiom of the power set: x P ( x) is a set 3

The class N of the natural numbers was ined above Axiom of infinity: N is a set A Relation is a class all whose elements are ordered pairs Dom( R ) = { x : y x, y R}, Range( R ) = { y : x x, y R} A Function is a Relation R such that x y1 y2( x, y1 R x, y2 R) y1 = y2) Axiom of replacement: If R is a Function, and Dom( R ) is a set, then Range( R ) is a set (The axiom of choice will be considered later) 4 Transitive models of set theory Let Φ be any formula in the language of classes All variables, free or bound, in Φ are class-variables (the set-variables, which are a device of abbreviation, are not used) Given any variable X not occurring in Φ either as a free or a bound variable, we let Φ [ X ] denote the formula, with the single free variable X, obtained by relativizing each quantifier in Φ to subclasses of X This means replacing each Y in Φ by YY ( X ), and Y by YY ( X ) Let us abbreviate YY ( X ) by Y X, and YY ( X ) by Y X Note that if we have a set-quantifier y, with y a set- variable (as usual), this means Y(( U( Y U)) ) After relativizing to subclasses to X, it becomes ( Y X)(( U X)( Y U) ), which is equivalent to ( Y X)(Y X ) Now, from now on, we assume that the class X is transitive: y x X implies y X Thus, Y X implies that Y is a set, and Y X Therefore, the phrase ( Y X)( Y X ) is equivalent to yy ( X ) Another remark Frequently, we can re-write formulas by using the abbreviations u Y for uu ( Y ), and u Y for uu ( Y ) We conclude that, with X transitive, the set-quantifier y, after relativizing to subclasses of X, becomes y X, and similarly, y becomes y X Moreover, if our original formula Φ contains the bounded quantifier u v, or u v, then in Φ [ X ] the quantifier remains the same: the reason is that 4

u(( u X u v) ) is the same as uu ( v ), with the understanding that v X, since X is transitive; similarly for u v Consider the example of the power-set axiom as Φ (this is a senence, without free variables): y z u( u z v uv y) (I have re-written the phrase u y, that is, vv ( u v y), as v uv y ) Then Φ[ X ] is (equivalent to) ( y X)( z X)( u X)( u z v uv y) Let us examine what this means (of course, it may or may not be true, depending on what X is) The set z said to exist has to satisfy that, for u in X, u is in z iff u y; that is, z X = P ( y) X But since z is to be in X, and X is transitive, z X = z Thus, it is required that z = P ( y) X In conclusion: the truth of Φ [ X ], the power-set axiom for the transitive structure ( X, X ), is to say that P ( y) X is an element of X ; P ( y) X X 5