The Debreu-Scarf Theorem: The Core Converges to the Walrasian Allocations

Similar documents
The Walrasian Model and Walrasian Equilibrium

Economics 501B Final Exam Fall 2017 Solutions

Market Equilibrium and the Core

Second Welfare Theorem

Differentiable Welfare Theorems Existence of a Competitive Equilibrium: Preliminaries

Welfare Economics: Lecture 12

The Fundamental Welfare Theorems

Notes on General Equilibrium

First Welfare Theorem

The Fundamental Welfare Theorems

Economics 200A part 2 UCSD Fall quarter 2011 Prof. R. Starr Mr. Troy Kravitz1 FINAL EXAMINATION SUGGESTED ANSWERS

The Ohio State University Department of Economics. Homework Set Questions and Answers

Equilibrium and Pareto Efficiency in an exchange economy

The Consumer, the Firm, and an Economy

Lecture 1. History of general equilibrium theory

Existence, Computation, and Applications of Equilibrium

ANSWERS TO ODD NUMBERED EXERCISES IN CHAPTER 3

Pareto Efficiency (also called Pareto Optimality)

Notes IV General Equilibrium and Welfare Properties

Fundamental Theorems of Welfare Economics

ECONOMICS 001 Microeconomic Theory Summer Mid-semester Exam 2. There are two questions. Answer both. Marks are given in parentheses.

Introduction to General Equilibrium

Lecture Notes October 18, Reading assignment for this lecture: Syllabus, section I.

Core. Ichiro Obara. December 3, 2008 UCLA. Obara (UCLA) Core December 3, / 22

Economic Core, Fair Allocations, and Social Choice Theory

Competitive Equilibrium

1 Second Welfare Theorem

Question 1. (p p) (x(p, w ) x(p, w)) 0. with strict inequality if x(p, w) x(p, w ).

General equilibrium with externalities and tradable licenses

Market Outcomes: Efficient or Fair?

A Simple Market-Like Allocation Mechanism for Public Goods

KIER DISCUSSION PAPER SERIES

Economics 201b Spring 2010 Solutions to Problem Set 1 John Zhu

Introduction to General Equilibrium: Framework.

General Equilibrium. General Equilibrium, Berardino. Cesi, MSc Tor Vergata

PhD Qualifier Examination

Core equivalence and welfare properties without divisible goods

Short correct answers are sufficient and get full credit. Including irrelevant (though correct) information in an answer will not increase the score.

EC487 Advanced Microeconomics, Part I: Lecture 5

Ph.D. Preliminary Examination MICROECONOMIC THEORY Applied Economics Graduate Program June 2016

Contracts under Asymmetric Information

Short correct answers are sufficient and get full credit. Including irrelevant (though correct) information in an answer will not increase the score.

(ii) An input requirement set for this technology is clearly not convex as it

Problem Set 1 Welfare Economics

Microeconomic Theory -1- Introduction

Economics 101 Lecture 5 - Firms and Production

Department of Economics The Ohio State University Final Exam Questions and Answers Econ 8712

Advanced Microeconomic Theory. Chapter 6: Partial and General Equilibrium

Advanced Microeconomics

Week 6: Consumer Theory Part 1 (Jehle and Reny, Chapter 1)

Lecture #3. General equilibrium

Adding Production to the Theory

Positive Theory of Equilibrium: Existence, Uniqueness, and Stability

Walrasian Equilibrium in an exchange economy

Economics 201B Second Half. Lecture 12-4/22/10. Core is the most commonly used. The core is the set of all allocations such that no coalition (set of

A : a b c d a : B C A E B : d b c a b : C A B D E C : d c a c : E D B C D : a d b d : A D E B C E : a b d. A : a b c d a : B C A D E

Competitive Market Mechanisms as Social Choice Procedures

General Equilibrium and Welfare

3. THE EXCHANGE ECONOMY

ANSWER KEY. University of California, Davis Date: June 22, 2015

In the Name of God. Sharif University of Technology. Microeconomics 1. Graduate School of Management and Economics. Dr. S.

IMPOSSIBILITY OF A WALRASIAN BARGAINING SOLUTION 1

Noncooperative Games, Couplings Constraints, and Partial Effi ciency

3.2 THE FUNDAMENTAL WELFARE THEOREMS

1 General Equilibrium

Lecture 2 The Centralized Economy

Are We There Yet? Mechanism Design Beyond Equilibrium

Uniqueness, Stability, and Gross Substitutes

4 Lecture Applications

Public Economics Ben Heijdra Chapter 9: Introduction to Normative Public Economics

Lecture Notes for January 8, 2009; part 2

Advanced Microeconomic Analysis, Lecture 6

Economics 101. Lecture 2 - The Walrasian Model and Consumer Choice

Microeconomics. Joana Pais. Fall Joana Pais

Econ 401A: Economic Theory Mid-term. Answers

0 Aims of this course

Ph.D. Preliminary Examination MICROECONOMIC THEORY Applied Economics Graduate Program May 2012

Unlinked Allocations in an Exchange Economy with One Good and One Bad

Microeconomics, Block I Part 2

Implementation of Marginal Cost Pricing Equilibrium Allocations with Transfers in Economies with Increasing Returns to Scale


Department of Economics The Ohio State University Midterm Answers Econ 805

Can everyone benefit from innovation?

Mathematical models in economy. Short descriptions

Implementation of marginal cost pricing equilibrium allocations with transfers in economies with increasing returns to scale

Firms and returns to scale -1- John Riley

The Relation Between Implementability and the Core

Overview. Producer Theory. Consumer Theory. Exchange

Representation of TU games by coalition production economies

2.9. V = u(x,y) + a(x-f(l x,t x )) + b(y-g(l y,t y )) + c(l o -L x -L y ) + d(t o -T x -T y ) (1) (a) Suggested Answer: V u a 0 (2) u x = -a b 0 (3)

Algorithmic Game Theory and Applications

Chapter 4. Applications/Variations

1 Jan 28: Overview and Review of Equilibrium

Final Examination with Answers: Economics 210A

Firms and returns to scale -1- Firms and returns to scale

Lecture 6: Competitive Equilibrium in the Growth Model (II)

A Core Equilibrium Convergence in a. Public Goods Economy

Introductory Microeconomics

Tilburg University. Core Equivalence in Economies With Satiation Konovalov, A. Publication date: Link to publication

Microeconomics II. MOSEC, LUISS Guido Carli Problem Set n 3

Transcription:

The Debreu-Scarf Theorem: The Core Converges to the Walrasian Allocations We ve shown that any Walrasian equilibrium allocation (any WEA) is in the core, but it s obvious that the converse is far from true: most core allocations are not WEAs for the given initial distribution of goods. (Core allocations are Pareto efficient, so the Second Welfare Theorem does tell us that they can be supported as WEAs if we first implement some kind of redistribution.) But we saw, at least in an example, that some core allocations the ones that are farthest from being Walrasian were eliminated as we added consumers to the economy. The more consumers we added, the more allocations we eliminated: the additional consumers provided more opportunity to improve upon any proposed allocation. It seems reasonable to conjecture, then, that when the economy is very large (i.e., when it has very many consumers), the core may consist only of WEAs and allocations very near them i.e., that core allocations are very nearly WEAs. And that perhaps in the limit, core allocations are Walrasian equilibrium allocations. As we ve seen, merely stating this idea formally is difficult. We ll take the approach that Edgeworth took when he first came up with this idea, and which Debreu and Scarf finally formalized and used to prove the conjecture many decades later the idea of considering ever-larger replications of a basic economy. In this framework, the theorem we state and prove (for the 2 2 case) says that for any allocation that s not a WEA, if we make the economy large enough (i.e., if we replicate it sufficiently many times), it will be so large that the non-wea we started with will fail to be in the large economy s core. Theorem: Let E = (u t, x t ) T t=1 be an economy in which each u t is continuous, strictly quasiconcave, and strictly increasing, and in which x t k > 0 for each t T and each good k = 1,..., l. If an allocation (x t ) T R T + l is not a Walrasian equilibrium allocation for E, then there is an integer r such that, for all r r, the allocation r (x t ) T is not in the core of the replication economy r E. Proof: (For the 2 2 case 2 persons, 2 goods) (This proof assumes that each u t is differentiable. This is not essential, but it makes the proof more transparent.) Suppose that (( x 1, ŷ 1 ), ( x 2, ŷ 2 )), or ( x t, ŷ t ) T for short, is in the core, but is not a Walrasian equilibrium allocation (a WEA). We will show that if r is large enough, then the r-fold replication of ( x t, ŷ t ) T i.e., r ( x t, ŷ t ) T will not be in the core of the r-fold replication r E.

First, notice that ( x t, ŷ t ) T ( x t, ẙ t ) T : we ve assumed that ( x t, ŷ t ) T is in the core, so it is Pareto efficient; but if the endowment allocation is Pareto efficient, then the Second Welfare Theorem would ensure that it s a WEA, and we ve assumed that ( x t, ŷ t ) T is not a WEA. Let L denote the line that passes through, say, ( x 1, ŷ 1 ) and ( x 1, ẙ 1 ), and let τ be its slope: τ = ŷ1 ẙ 1 x 1 x = ŷ2 ẙ 2 1 x 2 x, 2 which is the trading ratio defined by ( x t, ŷ t ) T and ( x t, ẙ t ) T. [The two traders trading ratios are equal because x 1 + x 2 = x and ŷ 1 + ŷ 2 = ẙ, which follows from the fact that each u t is increasing.] Wlog, assume that the common MRS at ( x t, ŷ t ) T, denoted σ, satisfies σ < τ, and assume that x 1 > x 1 and x 2 < x 2. [The common MRS exists because ( x t, ŷ t ) T is Pareto efficient and preferences are quasiconcave.] Since σ < τ, each consumer would gain by giving up some (perhaps only very little) of the x-good in return for the y-good at the rate τ, as depicted in Figure 1. If we write for type t s net trades, and z t = (z t x, z t y) = (x t x t, y t ẙ t ) ũ t (z t ) := u t ( x t + z t x, ẙ t + z t y) for type t s utility from a net trade z t, then we have (1) ẑ 1 + ẑ 2 = (0, 0), and (2) ũ 1 (λ 1 ẑ 1 ) > ũ 1 (ẑ 1 ) and ũ 2 (λ 2 ẑ 2 ) > ũ 2 (ẑ 2 ) for some λ 1 < 1 and λ 2 > 1. We need to construct a coalition made up of α 1 members of type 1 and α 2 members of type 2, and give each member of the coalition the net trade λ t ẑ t (depending on the member s type, t = 1 or t = 2), thereby making each member better off than at ẑ t. The question is: How can we use the numbers λ 1 < 1 and λ 2 > 1 to determine the numbers α 1 and α 2 (which must be integers)? If each member of the coalition receives the net trade ẑ t (t = 1, 2), then the coalition s aggregate net trade will be α 1 λ 1 ẑ 1 + α 2 λ 2 ẑ 2. That aggregate net trade has to be (0, 0) if the coalition is to implement it unilaterally. Therefore we need to have α 1 λ 1 ẑ 1 + α 2 λ 2 ẑ 2 = (0, 0). Since we do have ẑ 1 + ẑ 2 = (0, 0), it will suffice to have α 2 (3) α 1 λ 1 = α 2 λ 2 ; i.e., = λ 1. α 1 λ 2 If λ 1 and λ 2 are rational numbers (each a ratio of integers), then we can choose integers α 1 and α 2 that satisfy (3), and then we let r = max{α 1, α 2 }. And it s clear from (2), together with continuity of each u t, that we can indeed choose λ 1 and λ 2 to be rational. 2

Concluding Remarks: The way we ve modeled large economies is extremely special and unrealistic. An actual economy, if it s very large, isn t going to consist of only a small number of types of consumer, with every consumer being one of these few types. Even if this were a good approximation even if there were a small number of types and every consumer were very close to one of those types it would be astonishing if there were also exactly the same number of consumers of each type. Shortly after Debreu and Scarf published their paper on the core convergence theorem, in 1963, Robert Aumann published a paper in which he took a remarkably innovative approach to formulating a model of a large economy in which individual consumers have negligible influence. Aumann modeled a large economy as one with an infinite set of consumers, endowed with a measure in which each individual consumer has measure zero. Within this model, Aumann used essentially the Debreu-Scarf method of proof to show that in a large economy the only core allocations are the Walrasian equilibrium allocations. Aumann s paper especially the introductory section is one of the most striking and elegant papers in economics. You should definitely read both the introductory and concluding sections, and make the effort to read the remaining five pages which contain the formal model and proof. The paper is available on the course website, in the Readings section. After Aumann s paper, a great deal of work was devoted to these ideas over the subsequent two or three decades, in which Aumann s continuum model (and the core equivalence result, and others) was shown to be the limiting case, in a well-defined sense, of large but finite economies. So what s the significance of the Core Convergence (Debreu-Scarf) Theorem? It tells us that if the economy is sufficiently large that individual consumers are negligible, then whatever institution we use to allocate resources, we will end up with the same outcome we would have attained via markets and prices. Of course, that assumes we have no externalities, consumers have complete information about the prices and the commodities, and consumers are free to go their own way, using their own resources independently of other consumers. And note that we didn t allow production, which complicates things considerably, largely because of scale phenomena. The concept of the core is important in contexts other than large economies. For one example, in auction theory, see the paper by Ausubel and Milgrom on the course website, especially Section 5 of the paper. 3

Exercise: The Core Shrinks Under Replication We begin with a 2 2 Edgeworth Box exchange economy: each consumer has the same preference, described by the utility function u(x, y) = xy; Consumer 1 owns the bundle ( x 1, ẙ 1 ) = (15, 30); and Consumer 2 owns the bundle ( x 2, ẙ 2 ) = (75, 30). (a) Verify that there is a unique Walrasian (competitive) equilibrium, in which the price ratio is p x /p y = 2/3 and the consumption bundles are (x 1, y 1 ) = (30, 20) and (x 2, y 2 ) = (60, 40). (b) Verify that the Pareto allocations are the ones that allocate the entire resource endowment of ( x, ẙ) = (90, 60) and satisfy y 1 /x 1 = y 2 /x 2 = 2/3. (c) In the Edgeworth Box draw the competitive allocation, the Pareto allocations, and each consumer s budget constraint at the competitive prices. Draw each consumer s indifference curve containing his initial bundle and indicate the core allocations in the diagram. (d) Verify that the Pareto allocations for which x 1 < 675 are not in the core. Note that 675 is approximately 26. Similarly, the Pareto allocations for which x 2 < 3375 58.1 are not in the core. (e) Consider a proposed allocation (ˆx 1, ŷ 1 ) = (27, 18) and (ˆx 2, ŷ 2 ) = (63, 42). Note that each consumer s marginal rate of substitution at the proposal is 2/3. Verify that the proposal is in the core. Verify that the trading ratio τ defined by the proposal is τ = 1. As in our lecture notes on the Debreu-Scarf Theorem, use the shrinkage factor λ 1 = 2/3 and the expansion factor λ 2 = 4/3 to verify that a coalition of just two Type 1 consumers and one Type 2 consumer can unilaterally allocate their initial bundles to make all three of them better off than in the proposal. Therefore the proposal is not in the core if there are two or more consumers of each type. (f) Now consider the proposal (ˆx 1, ŷ 1 ) = (28 1, 19) and (ˆx 2 2, ŷ 2 ) = (61 1, 41), and use the same 2 λ 1 and λ 2 as in (e) to establish that this proposal too is not in the core if there are two or more consumers of each type. (g) Now consider the proposal (ˆx 1, ŷ 1 ) = (29, 19 1) and (ˆx 3 2, ŷ 2 ) = (61, 40 2 ), and use the factors 3 λ 1 = 4/5 and λ 2 = 6/5 to establish that this proposal is not in the core if there are three or more consumers of each type. 1