Commentary on Guarini

Similar documents
Connectionist Coherence and Moral Reasoning

Lecture 12: Arguments for the absolutist and relationist views of space

Why the Difference Between Quantum and Classical Physics is Irrelevant to the Mind/Body Problem

Part II A Reexamination of Contemporary Utilitarianism

So, what are special sciences? ones that are particularly dear to the author? ( Oh dear. I am touched. Psychology is just, so, well, special!

Sklar s Maneuver. Bradford Skow ABSTRACT

Comments on The Role of Large Scale Assessments in Research on Educational Effectiveness and School Development by Eckhard Klieme, Ph.D.

The paradox of knowability, the knower, and the believer

Scientific Explanation- Causation and Unification

Published in Analysis, 2004, 64 (1), pp

The Philosophy of Quantum Mechanics (Handout Eight) between the microphysical and the macrophysical. The macrophysical world could be understood

Favoring, Likelihoodism, and Bayesianism

For True Conditionalizers Weisberg s Paradox is a False Alarm

Russell s logicism. Jeff Speaks. September 26, 2007

For True Conditionalizers Weisberg s Paradox is a False Alarm

McTaggart s Argument for the Unreality of Time:

Precis of Aristotle s Modal Syllogistic

Argumentation and rules with exceptions

The Conjunction and Disjunction Theses

As you scroll through this review, you move your hand; this causes the

A new resolution of the Judy Benjamin problem

PROOF-THEORETIC REDUCTION AS A PHILOSOPHER S TOOL

Popper s Measure of Corroboration and P h b

COMP310 Multi-Agent Systems Chapter 16 - Argumentation. Dr Terry R. Payne Department of Computer Science

Review of Gordon Belot, Geometric Possibility Oxford: Oxford UP, 2011

In Defense of Jeffrey Conditionalization

Accuracy, Language Dependence and Joyce s Argument for Probabilism

Some Thoughts on Computation and Simulation in Cognitive Science

Measurement Independence, Parameter Independence and Non-locality

Comments on Markosian s How Fast Does Time Pass?

The Varieties of (Relative) Modality

Marc Lange -- IRIS. European Journal of Philosophy and Public Debate

ON THE FAITHFUL INTERPRETATION OF PURE WAVE MECHANICS

On an Unsound Proof of the Existence of Possible Worlds

A Little Deductive Logic

Journal of Theoretics Vol.5-3 Guest Commentary

Dr. Truthlove, or How I Learned to Stop Worrying and Love Bayesian Probabilities

Quantum Mechanics: Interpretation and Philosophy

A Little Deductive Logic

Absolute motion versus relative motion in Special Relativity is not dealt with properly

I. Induction, Probability and Confirmation: Introduction

Lecture - 24 Radial Basis Function Networks: Cover s Theorem

What Does Quantum Mechanics Suggest About Our Perceptions of Reality?

A NOTE ON THE ARTICU "SOMF: EXPERIMENTAL n-person GAMES" ' R. Duncan Luce

Philosophy of Mathematics Structuralism

Beliefs, we will assume, come in degrees. As a shorthand, we will refer to these. Syracuse University

The Philosophy of Physics. Special Relativity and Minkowski Spacetime

Philosophy 240 Symbolic Logic. Russell Marcus Hamilton College Fall 2014

Ontology on Shaky Grounds

Structuralism and the Limits of Skepticism. David Chalmers Thalheimer Lecture 3

Avoiding the Block Universe: A Reply to Petkov Peter Bokulich Boston University Draft: 3 Feb. 2006

In Being and Nothingness, Sartre identifies being-for-itself as consisting in the

ON MEREOLOGICAL ESSENTIALISM*

The mousetrap. Figure by MIT OCW.

The nature of Reality: Einstein-Podolsky-Rosen Argument in QM

Philosophy 5340 Epistemology. Topic 3: Analysis, Analytically Basic Concepts, Direct Acquaintance, and Theoretical Terms. Part 2: Theoretical Terms

Paradoxes of special relativity

Structure learning in human causal induction

Précis of Modality and Explanatory Reasoning

B. Weaver (24-Mar-2005) Multiple Regression Chapter 5: Multiple Regression Y ) (5.1) Deviation score = (Y i

COMP310 MultiAgent Systems. Chapter 16 - Argumentation

On the Evolution of the Concept of Time

First-Degree Entailment

CHAPTER 6 - THINKING ABOUT AND PRACTICING PROPOSITIONAL LOGIC

Sidgwick s Argument for Utilitarianism and his Moral Epistemology: A Reply to David Phillips

Models of Strategic Reasoning Lecture 2

Critical Notice: Bas van Fraassen, Scientific Representation: Paradoxes of Perspective Oxford University Press, 2008, xiv pages

Gunk Mountains: A Puzzle

Chapter 2. Mathematical Reasoning. 2.1 Mathematical Models

Confirmation Theory. Pittsburgh Summer Program 1. Center for the Philosophy of Science, University of Pittsburgh July 7, 2017

Zombies are serious business

CAUSATION. Chapter 14. Causation and the Direction of Time Preliminary Considerations in Support of a Causal Analysis of Temporal Concepts

Explanation and Argument in Mathematical Practice

The claim that composition is identity is an intuition in search of a formulation.

Notes on Chapter 2 of Dedekind s Theory of Algebraic Integers

Conceivability and Modal Knowledge

Deep Metaphysical Indeterminacy

Dick's PhAQs II: Philosopher-Asked Questions

PHILOSOPHY OF PHYSICS (Spring 2002) 1 Substantivalism vs. relationism. Lecture 17: Substantivalism vs. relationism

A Crucial Mistake in the Free Will Debate

Alternative Technologies

Expressive Power, Mood, and Actuality

A-Theory or B-Theory of Time? An Aristotelian Answer

Desire-as-belief revisited

4 Derivations in the Propositional Calculus

Identity in Physics and Elsewhere

FIRST PUBLIC EXAMINATION. Preliminary Examination in Philosophy, Politics and Economics INTRODUCTION TO PHILOSOPHY LONG VACATION 2014

, (1) e i = ˆσ 1 h ii. c 2016, Jeffrey S. Simonoff 1

Introduction to Logic and Axiomatic Set Theory

Superposition - World of Color and Hardness

Pattern Recognition Prof. P. S. Sastry Department of Electronics and Communication Engineering Indian Institute of Science, Bangalore

Knowledge, Truth, and Mathematics

has been falsified by the development of special relativity. In this paper, I identify and reject an

Formal Epistemology: Lecture Notes. Horacio Arló-Costa Carnegie Mellon University

Ex Post Cheap Talk : Value of Information and Value of Signals

For Philosophy and Phenomenolgical Research

On Likelihoodism and Intelligent Design

A Note on the Existence of Ratifiable Acts

is short for the thing which is Pond at t 1

Slope Fields: Graphing Solutions Without the Solutions

Transcription:

University of Windsor Scholarship at UWindsor OSSA Conference Archive OSSA 5 May 14th, 9:00 AM - May 17th, 5:00 PM Commentary on Guarini Andrew Bailey Follow this and additional works at: http://scholar.uwindsor.ca/ossaarchive Part of the Philosophy Commons Andrew Bailey, "Commentary on Guarini" (May 14, 2003). OSSA Conference Archive. Paper 38. http://scholar.uwindsor.ca/ossaarchive/ossa5/papersandcommentaries/38 This Commentary is brought to you for free and open access by the Faculty of Arts, Humanities and Social Sciences at Scholarship at UWindsor. It has been accepted for inclusion in OSSA Conference Archive by an authorized administrator of Scholarship at UWindsor. For more information, please contact scholarship@uwindsor.ca.

Author: Commentary on: Andrew Bailey M. Guarini s Connectionist Coherence and Moral Reasoning 2003 Andrew Bailey Marcello Guarini s paper is a critical examination of Paul Thagard s computational model of moral reasoning. As Guarini explains, Thagard s basic idea is that we can, in general, model many of our rational deliberations as a process of settling on an interpretation of a particular domain that fits the available information better than any available alternative. The important notion of fitting is cashed out by Thagard in terms of coherence. The elements of a domain such as a particular theory-selection problem in science, an ethical dilemma, or a difficult choice between competing job offers are treated by Thagard as a set of representations. These representations stand in various relations of local coherence, according to Thagard: some of them cohere with other elements, in virtue of such more primitive relations as explanation, deduction, facilitation, association, and so on (Thagard and Verbeurgt 1998, 3), and others incohere, because of their relations of inconsistency, incompatibility, and negative association (Thagard and Verbeurgt 1998, 3). This set of local coherences between the elements of a domain can be modelled as giving rise to a set of constraints: where two elements cohere, there is a positive constraint between them; where they incohere, the constraint is negative. The coherence problem consists of dividing a set of elements into accepted and rejected sets in a way that satisfies the most constraints (Thagard and Verbeurgt 1998, 3). Positive constraints can be satisfied either by keeping both of the locally cohering elements, or by rejecting them both. Negative constraints are satisfiable only by keeping one element and rejecting the other. The solution of a coherence problem gives a result that Thagard calls global coherence. The goal in various sorts of rational deliberation, according to Thagard, is to maximize global coherence to pick the solution that satisfies as many constraints as possible (and thus which respects all the relations of local coherence for the domain as far as possible). As Guarini notes, this coherence approach to modelling reasoning is what Thagard calls biscriptive, meaning that it is neither purely descriptive of how people actually do reason, nor purely prescriptive of how they should. As Thagard puts it, his model describes how people make inferences when they are in accord with the best practices compatible with their cognitive capacities (Thagard 1992, 97). Thagard s biscriptive model of ethical reasoning, as Guarini tells us, actually depends upon a kind of meta-coherence a coherence of at least four kinds of global coherence for four connected domains: explanatory, deductive, deliberative and analogical. Roughly, explanatory coherence generates the best fit with empirical data; deductive coherence produces the best fit between general principles and particular judgements; deliberative coherence gets you the best fit between judgements and goals; and analogical coherence brings out the best fit between judgements of some cases with judgements of other similar cases. These four sets of elements are, according to Thagard, connected by positive and negative constraints, and meta-global coherence is achieved by satisfying as many of these constraints as possible. Thagard calls this a multicoherence theory of ethics (Thagard 1998). This ethical theory is descriptive, insofar as it purports to model an idealized version of the way in which people actually make ethical 1

judgements, when they are being rational, but prescriptive insofar as it sets out to be an account of the way in which rational ethical judgements should optimally be made: the appropriate ethical judgement, presumably, is the one that maximizes the meta-global coherence of the ethical domain in question. Guarini raises various problems with Thagard s account of ethical reasoning; these problems fall into three groups. The first set of problems Guarini broaches concerns the issue of determining the positive and negative constraints both between the elements of each domain (explanatory, deductive, deliberative and analogical), and between the domains themselves. Thagard does not (as far as I know) provide much detailed discussion on how these parameters are to be set in ethical deliberations, 1 but implicit in his discussion seems to be the assumption that the constraints will be to a large degree determined in such a way that they produce the correct answer for problems to which we already feel we know the answer (such as historical cases of scientific theory choice). If the network, so defined, produces good answers to a range of uncontroversial cases, it may be that we can then suppose that it will produce reliable answers to new problems. It could be, Guarini admits, that such a procedure will work for the making of scientific judgements where there is quite a bit of agreement regarding which theories should have won when theories competed for acceptance (Guarini 2003, 9) but it will not do in the sphere of ethics, where not only is there is no comparable pool of uncontroversial moral judgements, but there is not even agreement on how different kinds of consideration such as empirical versus theoretical considerations should be appropriately weighted with respect to each other. As a result, Guarini claims, Thagard s theory falls short of its claim to produce ethical judgements that can command general rational assent. It seems to me, however, that the considerations Guarini is raising here point to two different sorts of problem with Thagard s model, and that, though Guarini does speak of two different underdetermination problems, they cross-cut the distinction Guarini is trying to draw and as such are not very clearly distinguished. Furthermore, neither of the problems has much in the end to do with the lack of a suitable pool of uncontroversial moral cases for training purposes. The first sort of problem seems to me to be a general problem with programming a network in this post facto kind of way, and it is what Guarini is getting at when he says that different assignments of weights for the different types of coherence [or, one might add, weightings between the types of coherence] may yield the same answers for an agreed upon body of successfully resolved disputes but not yield the same answers when new disputes arise (Guarini 2003, 11). That is, in general, and presumably in the scientific sphere as in the ethical, nonequivalent networks could produce the same set of answers for any given finite collection of problems but produce different answers to future problems. We are thus faced with the problem of rationally deciding which of the two networks has the right weighting. And notice that this problem cannot itself be solved by an appeal to coherence (at least, not at the level of the networks themselves) since the setting of the constraints for the problem domain is something that happens prior to, and sets the initial conditions for, considerations of global coherence. The second sort of underdetermination problem for Thagard that Guarini might be meaning to identify is of a quite different sort, and threatens to introduce precisely the sort of circularity to ethical deliberation that Thagard is keen to avoid. This is the concern that the setting of positive and negative constraints for a problem domain which, recall, occurs prior to and independently of the determination of global coherence is itself an ethical judgement. In particular, in determining the relative weighting of the four different kinds of coherence we are not relying merely upon such ethically-neutral considerations as deduction and association, but also on, for 2

example, our allegiances to particular ethical frameworks, such as consequentialism or deontology. Hence Thagard s hope that once discussion establishes a common set of constraints, coherence algorithms can yield [moral] consensus (Thagard 1998, 418) does not amount to the claim that non-moral foundational assumptions can be found which will pre-empt the need for ethical foundations (and in this Thagard s multicoherence account resembles other contemporary appeals to reflective equilibrium, such as, say, Rawls 1996). Guarini s next objection to Thagard seems to me to carry less weight. He argues, in essence, that Thagard is committed to the implausible view that more entailments yield greater coherence (Guarini 2003, 12), but it is not immediately clear that this is true. Thagard is certainly committed to the position that satisfying more constraints, both positive and negative, yields greater global coherence, but it is not immediately clear how this commitment entails that more positive linkage is better (Guarini 2003, 12). Perhaps one way of capturing what Guarini is getting at is with the following example: consider a domain of elements together with their appropriate constraints. Imagine that some sorting of this domain into accepted and rejected elements produces the best possible degree of satisfaction of these constraints. Then suppose that, for example, we add an additional element that is entailed by some set of elements of the domain. This would add at least one additional satisfied constraint, and thus the new domain, and the new problem-solution, would apparently be more coherent than the earlier one. All of this seems right, as far as it goes, but it is perhaps unnecessarily uncharitable to Thagard. Thagard s real position, surely, is that for a given domain maximizing global coherence consists in maximizing the number of constraints satisfied; there is no need to attribute to him the position that larger domains are more coherent than smaller ones, in virtue of their larger number of satisfied constraints. 2 Guarini s third main objection is that Thagard s model is too computationally unwieldy to ever actually be self-consciously carried out by normal human reasoners, and that as such it cannot be a model of how we reason when we reason at our best, as Thagard claims. Thagard considers a point very much like this one, and argues in detail that coherence problems run on connectionist networks are computationally tractable (Thagard and Verbeurgt 1998, 9 12). However, although Guarini concedes that it is possible that some neural net in the brain settles on the belief set that has greatest coherence (Guarini 2003, 14), he contends that this is not enough to account for the prescriptive force of moral reasoning: in order to argue that one moral position is superior to another, he suggests, one must be in a position to know that one s view is more globally coherent than the alternative, and it is this access which is denied us by our cognitive limitations although our interpretation may in fact be maximally coherent, we cannot run the computation in consciousness in order to discern that it is. While I think that Guarini s objection here has quite a lot of force, it bears pointing out that the worry seems to depend upon a kind of internalism about ethical knowledge it suggests, I think, that we cannot know that ethical position p is justified without knowing that we know that p. 3 It might be open to Thagard to reply that, as long as we are reasoning well according to his biscriptive model, then we are rationally justified in our ethical beliefs, even if we cannot tell from the inside, as it were, that we are justified. And in fact, Thagard not only stresses the piecemeal nature of our conscious moral reasoning, but also notes that ethical deliberation is an inherently social activity, and does not take place entirely within the confines of a single mind (Thagard 1998, 415). Just as Guarini intends his objections to Thagard to be a friendly critique, so too do I intend my comments on Guarini in the same spirit. We both agree, I think, that Thagard s work on 3

computational models of moral reasoning is sophisticated and fruitful, and Guarini s critical assessment of Thagard is helpful and productive in moving the debate forward. Notes 1 Though he does discuss the constraints for explanatory coherence in some detail in Thagard 1989 and 1992. 2 On a side-note, in his version of the Bernado case study Guarini says that positively constrained propositions tend to be accepted together and negatively constrained ones tend to be rejected together : this is at odds with Thagard s actual account, which has positively constrained elements either jointly accepted or jointly rejected, and negatively constrained elements asymmetrically accepted or rejected. 3 Of course this is quite a well-known problem with coherentism. See for example BonJour s struggles with the doxastic assumption in his 1985. References BonJour, Laurence. The Structure of Empirical Knowledge. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Guarini, Marcello. 2003. Connectionist Coherence and Moral Reasoning. Unpublished manuscript. Rawls, John. 1996. Political Liberalism. New York: Columbia University Press. Thagard, Paul. 1989. Explanatory Coherence, Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12: 435 467. Thagard, Paul. 1992. Conceptual Revolutions. Princeton: Princeton University Press. Thagard, Paul. 1998. Ethical Coherence, Philosophical Psychology 11: 405 422. Thagard, Paul, and Karsten Verbeurgt. 1998. Coherence as Constraint Satisfaction, Cognitive Science 22: 1 24. 4