Symmetric Solutions of Some Production Economies

Similar documents
A NOTE ON THE ARTICU "SOMF: EXPERIMENTAL n-person GAMES" ' R. Duncan Luce

5.2 A characterization of the nonemptiness of the core

BIPARTITE GRAPHS AND THE SHAPLEY VALUE

Game Theory. Lecture Notes By Y. Narahari. Department of Computer Science and Automation Indian Institute of Science Bangalore, India November 2007

The assignment game: core, competitive equilibria and multiple partnership

COOPERATIVE GAME THEORY: CORE AND SHAPLEY VALUE

On the Balancedness of m-sequencing Games

SANDWICH GAMES. July 9, 2014

Solutions without dummy axiom for TU cooperative games

Incentives to form the grand coalition versus no incentive to split off from the grand coalition

Majority Decision Rules with Minority Protections: Cost Assignments for Public Projects

Question 1. (p p) (x(p, w ) x(p, w)) 0. with strict inequality if x(p, w) x(p, w ).

Cooperative Games. Stéphane Airiau. Institute for Logic, Language & Computations (ILLC) University of Amsterdam

Cooperative Games. M2 ISI Systèmes MultiAgents. Stéphane Airiau LAMSADE

Zero-Sum Games Public Strategies Minimax Theorem and Nash Equilibria Appendix. Zero-Sum Games. Algorithmic Game Theory.

A Farsighted Stable Set for Partition Function Games

Cowles Foundation for Research in Economics at Yale University

Expectation Formation Rules and the Core of Partition Function Games

NOTES ON COOPERATIVE GAME THEORY AND THE CORE. 1. Introduction

Cooperative assignment games with the inverse Monge property

The Coordinate-Wise Core for Multiple-Type Housing Markets is Second-Best Incentive Compatible

a i,1 a i,j a i,m be vectors with positive entries. The linear programming problem associated to A, b and c is to find all vectors sa b

Farsighted stability of collusive price leadership. Yoshio Kamijo and Shigeo Muto Discussion Paper No

Answers to Spring 2014 Microeconomics Prelim

64 P. ERDOS AND E. G. STRAUS It is possible that (1.1) has only a finite number of solutions for fixed t and variable k > 2, but we cannot prove this

Interval values for strategic games in which players cooperate

Existence of Optimal Strategies in Markov Games with Incomplete Information

On the Shapley-Scarf Economy: The Case of Multiple Types of Indivisible Goods

The core of voting games: a partition approach

Expectation Formation Rules and the Core of Partition Function Games

2.1 Definition and graphical representation for games with up to three players

Lower Bounds for q-ary Codes with Large Covering Radius

Department of Applied Mathematics Faculty of EEMCS. University of Twente. Memorandum No Owen coalitional value without additivity axiom

ECONOMIC STRENGTH IN COOPERATIVE GAMES

Weighted values and the Core in NTU games

Subgame Perfect Equilibria in Stage Games

Could Nash equilibria exist if the payoff functions are not quasi-concave?

The Distribution of Optimal Strategies in Symmetric Zero-sum Games

Solutions to Exercises of Section IV.1.

Implementation of the Ordinal Shapley Value for a three-agent economy 1

AVERAGE TREE SOLUTION AND SUBCORE FOR ACYCLIC GRAPH GAMES

A RECURSIVE CORE FOR PARTITION FUNCTION FORM GAMES

האוניברסיטה העברית בירושלים

CORE AND NO-TREAT EQUILIBRIUM IN TOURNAMENT GAMES WITH EXTERNALITIES

ENCOURAGING THE GRAND COALITION IN CONVEX COOPERATIVE GAMES

Boundary Behavior of Excess Demand Functions without the Strong Monotonicity Assumption

f Wi; (x) I dfi< x i=1,.,m; j= 1,...,I MINIMAL COMPLETE CLASS OF DECISION FUNCTIONS WHEN THE CHARACTERIZATION OF THE

Assignment Games with Externalities

Algorithmic Game Theory and Applications. Lecture 4: 2-player zero-sum games, and the Minimax Theorem

Mixed Refinements of Shapley s Saddles and Weak Tournaments

A partial characterization of the core in Bertrand oligopoly TU-games with transferable technologies

Weighted Voting Games

NEGOTIATION-PROOF CORRELATED EQUILIBRIUM

April 25 May 6, 2016, Verona, Italy. GAME THEORY and APPLICATIONS Mikhail Ivanov Krastanov

Combinatorial Agency of Threshold Functions

Monotonic ɛ-equilibria in strongly symmetric games

Problems and Solutions

Stackelberg oligopoly TU-games: characterization of the core and 1-concavity of the dual game

Players Indifferent to Cooperate and Characterizations of the Shapley Value

A simple algorithm for the nucleolus of airport profit games

Converse consistency and the constrained equal benefits rule in airport problems

The Core and Coalition Formation in an N-person Network Game *

Core. Ichiro Obara. December 3, 2008 UCLA. Obara (UCLA) Core December 3, / 22

princeton univ. F 13 cos 521: Advanced Algorithm Design Lecture 17: Duality and MinMax Theorem Lecturer: Sanjeev Arora

Online Interval Coloring and Variants

The Folk Theorem for Finitely Repeated Games with Mixed Strategies

About partial probabilistic information

in Search Advertising

Today: Linear Programming (con t.)

NOTE. A 2 2 Game without the Fictitious Play Property

Equivalent Bilevel Programming Form for the Generalized Nash Equilibrium Problem

A Cooperative Approach to Queue Allocation of Indivisible Objects

The Max-Convolution Approach to Equilibrium Models with Indivisibilities 1

Static Models of Oligopoly

The Bargaining Set of an Exchange Economy with Discrete. Resources

Coalitional Structure of the Muller-Satterthwaite Theorem

Zero sum games Proving the vn theorem. Zero sum games. Roberto Lucchetti. Politecnico di Milano

Discrete Applied Mathematics

Multimarket Oligopolies with Restricted Market Access

VALUES OF NON-ATOMIC GAMES, IV: THE VALUE AND THE CORE

Self-stabilizing uncoupled dynamics

Representation of TU games by coalition production economies

Avoider-Enforcer games played on edge disjoint hypergraphs

Strategy-Proofness and the Core in House Allocation Problems

Contractually Stable Networks

No-envy in Queueing Problems

ASYMPTOTIC VALUE OF MIXED GAMES*

Recognizing single-peaked preferences on aggregated choice data

A Nash Equilibrium Solution for the Discrete Two-Person Cost Sharing Problem

Advanced Microeconomics

On Hotelling s Stability in Competition

Department of Applied Mathematics Faculty of EEMCS. University of Twente. Memorandum No. 1796

Algorithmic Strategy Complexity

Aumann-Shapley Values on a Class of Cooperative Fuzzy Games

Convex Sets with Applications to Economics

The decomposability of simple orthogonal arrays on 3 symbols having t + 1 rows and strength t

Convexity of Bertrand oligopoly TU-games with differentiated products

Dynamic Coalitional TU Games: Distributed Bargaining among Players Neighbors

Power in the US Legislature

The core of voting games with externalities

Transcription:

Symmetric Solutions of Some Production Economies By SERGIU HART 1) '-, Abstract,' A symmetric n-person game (n, k) (for positive integer k) is defined in its characteristic function form by v(s) = 8 Ilk], where 181 is the number of players in the coalition 8 and [xl denotes U the largest integer not greater than x, (i.e., any k players, but not less, can "produce" one unit). It is proved that in any imputation in any symmetric von Neumann-Morgenstern solution.of such a game, a blocking coalition of p = n - k + 1 players who receive the largest payoffs is formed, and their payoffs are always equal. Conditions for existence and uniqueness of,such symmetric solutions with the other k - 1 payoffs equal too are proved; other cases are discussed thereafter. 1. Introduction Tl1e purpose of this paper is the determination of symmetric von Neumann- Morgenstern soluti9ns to a family of symmetric n-person games. Let it and k be positive integers with 2 ::; k ::; n, and let q be the unique integer satisfying ~ q k ::; n < (q + l)k. (1) Define an n-person game (n, k) by 0, 1, 2, Is 1< k, k::; Is 1 < 2k, 2k::;ISI<3k, v(s) = (2) j, jk::; Is I < (j + l)k, q, qk::;lsl, where v(s) is the characteristic function of the game, and IS Idenotes the numbcr of players in S. The motivation for studying this kind of game comes from economics. Consider an economy consisting of n persons, each of them initially owning one unit of some raw material. This raw material may be used to construct a certain consumer product, but it can only be produced in batches. For the production of one unit of the consumer product, k units of the raw material are needed; but with less than k units of the raw material, nothing can be produced. 1) SERGIU HART, Department of Mathematical Sciences, Tel Aviv University, Tel Aviv, Israel.

54 SERGIU HART This kind of economy embodies in perhaps the most elemental form the problems of production in which the returns to scale are not constant or decreasing, and more specifically, the problems of set-up costs. Such economies have defied treatment by more conventional concepts of game theory and economics, such as the core, the competitive equilibrium, and so on. Though, of course, the games considered here are far from being the most general such production economies, we feel that they embody some of their most typical features, and that the study of these games may well lead to insights that will generalize to much larger classes. of production economies. For q = 1, we get a class of games whose unique symmetric solutions were found by BOTT [1953]. Hence we are interested by the games (n, k) with q ~ 2. Let p = n - k + 1. Then a v-player coalition is a "minimal blocking coalition" (i.e., the smallest one which is large enough to block its complement from getting anything). The solution of Bott was based on such coalitions: all the players divide into disjoint p-player coalitions; the remaining players get nothing, and all the members of a particular blocking coalition receive the same amount. For q ~ 2, there is only one2) blocking coalition, and it has, too, an essential role in the symmetric solutions. Without loss of generality, we will denote the players 1,2,..., n, and let N = {1, 2,..., n} be the set of all players. An imputation a is an n-dimensional vector (al,a2,'",an) satisfying (i) ai ~ 0 = v({i}) for all i(l ::; i::; n), and (ii) n L ai S q = v(n). i= 1. A set U of imputations is called symmetric if it contains all imputations arising from permutations of the indices of any imputation in U. A symmetric set which is a solution is a symmetric solution. In Theorem 1 we prove that in any. symmetric solution to a game (n, k) (with q ~ 2), the largest p coordinates of any imputation are equal. This motivates us to pay special attention to imputations with thep largest coordinates equal and the other k - 1 coordinates also equal. Let V be the symmetric set 3) consisting of all such imputations whose largest coordinate is ~ 1/1" In Theorem 2 we prove that V is a symmetric solution to the game (n, k) (with q ~ 2) if and only if n ~ (q + l)(k - 1). Moreover, whenever n ~ (q + l)k - 3, the set V is also the unique symmetric solution-this is proved in Theorem 3. To illustrate these theorems, consider the two conditions (i) n ~ (q + l)(k - 1), (ii) n ~ (q + l)k - 3. 2) i.e., the maximal number of disjoint blocking coalitions that can be formed is onc. 3) From now on, when we refer to V we will always mean this particular set.

Symmetric Solutions of Some Production Economies 55 Note that (i) holds for q z k - 1 (since n z qk by (1)), and (i) implies (ii) always (since q z 2); moreover (i) is equivalent to (ii) for q = 2. Thus, if we take a constant k, for n z (k - 1)2, V is always a symmetric solution, and this is true also for some smaller n. E.g., if k = 7, then V is a symmetric solution for the nthat are underlined, and is known to be unique for the n that are double underlined in the following table: 14,15,16, 17, ~,!2,~, 21,22,23,~,~,~,~, 28, 29, ~, J}, ~, ~, 3j, 35,19, 3.], ~, ~, 1Q,1J, ~,4},41,~,1,1J,1, 42, 5..9,~,~,~,~,~, (q = 2) (q = 3) (q = 4) (q = 5) (q = 6) (q = 7) We will note that in the case (n,k) is a zero-sum game, i.e. when n = (q + 1)k - 1, it was already known that V is a symmetric solution (see GELBAUM[1959J, Theorem 3.1); but its uniqueness is proved only here. 2. Preliminaries An ordered imputation a is an imputation satisfying al Z a2 Z... z an, Thus a symmetric set is characterized by its ordered imputations. We will redefine the concept of domination for ordered imputations. Let a, b be ordered imputatations. Then a> b (a dominates b via S over T) where S = {ii, i2,..., im) C N SIT and T = {jl,j2,...,jm} en, if (i) I air> bjr for 1 S r s m, and (ii) I ai S v(s) ("efficiency"). ~ ies We write a > b (a dominates b) if there are Sand T such that a > b. 0 SIT In all our proofs we need to decide whether or not at least one member of a symmetric set U of imputations dominates a given imputation b. This is equivalent to the problem of deciding whether some ordered imputation a in U dominates 4) the ordered imputation b' that we get from b. Hence we can deal only with ordere'd imputations. From now on, domination will always be according to the above definition. We will first prove a simple but useful lemma: 4) Domination between ordered imputations.

56 SERGIU HART Lemma: Let a, b be ordered imputations, such that a ~ b via SiT, Then there are coalitions S* and T* such that a ~ b via S* IT*,and IS* I= IT*I = k. Proof: Let Is 1= IT I = m, thenjk::; m < (j + 1)k (for somej ~ 1), hence v(s) j j 1 W=-;;::; jk ="k' '-. Let S = {il,i2,...,im} and T = {j1,j2,...,jm} (with the correspondence ir<.-4jr by air> bj. Without loss of generality let il > i2 >... > im, hence ail ::; ail ::; ::;... ::; aim' Let S* = {ii' i2,..., ik} and T* = {j I,j2,..,,jk}' Then air> bjr for 1 ::; r ::; k, and S* is effective for a since 3. The Theorems and their Proofs k k L a; ::; - L a; ::; v(s) ::; 1 = v(s*), ies' m ies WI JJ I We are ready now to state exactly and prove our results, Q.E.D. Theorem 1 : Let U be a symmetric solution to the game (n, k) for q ;?: 2, Let a be an ordered imputation in U, Then where p = n - k + 1. al=a2=...=ap, Proof: Suppose that aid > aid+ I for some, 1 ::; io ::; p - 1. Let b be the ordered imputation given by bi = ai + B, for i =f io, and bid= aid- (n - 1)B, where B > 0 is small enough so that bid> bio+i' Let S = T = {p,p+. 1,...,n}. Then b ~ a via SIT(\SI = ITI = k, and S is effective for b since Lbi::; ~ t bi k ies n,i=1 = -. q ::; 1 = v(s». Hence b ~ U, and therefore there exists anoth~[ordered n -. imputation c in U such that c ~ b.. By the previous lemma, the domination is via k-player coalitions. For b we can take without loss of generality the smallest k coordinates bp, bp-1;.1,.." bn. As for c, let {ii' i2,..., ik} be the dominating set: Cir > bp+r-i for r=1,2,...,k,

Symmetric Solutions of Some Production Economies 57 But bp+r-1 = ap+r-1 + /; for all r (1 ::; r ::; k) since io < p, hence cir>ap+r-1 for r=1,2,...,k. I.e., c>- a via {i1, i2,..., ik}i{p,p + 1,..., n}, which contradicts a and c are members of the solution U. the fact that both Q.E.D. The next theorem gives the necessary and sufficient condition for V to be a solution. Theorem 2.. The symmetric set V generated by all the ordered imputations a satisfying and a1 = a2 =... = ap = IX1, (3) ap+ 1 = ap+2 =... = an = IX2, (4) IX1~ 11k is a symmetric solution to the game (n, k) (with q ~ 2), if and only if n ~ (q + 1)(k - 1). Proof: Unless we indicate otherwise, a symbol of the form (IX1"'" IX1,IX2,...; IX2)will denote (IX1"",0(1,IX2,...,IX2) ' r--' ' v ', p k - 1 i.e. the imputation whose first p coordinates are 0(1 and whose last k - 1 coordinates are 0(2' First we will prove that whenever (6) is satisfied, V is a symmetric solution to the game. / Suppose a and b are ordered imputations in V, and a >- b. From the lemma, itfollows thatthe domination is viak-g\ayercoalitions. Leta = (0(1,...,0(1,0(2,...,0(2) and b = (/31,...,/31,/32,...,/32)' Then at least one of the dominated coordinates is /31' hence 0(1 > /31' Since pix1 + (k - 1)0(2 = q = P/31+ (k - 1)/32';we must have 0(2< /32' hence all the dominating coordinates are 0(1' By effectiveness ko(l ::; 1 or 0(1::; 11k, so /31 < 11k, which contradicts (5) for b. Therefore, the set V is internally consistent.. To prove that the set V is extradominative, we will use the fact that for any a = (0(1,...,0(1' IX2"'" 0(2)in V, a coalition of k - 1 O(l'S and one 0(2 is efficient: (5) (6) (k - 1)0(1 + 0(2 ::; 1. (7) Forq::; k - 1, thisfollowsfrom(6):n ~ (q + 1)(k - 1)hencep = n - (k - 1) ~ q(k - 1) and (k - 1)0(1+ 0(2 = [q(k - 1)0(1 + q0(2j/q ::; [P0(1 + (k - 1)0(2J/q= 1.

58 SERGIU HART For q > k - 1 we get q(k - l)al + qa2 = q(k - l)al + (q - k + 1)a2 + (k - 1)a2 s (qk - k + l)al + (k - l)ai s pal + (k - 1)a2 = q and so (7) is proved. Now let b be any imputation not in V. We will show that it is dominated by some imputation a in V. We have two cases: Case 1: bp < l/k. Define al = l/k and a2 such that pal + (k - 1)a2 = (al,...,al,a2,...,a2)ev dominates b via k at's. q, then a = Case 2: bp 2: l/k. Since b ~ V, (3) or (4) are not satisfied, hence n pbp + (k - l)bn < L bi = q. i = 1 Let 0 < 6 = [q - (pbp + (k - l)bn)]/n, and define al = bp + 6 and a2 = bn + 6. Then a = (al,...,al",a2,...,a2) is an ordered imputation in V, and a>-b via k - 1 at's (which dominate bp,bp+1,...,bn-1) and one a2 (which dominates bn), the effectiveness being ensured by (7). Hence V is a symmetric solution. Now we prove the converse. It will follow from the fact that if(6) is not satisfied, the set V does not dominate all imputations outside V. Let b be the ordered imputation defined by b =b =...=b =- 1 2 I' k-1' b 1'+1- - b 1'+2 - -'-... - bn-1 - bn = 0 1 1 k - 2 [q p - ~ ' ] and (k > 2 otherwise (6) holds). But q - > 0 (this is equivalent to the converse k ~ 1 of (6)), i.e. bn-l > bn, hence b ~ V. Let a = (al,...,al,a2,...,a2) be an ordered imputation in V such that a >-b; without loss of generality, let bp,bp+l,...,bn be the k dominated coordinates. Then al > bp = k ~ 1 hence (k - l)al > 1, which implies that there are at most k - 2 at's in the dominating coalition. Hence there are at least two a2's, which dominate bn,bn-l' therefore a2 > bn-l' But this leads to a contradiction, for q = pal + (k - 1)a2 > pbp"+ (k - l)bn-l p k-1 =k"=t+ k-2 q-k"=t [ p ]

Symmetric Solutions of Some ProducllUn Economies 59 =q+~ k-2 [ q-~ k-1 J >q the last inequality again following from n < (q + 1)(k - 1). Hence b is not dominated by any member of V, which proves that V cannot be a solution. Q.E.D. Now we come to the uniqueness theorem. Theorem 3 : Let V be the symmetric set generated by all ordered imputations satisfying (3)-(5). If n ;;::(q + 1)k - 3 (8) then V is the unique symmetric solution to the game (n,k) (with q ;;::2). Proof: Let U be a symmetric solution to the game. By Theorem 1, if a is any ordered imputation in U, then al = a2 =... = ap = 1X1'Suppose aio > aio+1 for p + 1 :::; io :::;n - 1. Define an ordered imputation b.by bi = ai +, for i t io, and big = aio - (n - 1), where > 0 is small enough so t~at big > big+ l' Then b >-a via SiT, where S = T= {p -1,p,...,io -1,io + 1,...,n}. The effectiveness of this coalition for b follows from. b 1 + b2 +... + bk ;;:: bk+l + bk+2 +... + b2k ;;:: b(q-2)k+l + b(q-2)k+2 +... + b(q-l)k-l + big 2 bp-l + bp +... + bio-l + bio+l +... + bn. l'he rows are disjoint (the last two because (q - 1)k - 1 :::;n - k - 1 = n p - 2 < P - 1); the sum of all q rows is at most I bi = q, hence the last onds :::; 1. i= 1 Therefore, b r/=u, and there exists an ordered imputation c in U such that c >- b. By Theorem 1, Cl = C2 =... = cp = Yl' From (8), we get qk - 2 :::; P = n - k + 1, hence (k - 1)Yl + Cp+2:::;[q(k - 1)Yt + 2Cp+2J/q :::;[(qk - ~)Yl +i=t+/i}q:::; 1. (9) coalition. There are then two possibili- Let i be the largest index in the dominating ties:

60 SERGIU HART Case 1: i S P + 1. Then the dominating coordinates must be }'1,"" }'1,Ci, and hence }'1 > bp = (J(1 + 8 > (J(1 }'1 > bp+1 = ap+1 + 8 > ap+1 }'1 > bio = aio - (n - 1)8 Ci > bn = an + 8 > an, Instead of bio we can take bp-1 = (J(1 + B (because of the inequality in the first. line), and we get c >-a (via the same coalition for c, and {p -l,p,...,io -1, io + 1,..., n} for a), which is a contradiction because a, C E U. Case 2: i ~ P + 2. Then in the dominating coalition, we can change the first k - 1 coordinates to }'1 (since Ci S cp+z, it follows from (9) that it is still efficient), and proceed as in Case 1. In any case we got a contradiction, hence ap+1 = ap+z =... (J(z, = an = i.e. any ordered imputation in U satisfies (3) and (4). Let b be an ordered imputation in V, i.e. satisfying (3), (4) and (5). Then no ordered imputation a satisfying (3) and (4) can dominate it (see the proof of the internal consistency of V in Theorem 2: if a >- b, where a and b satisfy (3) and (4), then (J(1 > P1 ~ llk because (5) is fulfilled by b; hence both a and b are in V and this contradicts a >- b). Hence no a in U dominates b, therefore b E U, arid V C U. But V is a solution, so every a E U\V is dominated by some be Vc U, hence U\ V must be empty (otherwise a >- b, where a, be U). Hence U = V, and V is the unique symmetric solution. Q.E.D. 4. Discussion Two problems are still open: (i) what are the symmetric solutions, if any, to the game (n,k) when (6) is not satisfied, and (ii) is V the unique symmetric solution when (6) but not (8) are satisfied. The following two examples indicate that the answers are much more com~ plicated than the theorems proved here. First, let n = 17 and k = 7 (hence V is not a solution). It can be easily checked that the unique symmetric solution is the symmetric set generated by all the ordered imputations ~~,O), where 3 (J(1 2 19s sit' and 11 5

Symmetric Solutions of Some Production Economies 61 1 32 (0:1,...,0:1,0:2,...,0:2), where _ 7 S 0:1 S 209' ~ '--v ' 11 6 Even more interesting is the second example: n = 23 and k = 10. Then all the ordered imputations 3 1 (0:1,...;0:1,0:2,...,0:2,0,0), where _ ~ '---v c-' 28 SiX1S- 7 ' 14 7 ( 5 5 1 1,49"~"49',J4":"14:0, ) 14 8 ( 19 19 1 1 ~',14"~"14, )' 14 9 generate a symmetric solution to the game. Note that in the last imputation, the largest coordinate is less than llk. By a similar method to that used in the proof of Theorem 3, it can be proved that whenever n = (q + 1)k - m (for 4 S m S k), all the smallest k - 1coordinates but the last m - 3 must be equal in any imputation in any symmetric solution. Further results were also obtained regarding the uniqueness of V (and of other solutions, as above), but they still do not cover all the cases.. As to the economic meaning of the results, two facts are important. First - the v-player coalition that is formed, whose members receive the largest payoffs. This illustrates the "exploitation" process of the small an~ powerless economic agents (here, k - 1 players who a priori can get nothing) by the powerful ones, and indicates that some kind of cartel is formed. Second - the strong competition between the p largest players, that implies the equality of their payoffs (and this is true for any symmetric solution). It is interesting that most of the players (P) receive the same payoff, which is different from the case of the games of BOTT [1953]. This leads to the conclusion that the competition is strong when there are at least two units, and this is similar to other results in the theory of economic games (e.g., SHITOVITZand SHAPLEY [1961J, etc.). and Acknowledgement I wish to acknowledge the help of Professor R. J. AUMANN,who first pointed out these problems and whose conversations guided their solution.

62 SERGIU HART References BOTT, R.: Symmetric Solutions to Majority Games. Annals of Mathematics Studies 28,319-323,1953. GELDAUM, B. R.: Symmetric Zero-Sum n-person Games, Annals of Mathematics Studies 40,95-109, 1959. YON NEUMANN, J., and O. MORGENSTERN: Theory of Games and Economic Behavior. Princeton University Press, 1944. SHAPLEY, L. S.: Values of Large Games, III: A Corporation with Two Large Stockholders. Memorandum RM-2650-PR, The Rand Corporation, December 1961. SHITOYITZ, B.: Oligopoly in Markets with a Continuum of Traders. To appear in Econometrica. Received June, 1972.