Hicksian Demand and Expenditure Function Duality, Slutsky Equation

Similar documents
Properties of Walrasian Demand

Econ 121b: Intermediate Microeconomics

GARP and Afriat s Theorem Production

Structural Properties of Utility Functions Walrasian Demand

Consumer Theory. Ichiro Obara. October 8, 2012 UCLA. Obara (UCLA) Consumer Theory October 8, / 51

Utility Maximization Problem

Utility Maximization Problem. Advanced Microeconomic Theory 2

Economics 121b: Intermediate Microeconomics Midterm Suggested Solutions 2/8/ (a) The equation of the indifference curve is given by,

Week 7: The Consumer (Malinvaud, Chapter 2 and 4) / Consumer November Theory 1, 2015 (Jehle and 1 / Reny, 32

Advanced Microeconomic Theory. Chapter 2: Demand Theory

Revealed Preferences and Utility Functions

Notes I Classical Demand Theory: Review of Important Concepts

Econ 5150: Applied Econometrics Empirical Demand Analysis. Sung Y. Park CUHK

Last Revised: :19: (Fri, 12 Jan 2007)(Revision:

Rice University. Answer Key to Mid-Semester Examination Fall ECON 501: Advanced Microeconomic Theory. Part A

Notes on Consumer Theory

Applications I: consumer theory

The Fundamental Welfare Theorems

Week 9: Topics in Consumer Theory (Jehle and Reny, Chapter 2)

Microeconomics II Lecture 4. Marshallian and Hicksian demands for goods with an endowment (Labour supply)

i) This is simply an application of Berge s Maximum Theorem, but it is actually not too difficult to prove the result directly.

Chapter 1 Consumer Theory Part II

Consumer theory Topics in consumer theory. Microeconomics. Joana Pais. Fall Joana Pais

Microeconomics, Block I Part 1

Competitive Consumer Demand 1

Maximum Value Functions and the Envelope Theorem

Midterm #1 EconS 527 Wednesday, February 21st, 2018

Microeconomic Theory-I Washington State University Midterm Exam #1 - Answer key. Fall 2016

Recitation #2 (August 31st, 2018)

Microeconomic Theory: Lecture 2 Choice Theory and Consumer Demand

Duality. for The New Palgrave Dictionary of Economics, 2nd ed. Lawrence E. Blume

Recitation 2-09/01/2017 (Solution)

Alp Simsek (MIT) Recitation Notes: 1. Gorman s Aggregation Th eorem2. Normative Representative November 9, Household Theorem / 16

Part 2C. 3. Slutsky Equations Slutsky Slutsky Own-Price Effects

Problem set 2 solutions Prof. Justin Marion Econ 100M Winter 2012

EconS 501 Final Exam - December 10th, 2018

Advanced Microeconomic Analysis, Lecture 6

Chapter 4. Maximum Theorem, Implicit Function Theorem and Envelope Theorem

Lecture 1. History of general equilibrium theory

Microeconomic Theory -1- Introduction

Course Handouts ECON 4161/8001 MICROECONOMIC ANALYSIS. Jan Werner. University of Minnesota

1 Theory of the Firm: Topics and Exercises

First Welfare Theorem

Notes IV General Equilibrium and Welfare Properties

Econ Slides from Lecture 14

E 600 Chapter 4: Optimization

Second Welfare Theorem

Problem Set 5: Expenditure Minimization, Duality, and Welfare 1. Suppose you were given the following expenditure function: β (α

Final Exam - Math Camp August 27, 2014

Monotone comparative statics Finite Data and GARP

= 2 = 1.5. Figure 4.1: WARP violated

Seminars on Mathematics for Economics and Finance Topic 5: Optimization Kuhn-Tucker conditions for problems with inequality constraints 1

Mathematical Appendix

On the (Non-)Differentiability of the Optimal Value Function When the Optimal Solution Is Unique

Differentiable Welfare Theorems Existence of a Competitive Equilibrium: Preliminaries

The Ohio State University Department of Economics. Homework Set Questions and Answers

Advanced Microeconomics

Introductory Microeconomics

PhD Qualifier Examination

Economics 101. Lecture 2 - The Walrasian Model and Consumer Choice

Mathematical Foundations -1- Constrained Optimization. Constrained Optimization. An intuitive approach 2. First Order Conditions (FOC) 7

EC487 Advanced Microeconomics, Part I: Lecture 2

Advanced Microeconomics Fall Lecture Note 1 Choice-Based Approach: Price e ects, Wealth e ects and the WARP

Advanced Microeconomics I: Consumers, Firms and Markets Chapters 1+2

Advanced Microeconomics

Microeconomic Theory I Midterm

Microeconomics II. MOSEC, LUISS Guido Carli Problem Set n 3

Week 5 Consumer Theory (Jehle and Reny, Ch.2)

Preference and Utility

ECON501 - Vector Di erentiation Simon Grant

Solutions to selected exercises from Jehle and Reny (2001): Advanced Microeconomic Theory

Advanced Microeconomic Analysis Solutions to Midterm Exam

Week 10: Theory of the Firm (Jehle and Reny, Chapter 3)

1. Suppose preferences are represented by the Cobb-Douglas utility function, u(x1,x2) = Ax 1 a x 2

Microeconomic Theory I Midterm October 2017

EE290O / IEOR 290 Lecture 05

AGRICULTURAL ECONOMICS STAFF PAPER SERIES

Microeconomics I Fall 2007 Prof. I. Hafalir

Midterm Exam, Econ 210A, Fall 2008

Chapter 8: Slutsky Decomposition

Microeconomics. Joana Pais. Fall Joana Pais

Microeconomic Analysis

The Envelope Theorem

Beyond CES: Three Alternative Classes of Flexible Homothetic Demand Systems

Solution Homework 1 - EconS 501

Introduction to General Equilibrium: Framework.

Lecture Notes for Chapter 12

Beyond CES: Three Alternative Classes of Flexible Homothetic Demand Systems

Generalized Convexity in Economics

GS/ECON 5010 section B Answers to Assignment 1 September Q1. Are the preferences described below transitive? Strictly monotonic? Convex?

Ph.D. Preliminary Examination MICROECONOMIC THEORY Applied Economics Graduate Program May 2012

Advanced Microeconomic Theory. Chapter 6: Partial and General Equilibrium

1.3 The Indirect Utility Function

1 + x 1/2. b) For what values of k is g a quasi-concave function? For what values of k is g a concave function? Explain your answers.

Final Examination with Answers: Economics 210A

The Fundamental Welfare Theorems

CHAPTER 4: HIGHER ORDER DERIVATIVES. Likewise, we may define the higher order derivatives. f(x, y, z) = xy 2 + e zx. y = 2xy.

Econometrics Lecture 10: Applied Demand Analysis

3. Neoclassical Demand Theory. 3.1 Preferences

DECISIONS AND GAMES. PART I

Transcription:

Hicksian Demand and Expenditure Function Duality, Slutsky Equation Econ 2100 Fall 2017 Lecture 6, September 14 Outline 1 Applications of Envelope Theorem 2 Hicksian Demand 3 Duality 4 Connections between Walrasian and Hicksian demand functions. 5 Slutsky Decomposition: Income and Substitution Effects

Envelope Theorem With Constraints The maximization problem is: x (q) = arg max φ(x; q) F (x;q)=0 k Using the Chain Rule, the change of φ (q) = φ(x (q); q) is: D q φ(x (q); q) = D q φ(x, q) q=q, x=x (q) + D xφ(x, q) q=q, x=x (q) D qx (q) Because the constraints hold, F (x; q) = 0 k and thus D x F (x; q)d q x (q) =D q F (x; q) From FOC we get D x φ(x; q) = λ D x F (x; q) Thus, D x φ(x, q) q=q, x=x (q) D qx (q) =λ D x F (x; q)d q x (q) = λ D q F (x; q) Envelope Theorem With Constraints Then, the change in the objective function due to a change in q is: D q φ(x (q); q) = D q φ(x, q) q=q,x=x (q) (λ (q)) D q F (x, q) q=q,x=x ( q)

Envelope Theorem (With Constraints) Summary The Envelope Theorem is: D q φ(x (q); q) = D q φ(x, q) q=q, x=x (q) (λ (q)) D q F (x, q) q=q, x=x(q) The direct effect of the parameter q is on both the value of φ evaluated at the maximizer x (q) but also on the constraints. In the consumer s problem, the entire differential effect of price and wage changes on indirect utility occurs via the budget constraint. φ is the utility function u, and φ(x ( ); ) is u(x ( )) (the indirect utility function v(p, w )) F is the budget constraint p x w ; one can then figure out how the equality above would work if (some) prices and income change. Exercise Compute the price effects, x (p,w ) function on R 2 +. with k = 1, 2 for the Cobb Douglas utility

Application: Roy s Identity Walrasian demand is x (q) = arg max u(x) subject to p x w = 0 v p i Use the previous results with φ(x, q) = u(x), φ(x ( q); q) = u(x (p, w)) = v(p, w), and F (x, q) = p x w. the effect of prices and wage on utility is only via the budget constraint. The Envelope theorem says: D q φ(x ( q); q) = D q φ(x, q) x=x (q),q= q [λ ( q)] D q F (x, q) x=x ( q),q= q Thus = u p i x=x (p,w ) v w = u w λ (p x w ) p i x=x (p,w ) λ=λ (p,w ) x=x (p,w ) λ (p x w ) w = 0 λx i λ=λ (p,w ) = λ (p, w )xi (p, w ) x=x (p,w ) λ=λ (p,w ) x=x (p,w ) = 0+ λ λ=λ (p,w ) =λ (p, w ) x=x (p,w ) the Lagrange multiplier equals the marginal utility of a change in income. Divide one of the two expressions above by the other and obtain xi (p, w) = v p i. v w This is expression gives Roy s Identity: v p i = x i (p, w) v w.

Definition Hicksian Demand Given a utility function u : R n + R, the Hicksian demand correspondence h : R n ++ u(r n +) R n + is defined by h (p, v) = arg min p x subject to u(x) v. x R n + Hicksian demand finds the cheapest consumption bundle that achieves a given utility level. Hicksian demand is also called compensated since along it one can measure the impact of price changes for fixed utility. Walrasian demand x (p, w ) is also called uncompensated since along it price changes can make the consumer better-off or worse-off. Draw a picture. The constraint is in utils while the objective function is in money. For Walrasian (uncompensated) demand, the constraint is in money while the objective is in utils. This is the dual of the utility maximization problem: the solutions to the two problems are connected when prices are the same.

Properties of Hicksian Demand Proposition If u is continuous, then h (p, v) is nonempty and compact. Proof. By continuity, {x R n + : u(x) v}, the upper contour set of x, is closed. For a suffi ciently large M, the closed set {x R n + : p x M} and the upper contour set of x are not disjoint. Then h (p, v) = arg min p x subject to x R n + The modified constraint set is closed and bounded. u(x) v and p x M... from here on, the proof follows the proof that Walrasian demand is nonempty and compact... (fill in the details as exercise).

Hicksian Demand Is Downward Sloping Law of Demand:. 1 Take two price vectors p and q, and define x = h (p, v) and y = h (q, v) The following is a revealed preference argument: y could have been chosen at prices p but was not, hence y cannot be cheaper than x at prices p. p x p y 2 p (x y) 0 3 x could have been chosen at prices q but was not, hence x cannot be cheaper than y at prices q q x q y 4 q (x y) 0 or q (x y) 0 5 Adding 2. and 4. we get (p q) (x y) 0 6 Choose p and q so that p i q i and p j = q j for all j i: (p i q i ) (x i y i ) 0 A similar result does not hold for Walrasian demand.

The Expenditure Function Definition Given a continuous utility function u : R n + R, the expenditure function e : R n ++ u(r n +) R + is defined by for some x h (p, v). e(p, v) = p x This is the function that tracks the minimized value of the amount spent by the consumer as prices and utility change. Proposition If the utility function is continuous and locally nonsatiated, then the expenditure functions is homogeneous of degree 1 and concave in p. Proof. Question 5, Problem Set 4.

Walrasian and Hicksian Demand Are Equal Proposition Suppose u is continuous and locally nonsatiated. If v > u(0 n ), then: x (p, w) = h (p, v(p, w)); h (p, v) = x (p, e(p, v)). These are sets: the consumption bundles that maximize utility are the same as the consumption bundles that minimize expenditure, provided the constraints of the two problems match up. The income level for the constraint in the utility maximization problem must be w = p x where x h (p, v). The utility level for the constraint in the expenditure minimization problem must be v = u(x ) where x x (p, v). Walrasian and Hicksian demand must coincide when computed according to the same prices, income, and utility. The proposition implies that e(p, v(p, w)) = w and v(p, e(p, v)) = v so for a fixed price vector ^p, e(^p, ) and v(^p, ) are inverses of each other.

Walrasian and Hicksian Demand Are Equal We want to show that x x (p, w) solves min p x subject to u(x) u(x ) We want to show that x h (p, v) solves max u(x) subject to p x p x Proof. Pick x x (p, w), and suppose x / h (p, u(x )): x is a utility maximizer but not expenditure minimizer. Then x s.t. p x < p x w and u(x ) u(x ) By local nonsatiation, x (close to x ) s.t. p x < w and u(x ) > u(x ) contradicting the fact that x is a utility maximizer. Therefore x must also be a expenditure minimizer. Since p x = w by full expenditure, we also have e (p, v(p, w)) = w. Pick x h (p, v), and suppose x / x (p, p x ): x an expenditure minimizer but not a utility maximizer. Then x s.t. u(x ) > u (x ) and p x p x Consider the bundle αx with α < 1. By continuity of u, u(αx ) > u (x ) v for α < 1, α 1. Therefore, p αx < p x p x contradicting the fact that x is an expenditure minimizer. Therefore x must also be a utility maximizer. Because u (x ) = v we have v (p, e(p, v)) = v.

Definition Support Function Given a closed set K R n, the support function µ K : R n R { } is µ K (p) = inf x K p x. It can equal since there might exists x K such that p x becomes unboundedly negative for a closed set. for example: K = {x R 2 : x 1 R, x 2 [0, )}, and p = ( 1, 0). if K is convex (closed and bounded in R n ), the support function is finite. When a set K is convex, one can recover it using the support function: given a p R n, {x R n : p x µ K (p)} is an half space that contains K ; furthermore, K is the intersection of all such half spaces (for all p). If K is not convex, the intersection of all sets {x R n : p x µ K (p)} is the smallest closed convex set containing K (this is called the convex hull). Theorem (Duality Theorem) Let K be a nonempty closed set. There exists a unique x K such that p x = µ K (p) if and only if µ K is differentiable at p. If so, µ K (p) = x. The support function is linear in p. e(p, v) is the support function of the set K = {x R n + : u(x) v}.

Properties of the Expenditure Function Proposition If u(x) is continuous, locally nonsatiated, and strictly quasiconcave, then e(p, v) is differentiable in p. Proof. Immediate from the previous theorem (verify the assumptions hold). Question 6 Problem Set 4 Using the result above and the fact that h (p, v) = x (p, e(p, v)), provide suffi cient conditions for differentiability with respect to p of the indirect utility function, and extend the suffi cient conditions for continuity and differentiability in p of Walrasian demand to Hicksian demand.

Shephard s Lemma Proposition (Shephard s Lemma) Suppose u : R n + R is a continuous, locally nonsatiated, and strictly quasiconcave utility function. Then, for all p R n ++ and v R, h (p, v) = p e(p, v). Hicksian demand is the derivative of the expenditure function. There are diffrent ways to prove Shephard s Lemma: Use the duality theorem. Use the envelope theorem: let φ(x, q) = p x, φ(x (q); q) = e(p, v), and F (x, q) = u(x) v, then: D qφ(x ( q); q) = D qφ(x, q) x=x (q),q= q [λ ( q)] D qf (x, q) x=x ( q),q= q becomes pe(p, v) = h (p, v) 0 since F does not depend on p. Brute force (next slide).

Shephard s Lemma: Proof Proof. We want to show that h (p, v) = p e(p, v). Using the definition, and then the chain rule p e(p, v) = p [p h (p, u)] = h (p, u) + [p D p h (p, u)] The first order conditions of the minimization problem say p = λ p u (h (p, u)) Therefore p e(p, v) = h (p, u) + λ [ p u (h (p, u)) D p h (p, u)] At an optimum, the constraint must bind and so u (h (p, u)) = v Thus p u (h (p, u)) D p h (p, u) = 0 and therefore h (p, v) = p e(p, v). as desired.

Roy s Identity Proposition (Roy s identity) Suppose u is continuous, locally nonsatiated, and strictly quasiconcave and v is differentiable at (p, w) 0. Then x (p, w) = 1 p v(p, w), This can be also written as x k (p, w) = v (p,w ) w v (p,w ) v (p,w ) w, for all k Walrasian demand equals the derivative of the indirect utility function multiplied by a correction term. This correction normalizes by the marginal utility of wealth. There are diffrent ways to prove Roy s Identity Use the envelope theorem (earlier). Use the chain rule and the first order conditions. Brute force (next slide).

Proof. Roy s Identity We want to show that v (p,w ) xk p (p, w) = k v (p,w ) w Fix some p, w and let ū = v ( p, w). The following identity holds for all p v (p, e (p, ū)) = ū differentiating w.r.t p k we get v + v e = 0 w and therefore v + v w h k = 0 Let x k = x k ( p, w) and evaluate the previous equality at p, w: v + v w x k = 0 Solve for x k to get the result.

Definition Slutsky Matrix The Slutsky matrix, denoted D p h (p, v), is the n n matrix of derivative of the Hicksian demand function with respect to price (its first n dimensions). Notice this says function, so the Slutsky matrix is defined only when Hicksian demand is unique. Proposition Suppose u : R n + R is continuous, locally nonsatiated, strictly quasiconcave and h ( ) is continuously differentiable at (p, v). Then: 1 The Slutsky matrix is the Hessian of the expenditure function: D p h (p, v) = D 2 ppe(p, v); 2 The Slutsky matrix is symmetric and negative semidefinite; 3 D p h (p, v)p = 0 n. Proof. Question 8, Problem Set 4.

Proposition Slutsky Decomposition If u is continuous, locally nonsatiated, and strictly quasiconcave, and h is differentiable, then: for all (p, w) D p h (p, v(p, w)) = D p x (p, w) + D w x (p, w)x (p, w) or h j (p, v(p, w)) = x j (p, w) + x j (p, w) xk (p, w), w for all j, k Proof. Remember that h (p, v) = x (p, e(p, v)). Take the equality for good j and differentiate with respect to p k hj = x j + x j e = x j + x j w w h k Evaluate this for some p, w and u = v (p, w) so that h ( ) = x ( ) h j = x j + x j w x k

Slutsky Equation Hicksian decomposition of demand Rearranging from the previous proposition: xj (p, w) = h j (p, v(p, w)) x j (p, w) xk (p, w) p }{{ k w }}{{} substitution effect income effect This is also known as the Slutsky equation: it connects the derivatives of compensated and uncompensated demands. If one takes k = j, the following is the own price Slutsky equation xj (p, w) = h j (p, v(p, w)) x j (p, w) xj (p, w) p j p j w }{{}}{{} substitution effect income effect

Normal, Inferior, and Giffen Goods The own price Slutsky equation x j (p, w) = h j (p, v(p, w)) x j (p, w) xj (p, w). p j p j w }{{}}{{} substitution effect income effect Since the Slutsky matrix is negative semidefinite, h k / 0; the first term is always negative while the second can have either sign; the substitution effect always pushes the consumer to purchase less of a commodity when its price increases. Normal, Inferior, and Giffen Goods A normal good has a positive income affect. An inferior good has a negative income effect. A Giffen good has a negative overall effect (i.e. x k / > 0); this can happen only if the income effect is negative and overwhelms the substitution effect x k w x k < h k 0.

Definition ε y, q = y q q y Slutsky Equation and Elasticity is called the elasticity of y with respect to q Elasticity is a unit free measure (percentage change in y for a given percentage change in q) that is often used to compare price effects across different goods. The own price Slutsky equation x j x j (p, w) = h j (p, v(p, w)) x j (p, w) xj (p, w) p j p j w Multiply both sides by p j /xj ( ) and rewrite as (p, w) p j p j xj (p, w) = h j (p, v(p, w)) p j p j xj (p, w) x j (p, w) w p j w xj (p, w) xj (p, w) w or p j xj (p, w) ε xj, pj = ε hj, pj ε xj, w w The elasticty of Walrasian (uncompensated) demand is equal to the elasticity of Hicksian (compensated) demand minus the income elasticity of demand multiplied by the share that good has in the budget.

Gross Substitutes The cross price Slutsky equation x j (p, w) = h j (p, v(p, w)) x j (p, w) xj (p, w) w Intuitively, we think of two goods as substitutes if the demand for one increases when the price of the other increases. Definition We say good j is a gross substitute for k if x j (p,w ) 0. Unfortunately the definition of substitutes based on Walrasian (uncompensated) demand is not very useful since it does not satisfy symmetry: we can have x j (p,w ) x > 0 and k (p,w ) p j < 0. There is a better definition that is based on Hicksian (compensated) demand.

Definition Net Substitutes We say goods j and k are net substitutes if h j (p,w ) 0 and net complements if h j (p,w ) 0. This definition is symmetric: h j (p,w ) 0 if and only if h k (p,w ) p j 0. Proof. h j (p, w) = e(p,v ) p j = 2 e(p, v) p j = 2 e(p, v) p j = h k (p, w) p j by Shephard s Lemma by Young s Theorem by Shephard s Lemma again

Next Week Testable Implication of Consumer Theory Firm Behavior