Super-Quantum, Non-Signaling Correlations Cannot Exist

Similar documents
Super-Quantum, Non-Signaling Correlations Cannot Exist

arxiv: v2 [quant-ph] 22 Sep 2008

The relation between Hardy s non-locality and violation of Bell inequality

The CHSH game as a Bell test thought experiment

arxiv: v2 [quant-ph] 21 Oct 2013

arxiv: v3 [quant-ph] 20 Jan 2016

Article. Reference. Bell Inequalities for Arbitrarily High-Dimensional Systems. COLLINS, Daniel Geoffrey, et al.

arxiv: v2 [quant-ph] 13 Jan 2011

CAT L4: Quantum Non-Locality and Contextuality

Simulating Maximal Quantum Entanglement without Communication. CERF, N. J., et al. Abstract

Lecture 20: Bell inequalities and nonlocality

arxiv: v2 [quant-ph] 9 Apr 2009

Allen Stairs and Jeffrey Bub Correlations, Contexts and Quantum Logic

Lecture 6 Sept. 14, 2015

arxiv: v3 [quant-ph] 24 Oct 2012

Bell inequality for qunits with binary measurements

arxiv: v1 [quant-ph] 3 Oct 2012

Relation of the Bell inequalities with quantum logic, hidden variables and information theory

Lecture 12c: The range of classical and quantum correlations

The nature of Reality: Einstein-Podolsky-Rosen Argument in QM

Einstein-Podolsky-Rosen paradox and Bell s inequalities

Contextuality and Nonlocality in No Signaling Theories

arxiv:quant-ph/ v3 18 Jun 2005

Interconversion of nonlocal correlations

arxiv: v1 [quant-ph] 7 Jun 2016

arxiv: v2 [quant-ph] 19 Dec 2012

Quantum Correlations: From Bell inequalities to Tsirelson s theorem

Bit-Commitment and Coin Flipping in a Device-Independent Setting

Is Entanglement Sufficient to Enable Quantum Speedup?

KOLMOGOROV s PROBABILITY THEORY IN QUANTUM PHYSICS

A No-Go Result on Common Cause Approaches via Hardy s Paradox

Non-local setting and outcome information for violation of Bell's inequality

EPR Paradox and Bell Inequalities

Gisin s theorem for three qubits Author(s) Jing-Ling Chen, Chunfeng Wu, L. C. Kwek and C. H. Oh Source Physical Review Letters, 93,

Entanglement and non-locality of pure quantum states

A computational proof of locality in entanglement.

arxiv:quant-ph/ v1 15 Jun 1999

The controlled-not (CNOT) gate exors the first qubit into the second qubit ( a,b. a,a + b mod 2 ). Thus it permutes the four basis states as follows:

Odd Things about Quantum Mechanics: Abandoning Determinism In Newtonian physics, Maxwell theory, Einstein's special or general relativity, if an initi

A proof of Bell s inequality in quantum mechanics using causal interactions

arxiv: v4 [math-ph] 28 Aug 2013

Quantum theory without predefined causal structure

Has CHSH-inequality any relation to EPR-argument?

Locality and simultaneous elements of reality

Mathematical and Physical Examination of the Locality Condition in Bell s Theorem

(Non-)Contextuality of Physical Theories as an Axiom

arxiv:quant-ph/ v2 5 May 2003

arxiv: v4 [quant-ph] 28 Feb 2018

Report on Conceptual Foundations and Foils for QIP at the Perimeter Institute, May 9 May

Incompatibility Paradoxes

arxiv: v2 [quant-ph] 19 Jan 2018

Hardy s Paradox. Chapter Introduction

Randomness in nonlocal games between mistrustful players

Quantum measurements and Kolmogorovian probability theory

Spatial versus Sequential Correlations for Random Access Coding

Are there Quantum Effects Coming from Outside Space-Time? Nonlocality, Free Will & no-many-worlds

Bell s Theorem. Ben Dribus. June 8, Louisiana State University

NON HILBERTIAN QUANTUM MECHANICS ON THE FINITE GALOIS FIELD

arxiv: v1 [quant-ph] 23 May 2015

Non-local Boxes. Philippe Lamontagne. July 31, 2014

Stochastic Histories. Chapter Introduction

Bell s inequalities and their uses

Max-Planck-Institut für Mathematik in den Naturwissenschaften Leipzig

arxiv: v1 [quant-ph] 8 Feb 2016

CS286.2 Lecture 15: Tsirelson s characterization of XOR games

Stochastic Quantum Dynamics I. Born Rule

Quantum correlations and group C -algebras

Bell inequality, Bell states and maximally entangled states for n qubits

Logical difficulty from combining counterfactuals in the GHZ-Bell theorems

Logical difficulty from combining counterfactuals in the GHZ-Bell theorems

arxiv: v2 [quant-ph] 11 Nov 2014

Unitary evolution: this axiom governs how the state of the quantum system evolves in time.

Notes on Quantum Logic

Lecture 29 Relevant sections in text: 3.9

Device-Independent Quantum Information Processing

(Quantum?) Processes and Correlations with no definite causal order

Quantum mysteries revisited again

Lecture 14, Thurs March 2: Nonlocal Games

Quantum Entanglement, Quantum Cryptography, Beyond Quantum Mechanics, and Why Quantum Mechanics Brad Christensen Advisor: Paul G.

Research Article Simulation of Equatorial von Neumann Measurements on GHZ States Using Nonlocal Resources

Device-Independent Quantum Information Processing (DIQIP)

Tsirelson s problem and linear system games

MGP versus Kochen-Specker condition in hidden variables theories

Challenges in Quantum Information Science. Umesh V. Vazirani U. C. Berkeley

Why the quantum? - Bananaworld

Joint Distributions and Quantum Nonlocal Models

A history of entanglement

Solving the Einstein Podolsky Rosen puzzle: The origin of non-locality in Aspect-type experiments

Tsirelson s problem and linear system games

ON ARTHUR FINE'S INTERPRETATION QUANTUM MECHANICS

Instantaneous Nonlocal Measurements

Superqubits. Leron Borsten Imperial College, London

arxiv: v2 [quant-ph] 19 Nov 2010

Introduction to Bell s theorem: the theory that solidified quantum mechanics

Non-locality and Communication Complexity

arxiv: v3 [quant-ph] 12 Jan 2011

Entanglement and information

RUNS: A_B, A_B', A'_B,

Nonlocal Quantum XOR Games for Large Number of Players

Sample Problems for all sections of CMSC250, Midterm 1 Fall 2014

Transcription:

Super-Quantum, Non-Signaling Correlations Cannot Exist Pierre Uzan University Paris-Diderot, laboratory SPHERE, History and Philosophy of Science pierre.uzan@paris7.jussieu.fr Abstract Non-local correlations stronger than quantum correlations between two nonsignaling systems cannot exist. The reason is that any physically realizable PRbox that would give rise to such correlations requires to be described in a noncommutative, quantum-like language -which leads to the derivation of the Tsirelson bound. A paradigmatic toy-model of such super-quantum correlations is then considered and it is shown that it suffers from logical inconsistency. Keywords: Super-quantum correlations; Tsirelson bound; PR-boxes. Introduction Some physicists have suggested that non-local correlations stronger than quantum correlations between two sub-systems that cannot exchange any signal are theoretically possible [1]. However, as noted by these same authors, such non-signaling correlations that violate the Tsirelson bound have not yet been observed. Moreover, some indirect arguments have been formulated against the existence of these correlations, by mentioning the multiplication of information they would give rise to [2] or their rather implausible consequences regarding the cost of distributed computation [3]. However, it seems that the absence of experimental data and the latter arguments are not enough to fully convince these physicists of the inexistence of such nonsignaling, super-quantum correlations and the latter continue to explore very seriously their extraordinary consequences, like for example the possibility of non-local computation [1]. 1

Super-quantum correlations have been modeled in terms of boxes. A box, which is the central device of the Bell s game played by two parties [9], can be described by an arithmetic relation between couples of inputs, which can be regarded as the indexes of the two directions (right or left) each of the two parties (Alice and Bob) push her/his joystick, and outputs, which are the possible responses of the box for these actions. Super-quantum correlations between Alice s and Bob s outputs are compactly described by PR-boxes (labeled from the initials of Popescu and Rohrlich), which are defined by the following relation between its two possible inputs (x,y), whose values can be 0 or 1, and its two possible outputs (a,b), whose values are 0 or 1 [4]: a b = x.y, where is the addition modulo 2. In addition, as explained by Popescu [1], the non-signaling property can be implemented by asserting that the PR-boxes should yield couples of outputs with equal probabilities for each of the possible values of the product x.y (since, in this case, one of the parties cannot exploit his/her local information to find out the input of the other party). Explicitly, for x.y = 1, both inputs being equal to 1, the two possible outputs (a = 0 and b =1) and (a =1 and b = 0) must have a probability of occurrence of ½; and when x.y = 0, which means that the two inputs are different, the two possible outcomes (a = 0 and b = 0) and (a =1 and b=1) must also have a probability of occurrence of ½. Non-signaling PR-boxes can then be compactly described by the following relation [5]: (C0) P (a, b / x, y) = ½ if a b = x.y is realized = 0 otherwise. Toy-models that are supposed to satisfy such condition, and which would then show that bipartite super-quantum correlations can really be observed between two non-signaling systems, have even been proposed in recent publications [6-7]. 2

The present article will directly question the consistency of the very idea of super-quantum, non-signaling correlations. A first version of this argument, previously submitted for publication, has been strongly criticized by referees reluctant to its use of the mathematical formalism of operators and Hilbert spaces. The reason given by these physicists is that it is not legitimate to show that such super-quantum correlations cannot exist by appealing to the quantumlike formalism since their possible existence presupposes that this formalism would not be applicable for describing the situation under consideration. However, it seems that the latter presupposition has not received any genuine justification in the literature and there is no reason to assume a priori that a physical situation (such as the Bell s game under consideration) could not be described within this powerful mathematical framework. Actually, as will be shown hereafter, an accurate description of this game (PR-box) requires to be done in a non-commutative language of operators. After reminding the two conditions that should be satisfied by such nonsignaling super-quantum correlations (section I), the necessity to describe this game in a non-commutative, quantum-like language of operators will be justified in section II. This constraint mainly relies on the fact that an accurate description of PR-boxes should clearly distinguish between two properties of the actions that can be performed by the players: on the one hand, the compatibility of Alice s and Bob s actions that can be realized conjointly, and on the other hand the incompatibility of Alice s alternative actions and of Bob s alternative actions. The necessity of describing this game within a quantum-like framework leads to the limitation of the degree of correlation by the Tsirelson bound, which shows that non-signaling, super-quantum correlations cannot exist. Then, in order to clear up a persistent illusion in the community of physicists, the paradigmatic toy-model of such super-quantum correlations proposed by Popescu and Rohrlich, which is often mentioned as an indubitable proof of their 3

existence, will be briefly presented and it will be shown that it cannot do the job since it is based on an inconsistent correlation function (section IV). I. Characteristic properties of super-quantum correlations. Super-quantum, non-signaling correlations correlations satisfy the two following properties: (C1) The assertion that these correlations are more non-local than quantum correlations is expressed by the condition that the CHSH correlation factor between Alice s outcomes A x = a (with a = 0 or 1) of her two possible actions, indexed by x = 0 and x = 1, and Bob s outcomes B y = b (with b = 0 or 1) of his two possible actions y = 0 or 1, which is defined as: R = < C(A 0, B 0 ) + C(A 0, B 1 ) + C(A 1, B 0 ) C(A 1, B 1 ) > is strictly greater (in absolute value) than the Tsirelson bound: R > 2 2. In the definition of R, C(A x, B y ) denotes, for all x and y, the degree of correlation between the outcomes A x = a and B y = b for the joint action (x,y). (C2) The assertion that Alice and Bob cannot exchange signals is, in the language of boxes, expressed by the conditions that the probability that Alice obtains a particular outcome a is independent of the choice of Bob action, when he decides to push his joystick to the right or to the left -that is, this probability is independent of the value of y-, and vice versa [1]: For all possible actions x, x, y, y and for all possible outcomes a,b, b P(a, b / x, y) = b P(a, b / x, y ) a P(a, b / x, y) = a P(a, b / x, y). Denoting the sum on the possible outcomes b by P(a/x, y), the first equality can be more conveniently reformulated as: 4

(1) P (a / x, y) = P (a / x) Similarly, denoting the sum on the possible outputs a by P (b / x, y), the second equality can be more conveniently reformulated as: (2) P (b / x, y) = P (b / y) Let us notice that the non-signaling condition (C2) and the definition (C0) of PR-boxes imply together that the probabilities of obtaining any outcome for Alice or for Bob given any possible action are all equal to ½: (3) P(a/x) = P(b/y) = ½., for all a, b, x and y. For example, P(a/x), which is equal to P (a / x, y) for any y by the nonsignaling condition (C2), equation (2), can be written as: P(a/x) = b P(a, b / x, y), for any y, which is, for any x, equal to ½ according to the definition (C0) of PR-boxes. II. Which language for describing the PR-boxes? It is of essential importance to emphasize that for the physicists who have suggested the possible existence of such super-quantum correlations, the condition (C1) is a priori interpreted classically: the quantities A x, and B y that are involved in R are conceived of as random variables whose values are, respectively, the four possible outcomes for the two possible actions of Alice and Bob. It is then supposed that the quantities A x are mere functions, parametrized by the index of Alice s possible actions (x = 0 or 1), from the set of the responses of the box to the action x, for example { a light switches on, a light does not switches on }, to the set {0; 1} -and similarly for Bob. For example, if Alice chooses to perform the action indexed by 1 and obtains the output 0, the random variable A 1 takes the value 0, that is, A 1 = 0. Accordingly, the degree of correlation C(A x, B y ) between Alice s random variable A x and 5

Bob s random variable B y is defined as the expectation value of the product of these two functions: C(A x, B y) =df <A x B y > a,b P(a, b / x, y) a b. Like for classical mechanics, the set of functions A x and B y, for all x and y, can be endowed with the basic operations (sum, product and multiplication by a real number) and elementary properties (like distributivity, commutativity and existence of a norm), which leads to the structure of a commutative C* algebra of functions. However, this presupposition of classicity is doubtful for several reasons, which are quite similar to those that have led to the introduction and the development of the non-commutative quantum formalism. This game, which, like for quantum phenomena, involves stochastic processes (since the outcome of any action is not uniquely determined but can only be predicted with a certain probability), can be more accurately characterized as follows: 1) Incompatible descriptions: Like quantum phenomena that involve incompatible observables, the game under consideration involves incompatible actions that give rise to incompatible descriptions. Let us call the descriptive sentence Alice has pushed the joystick at right at time t and has obtained the outcome a by (a/0) t and the descriptive sentence Alice has pushed the joystick at left at time t and has obtained the outcome a by (a /1) t. By the fact that Alice s possible actions (indexed by x = 0 and x = 1) cannot be physically realized simultaneously, the conjunction of these two sentences (a/0) t and (a /1) t has no experimental meaning -which is expressed by the fact that, whatever are a and a, the probability P[(a/0) t and (a/1) t] cannot be computed. And similarly for the experimental descriptions (b/0) t and (b/1) t of Bob s alternative actions. By contrast, the game under consideration assumes that the couple of variables A x and B y (for all x and y) can always be evaluated conjointly, that is, at the same time -the four possible combinations of joint actions 6

(x, y) being equiprobable (i. e., they occur with probability ¼). This difference between the incompatibility of each of the player s alternative actions and the compatibility of all the actions of one player with all the actions of the other should be expressed in an accurate description of this game. 2) Underlying partial Boolean algebra: Due the previously mentioned incompatibility of the two alternative actions of each of the players, the structure of the experimental propositions that describe the game under consideration, endowed with the operations of conjunction, disjunction and negation, is not isomorphic to a Boolean algebra, but, as is the case for the set of sentences that describe a quantum experiment, to a partial Boolean algebra. Only the sub-algebra corresponding to sentences relative to compatible actions (like x and y at time t, or x = 0 at time t and x = 1 at time t > t, for example) is Boolean. This means that the game under consideration cannot be described in a commutative language of functions (which are here random variables). The fact that the structure of the descriptive sentences of this game is not Boolean can also be seen by the failure of some basic properties of classical logic. For example, the distributivity of the conjunction with regard to the disjunction fails since the sentence: = (a/0) t and [(0/1) t or (1/1) t ], which would be equivalent to (a/0) t in classical logic (since the sentences (0/1) t and (1/1) t describe complementary events), is not equivalent to the disjunctive sentence = [(a/0) t and ((0/1) t ] or [(a/0) t and (1/1) t ] 7

obtained by applying the law of distributivity to. For, as explained above, each of the sentences [(a/0) t and ((0/1) t ] or [(a/0) t and (1/1) t ] are conjunctions of incompatible descriptions that do not refer to any physical situation, and their disjunction cannot then be equivalent to (a/0) t. In terms of probabilities, this can be shown by noting that P[ ] = P [(a/0) t ] = ½ while P[ ] cannot be computed. 3) Erasure of the information relative to the previous outcomes: the probabilities P(a/x) and P(b/y), as well as the probabilities P(a,b/x,y) are given in all eternity, that is, independently of time and of any past (or future) action respectively performed by Alice, by Bob or conjointly by Alice and Bob. It can then be asserted that, as is the case for successive measurements of incompatible quantum observables, the information relative to the outcome of an action at time t is lost when another action is performed at time t >t and has then no influence on its outcome. This erasure of information, which is due here to the independence of the successive trials, can be written as: P[(a/x) t / (a /x ) t ] = P(a/x) t = ½ for all t. P[(b/y) t / (b /y ) t ] = P(b/y) t = ½ for all t. P [ (a,b/x,y) t / (a,b /x,y ) t ] = P (a,b /x,y) t = P (a,b /x,y) given by (C0). As is the case for quantum phenomena, the previously mentioned characteristics of this game (stochasticity, incompatibility of descriptions, underlying partial Boolean structure, erasure of the previous information) require to be represented in a non-commutative language of operators (or by some other isomorphic structure). In other words, an accurate description of this game must then be done within a non-commutative C* algebra of operators rather than within a commutative C* algebra of functions. These operators can be defined as follows: to say in the language of boxes that Alice chooses the 8

input x (for x = 0 or 1) and obtains the output a (for a = 0 or 1) can be translated in the language of operators by saying that Alice is measuring the observable A x, which is represented by a linear hermitean operator whose eigenvalues are 0 and 1, where the observables A x are supposed to act on a two-dimensional Hilbert space H A spanned by their two eigenvectors >Ax and >Ax. Similarly, to say in the language of boxes that Bob chooses the input y (with y = 0 or 1) and obtains the output b (with b = 0 or 1) can be translated into Bob measures the observable B y whose eigenvalues are 0 and 1, where B y is supposed to act on a two-dimensional Hilbert space H B spanned by the two eigenvectors >By and >By. As a consequence, the degree of correlation C(A x,b y) cannot be defined classically, as the expectation value of the product of real functions (random variables), but it must be defined like in quantum theory, by the expectation value of the product of the corresponding operators A x and B y defined above: C(A x,b y) =df <A x B y >, and R must then be defined as: (4) R = <A0 B0 + A0 B1 + A1 B0 A1 B1>. The condition (C1) must now be rewritten as: (C1 ) <A0 B0 + A0 B1 + A1 B0 A1 B1> > 2 2. III. Super-quantum, non-signaling correlations cannot exist. The incompatibility of the two conditions (C1 ) and (C2) that characterize together non-signaling super-quantum correlations can now be established. 9

The first step of the argument is to show that the description of this game implies the commutation of all Alice s box-observables (which are A0 and A1) with all Bob s box-observables (which are B 0 and B 1 ), that is: [A0, B0] = [A0, B1] = [A1, B0] = [A1, B1] = 0. From the condition (C2), by multiplying the first member of equality (1) by the second member of equality (2), we can write that: (4) P (a / x, y). P (b / y) = P (b / x, y). P (a / x). Using the definition of conditional probabilities, P (a / x, y) and P (b / x, y) can be rewritten as: P(a / x, y) = P(a, b/ x, y) / P(b/ a, x, y) P(b/ x, y) = P(a, b/ x, y) / P(a/ b, x, y). Reporting these expressions in equality (4), we obtain, after simplification: P(a/ b, x, y). P (b / y) = P(b/ a, x, y). P (a / x), which can be rewritten, more explicitly, as P (A x = a / B y = b). P (B y = b) = P (B y = b / A x = a). P (A x = a). The left member of this equation evaluates Alice s probability of obtaining the outcome a for A x once Bob has obtained the outcome b by measuring B y. It can then be interpreted as the sequential probability to measure B y = b and then A x = a. Similarly, the right member of this equation evaluates the sequential probability to measure A x = a and then B y = b. Consequently, the non-signaling condition (C2) leads to the following property: P (B y = b and then A x = a) = P (A x = a and then B y = b). 10

Since this condition holds for all possible outputs a and b and for all possible inputs x and y, it can be concluded that the non-signaling condition (C2) implies that all Alice s observables commute with all Bob s observables: (6) [A0, B0] = [A0, B1] = [A1, B0] = [A1, B1] = 0. The second step of the argument is to show that the condition (5) of commutativity of all Alice s observables with all Bob s observables is sufficient for establishing that the corresponding CHSH factor R defined above (by equation (4)) is smaller than the Tsirelson bound. This derivation is nothing but an adaptation to the present case of a well-known theorem shown by Landau [8] for binary observables with possible values -1 or +1. This theorem shows that the condition (5) entails that the CHSH correlation factor R is less than the Tsirelson bound. Actually, it is easy to see that this conclusion also holds with the weaker assumption that the spectrum of all the observables is bounded by 1 (that is, the possible values a and b of A x and B y are such that a 1 and b 1, for all x and y) 1 and, in particular, in the present case where the values of the observables can be 0 or 1: R 2 2. Consequently, the requirement of super non-locality (violation of the T- bound) is incompatible with the non-signaling condition (C2), which gives rise to the inequality (7). Super-quantum, non-signaling correlations cannot then exist. This result has been established directly, by analyzing the properties of the Bell s game under consideration in an appropriate non-commutative language of operators. It is in full agreement with the result of Pawlowski et al. [2] that shows that if such hypothetical super-quantum correlations would exist, a sort of multiplication of the information sent by one of the players to the other one would be possible (violation of the principle of Information 1 For, in this case, the quantities c and d considered by Landau in his derivation are such that (with his notations): c 2 4 + [a1, b1] [b2, a2] and d 2 4 + [a1, b1] [a2, b2], the equalities being replaced by inequalities. Consequently, the result < c > 2 < c 2 > 8 still holds. 11

Causality). It is also in full agreement with the result of van Dam [3] that shows that the existence of such super-quantum correlations implies that distributed computation could be performed with only one bit which seems quite implausible. IV. What about the explicit models of non-signaling PR-boxes? In contradiction with this result, some authors have yet proposed explicit models of boxes that would satisfy the conditions (C1) and (C2) at once [6-7]. The solution of this paradoxical situation is that these toy-models are either impossible to realize for purely logical reasons or they actually allow the exchange of signals. Let us consider here the praradigmatic toy-model of such super-quantum correlations, which is often mentioned as an indubitable proof of their existence. Rohlich and Popescu [6] have built an ad-hoc correlation function between two couples of spin observables (A, A ) and (B, B ), respectively defined on two non-signaling sub-systems S1 and S2, and whose directions a, b, a, b are separated by successive angles of /4 in a same plane (see the diagram, where the direction of A has been conventionally fixed to 0): B = S 3 / 4 A = S / 2 B = S / 4 A = S 0 Representation in the same plane of the two couples of spin observables (A,A ) and (B,B ) In this model the correlation function between two spin observables respectively defined on S1 and S2 only depends on the angle between these 12

two observables. In particular, the expectation values of the product of two spin observables, which depend only of their angle, is defined as follows: E( /4) = +1 and E(3 /4) = -1, Then, due to the directions of the spin observables reported in the previous diagram, the CHSH correlation factor can be computed as: (8) R = 3 E( /4) - E(3 /4) = 4. This result would then show that non-local correlations with R > 2 2 can exist between no-signaling systems. However, if we consider a separable state of the composite system S, the expectation values of the products of observables involved in the different terms of the relevant CHSH correlation factor are, in this case, factorable: they can then be written as the product of the expectation values of the observables acting on S1 an S2, respectively. Taking now into account the values of the correlation function for the different terms of R, we obtain the following equations: <AB> = <S /2 I > < I S /4 > = +1 <AB > = <S /2 I > < I S /4 > = +1 <A B> = <S I > < I S /4 > = +1 <A B > = <S I > < I S /4 > = -1. It is easy to see that the fourth equation, which implies that <S I> and <I S /4> are of opposite signs, is incompatible with the first three ones, which imply the contrary. Consequently, this model is logically inconsistent. 13

Conclusion The dream of realizing non-signaling PR-boxes, which would give rise to extraordinary, if not magical consequences, has resisted to credible arguments based on informational considerations that highlight their implausible consequences [2] [3]. More directly, this article has shown that such nonsignaling super-quantum correlations cannot be physically realized since their theoretical model, the non-signaling PR-boxes, must be described in a noncommutative, quantum-like language, which leads to the satisfaction of the Tsirelson bound. We hope that this stronger result will definitely convince the community of physicists of the impossibility of non-signaling super-quantum correlations and then of the unreality of non-signaling PR-boxes. References 1. S. Popescu 2015, Non-locality beyond quantum mechanics, in Alisa Bokulich, Gregg Jaeger Editors, Philosophy of Quantum Information and Entanglement, pp. 3-15, Cambridge Books Online. 2. M.P. Pawlowski, T. Paterek, D. Kaszlikowski, V. Scarani, A. Winter and M. Zukowski 2010, Information Causality as a Physical Principle. arxiv:0905.2292v3, 6 May. 3. W. van Dam 2005, Implausible Consequences of Superstrong Nonlocality, arxiv:quant-ph/0501159. 4. J.F. Clauser, M.A. Horne, A. Shimony and R.A. Holt 1969, Proposed experiment to test local hidden-variable theories, Phys. Rev. Lett. 23, 880 884. 14

5. J. Barrett, N. Linden, S. Massar, S. Pironio, S. Popescu and D. Roberts 2005, Non-local correlations as an information theoretic resource, Physical Review A 71. 6. S. Popescu and D. Rohrlich 1994, Quantum nonlocality as an axiom. Found. Phys. 24: 379-385. 7. T. Filk 2015, Mechanical model of a PR-Box, arxiv:1507.06789. 8. N. Gisin 2012, L impensable hasard, Non-localité, Téléportation, Merveilles Quantiques. Paris: Odile Jacob. English Translation: Quantum Chance: Nonlocality, Teleportation and Other Quantum Marvels, Springer 2014. 15