AN AXIOMATIZATION OF HERZBERGER'S 2-DIMENSIONAL PRESUPPOSITIONAL SEMANTICS JOHN N. MARTIN

Similar documents
KLEENE LOGIC AND INFERENCE

VALUATIONS FOR DIRECT PROPOSITIONAL

Přednáška 12. Důkazové kalkuly Kalkul Hilbertova typu. 11/29/2006 Hilbertův kalkul 1

Applied Logic. Lecture 1 - Propositional logic. Marcin Szczuka. Institute of Informatics, The University of Warsaw

1. Propositional Calculus

An Introduction to Modal Logic III

1. Propositional Calculus

An Introduction to Modal Logic V

Marie Duží

COMP219: Artificial Intelligence. Lecture 19: Logic for KR

Epistemic Semantics for Classical and Intuitionistic Logic

02 Propositional Logic

GÖDEL S COMPLETENESS AND INCOMPLETENESS THEOREMS. Contents 1. Introduction Gödel s Completeness Theorem

A Tableau Style Proof System for Two Paraconsistent Logics

Propositional Logic Arguments (5A) Young W. Lim 11/30/16

COMP219: Artificial Intelligence. Lecture 19: Logic for KR

CHAPTER 4 CLASSICAL PROPOSITIONAL SEMANTICS

Propositional logic. First order logic. Alexander Clark. Autumn 2014

Propositional Logic Arguments (5A) Young W. Lim 11/8/16

TABLEAUX VARIANTS OF SOME MODAL AND RELEVANT SYSTEMS

Omitting Types in Fuzzy Predicate Logics

COSE212: Programming Languages. Lecture 1 Inductive Definitions (1)

Overview. Knowledge-Based Agents. Introduction. COMP219: Artificial Intelligence. Lecture 19: Logic for KR

Kazimierz SWIRYDOWICZ UPPER PART OF THE LATTICE OF EXTENSIONS OF THE POSITIVE RELEVANT LOGIC R +

Propositional Logic Arguments (5A) Young W. Lim 10/11/16

In [3], Hallden in effect suggests that a modal (or other) system S 1}

KRIPKE S THEORY OF TRUTH 1. INTRODUCTION

First-Degree Entailment

Introduction to Metalogic

2. The Logic of Compound Statements Summary. Aaron Tan August 2017

Towards A Multi-Agent Subset Space Logic

A MODAL EXTENSION OF FIRST ORDER CLASSICAL LOGIC Part I

Propositional Logic: Review

Rasiowa-Sikorski proof system for the non-fregean sentential logic SCI

Axiom schema of Markov s principle preserves disjunction and existence properties

MAI0203 Lecture 7: Inference and Predicate Calculus

The Mother of All Paradoxes

Fuzzy Logic in Narrow Sense with Hedges

10 Propositional logic

ADMISSIBILITY OF ACKERMANN S RULE δ IN RELEVANT LOGICS

Piotr Kulicki The Use of Axiomatic Rejection

The Importance of Being Formal. Martin Henz. February 5, Propositional Logic

Advanced Topics in LP and FP

Propositional Calculus - Hilbert system H Moonzoo Kim CS Dept. KAIST

LING 501, Fall 2004: Laws of logic and the definitions of the connectives

Classical Propositional Logic

Computational Logic Lecture 3. Logical Entailment. Michael Genesereth Autumn Logical Reasoning

Draft of February 2019 please do not cite without permission. A new modal liar 1 T. Parent

AN EXTENSION OF THE PROBABILITY LOGIC LP P 2. Tatjana Stojanović 1, Ana Kaplarević-Mališić 1 and Zoran Ognjanović 2

First Order Logic: Syntax and Semantics

First-Order Logic. 1 Syntax. Domain of Discourse. FO Vocabulary. Terms

Chapter 11: Automated Proof Systems (1)

COSE212: Programming Languages. Lecture 1 Inductive Definitions (1)

Propositional Calculus - Hilbert system H Moonzoo Kim CS Division of EECS Dept. KAIST

Basic Algebraic Logic

Alternative Semantics for Unawareness

A SIMPLE AXIOMATIZATION OF LUKASIEWICZ S MODAL LOGIC

Paradoxes of Demonstrability

CHAPTER 11. Introduction to Intuitionistic Logic

Natural Deduction for Propositional Logic

INFERENCE RULES FOR PROBABILITY LOGIC. Marija Boričić

Maximal Introspection of Agents

The Modal Logic of Pure Provability

Language of Propositional Logic

Logic: Propositional Logic (Part I)

185.A09 Advanced Mathematical Logic

A non-classical refinement of the interpolation property for classical propositional logic

Intelligent Agents. First Order Logic. Ute Schmid. Cognitive Systems, Applied Computer Science, Bamberg University. last change: 19.

Natural Implication and Modus Ponens Principle 1

RELATIONS BETWEEN PARACONSISTENT LOGIC AND MANY-VALUED LOGIC

Logic and Inferences

Frege-numbers + Begriffsschrift revisited

Agents that reason logically

Logic Michælmas 2003

Propositional Logic: Part II - Syntax & Proofs 0-0

BETWEEN THE LOGIC OF PARMENIDES AND THE LOGIC OF LIAR

Many-Valued Modal Logics

A Little Deductive Logic

Propositional Logic Arguments (5A) Young W. Lim 2/23/17

Capturing Lewis s Elusive Knowledge

CHAPTER 2. FIRST ORDER LOGIC

Ki, K2 AND RELATED MODAL SYSTEMS. A. N. PRIOR

Propositional Logic. Testing, Quality Assurance, and Maintenance Winter Prof. Arie Gurfinkel

Deductive Systems. Lecture - 3

Chapter 4: Classical Propositional Semantics

Formal (natural) deduction in propositional logic

Conjunction: p q is true if both p, q are true, and false if at least one of p, q is false. The truth table for conjunction is as follows.

Socratic Proofs for Some Temporal Logics RESEARCH REPORT

Introduction to Logic in Computer Science: Autumn 2006

Modal Logic: Exercises

Proposition algebra and short-circuit logic

COUNTERFACTUALS AND SEMANTIC TABLEAUX

TR : Tableaux for the Logic of Proofs

Propositional logic (revision) & semantic entailment. p. 1/34

Propositional Logic Arguments (5A) Young W. Lim 11/29/16

Class 29 - November 3 Semantics for Predicate Logic

Inference in Propositional Logic

SOCRATES DID IT BEFORE GÖDEL

Description Logics. Foundations of Propositional Logic. franconi. Enrico Franconi

On the Complexity of the Reflected Logic of Proofs

Transcription:

378 Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic Volume XVIII, Number 3, July 3 977 NDJFAM AN AXIOMATIZATION OF HERZBERGER'S 2-DIMENSIONAL PRESUPPOSITIONAL SEMANTICS JOHN N. MARTIN The purpose of this paper* is to axiomatize two 4-valued propositional logics suggested by Herzberger in [l], section VI. They are of philosophical interest because their interpretation makes use of two ideas inspired by Jean Buridan: (1) a proposition may correspond to the world and yet be untrue because it is semantically deviant, and (2) logically valid arguments preserve correspondence with reality, not truth. If the two non-classical truth-values of these systems are identified, the resulting tables for the classical connectives are the weak and strong systems of Kleene. Unlike Kleene's system, the 4-valued ones offer a choice of designated values that renders semantic entailment perfectly classical. Compare Herzberger [2] and Martin [5]. Let the set 9r of formulas be inductively defined over a denumerable set of atomic formulas such that Ί A, A & B, CA, BA, TA f FA, XA, and fa are formulas if A and B are. Let W be the set of all m such that for some v and to, (1) for any atomic formula A, v(a), to(a) e {θ, l}; (2) v(ίa) = 1 if v(a) = 0; v(ίa) = 0 otherwise; v{a & B) = 1 if v(a) = v{b) = 1; v(a & B) = 0 otherwise; v(ca) = 1 if v{a) = 1; v(ca) = 0 otherwise; v(ba) = 1 if Ό(A) = 1; v(ba) = 0 otherwise; v{ίa) = 1 if v{a) = v(λ) = 1; tf(ta) = 0 otherwise; v{ψa) = 1 if v(a) = 0 and u(a) = 1; v(?a) = 0 otherwise; v{\a) = 1 if v{a) = 1 and \>(A) = 0; v(ta) = 0 otherwise; v(1a) = 1 if v(a) = v(a) = 0; v(ia) = 0 otherwise; (3) *(ΊA) = 1 if *CA) = 1; *(ΊA) = 0 otherwise; u(a & B) = 1 if n(λ) = *( ) = 1; nu & B) = 0 otherwise; *(CA) = n(bi4) = lι(ta) = ti(fa) = n(ta) = υ(fa) = 1; *I would like to thank Leo Simons for his helpful comments on a draft of this paper. Received September 25, 1975

AN AXIOMATIZATION 379 (4) to(a) = <*(A),*(A)>. Let 4 = (9, W), and abbreviate <11> by T, (01) by F, (10) by t, and (00) by f, and define AvB as l(la & IB), A -> B as ΊAvB, and A<-> as (A 5) & ( -> A). Intuitively, values on the first co-ordinate record whether a sentence corresponds to the world and values on the second whether it is semantically normal in the sense that all its presuppositions are satisfied. A sentence is assigned T for true iff it both corresponds and is normal and F for false iff though normal, it does not correspond. Hence ( C is read as 'corresponds' and *B' as 'is bivalent'. CA and BA could have been introduced by definition as ΊA vta and TA v FA respectively. The values on the first coordinate of members of W, those on the second, and the compound values for members of W conform to tables under I, II, and I x II respectively: Ί I B T F t f I & 1 10 I c 7ΓΎ~Ί~~ΓT~T 1 0 10 1 01 1 0 1 0 0 0 1 00 0 10 0 0 0 1 0 00 0 0 0 0 1 II Ί & lo c B J τ F II t I f 1 1 10 1 1 1 1 1 1 0 0 00 1 1 1 1 1 1 I XII Ί I & I T F t f I v I T F t f -» I T F t f c I B I T I F I t [I f T F T Ft f TTtt T F t f T T T F F F F T FFff T Ft f T T t t F T F T F F t f t f t f t t t t t f t f T F F F T F f t f f f f t f t f t t t t F F F F F T The operations of I x II are functionally incomplete as is seen from the fact that T and F are never taken into t or f. Further, substitution of truthfunctional equivalents fails among the non-classical formulas, e.g., if w(a) = T and \υ(b) = t, then nι(a <-» ) = t but m(ta «->TB) = F. If t and f are identified, Ί, &, and v become Kleene's weak connectives (cf. Kleene [3]). Let D = {T, t}be the set of designated values, and let a set Γ of formulas semantically entail A, briefly Γ \\-A, iff Vttie W, and VB e Γ, if ro(b) e Z), then m(a) e D. Observe also that is a conservative extension of classical logic. That is, for all formulas shared by both - and classical logic, Γ Ih^ iff the argument from Γ to A is classically valid. For, given

380 JOHN N. MARTIN any formula A made up from just Ί and &, v(a) conforms to the classical matrix for Ί and &, and n>(a) is designated iff v{a) = 1. The set of axioms for «is defined as the least set both containing all classical tautologies and all instances of the following axiom schemata, and closed under modus ponens: 1. (A& BA) ΊA 2. * ΊA& BA FA 3. (A& ISA) ta 4. (ΊA& IBA) 1A 5. BA- (ΊtA& ΊfA) 6.* (TAvFA) BA 7.* CA^A 8. BA^^B 1A 9.** (BA&B$*-*B(A&B) 10. Ί(TA& FA) 11. Ί(tA&fA) 12. BTA 13. BFA 14. BtA 15. BfA 16. BBA 17.* BCA Let A be deducible from Γ, briefly Γ i-a, iff there is a finite sequence A 19..., A n such that A w = A and A OT, m < n, is either an axiom, a member of Γ, or a consequent of previous A; by modus ponens. The theorems of -C are all formulas deducible from the empty set. They include the following as well as all instances of 6*, 7*, and 17* if C and B are introduced by definition: 18. TAvFAvtAvfA 19. Ί(TA&tA) 20. Ί(TA&fA) 21. Ί(FA&tA) 22. Ί(FA&fA) 23.** (BA & BB) ^ B(A B) 24. TA-CA 25. XA CA 26. FA ΊCA 27. fa-+ ICA 28. CA (TAvtA) 29. BA- (TAvFA) 30. B ΊCA 31. B ΊBA 32. B ΊTA 33. B ΊFA 34. B ΊtA 35. B 11A Let a set Γ of formulas be consistent iff for some A, Γ ^A, and let Γ be maximally consistent iff Γ is consistent and for all A, Ae Γ or ΊAe Γ. The proof that every consistent set is contained in a maximally consistent set carries over unaltered from classical logic. Lemma Any maximally consistent Γ is the set of all designated formulas of some me W. Proof: Let Γ be maximally consistent and define c, u, and tυ as follows: v{a) = 1 if Ae Γ, v{a) = 0 otherwise, lι(a) = 1 if BAe Γ, *>(A) = 0 otherwise, and ttί(a) = (v(a), ti(a)). Clearly, Γ is the set of formulas designated by w. To show tυe W, it suffices to show v and ti satisfy (l)-(3) of the definition of W. Since c and \ι are both functions from 9 into {1,0}, (l) is satisfied. For (2) consider first ΊA. If v{a) = 1, then Ae Γ, and c(ίa) = 0. If v(a) = 0, then ΊAe Γ, and v{la) = 1. Consider next A & B. If ι/(a) = v{b) = 1, then A, jbe Γ, A & Be Γ, and ι/(a & 5) = 1. If «/(A) or c(j3) is 0, then ΊA or IB is in Γ, Ί(A & B) e Γ, and i/(a & B) = 0. Consider CA. If w(a) e {T, t}, then AeΓ, CAeΓ, and v(ca) = 1. If w(a)e{f,f}, then ΊAeΓ, ΊCAeΓ, and v(ca) = 0. Consider BA. If n>(a)e{t, F}, then BAe Γ, and v{ba) = 1. If n>(a)e{t,f}, then ΊBAe Γ, and v{ba) = 0. Consider ΊA. If m(a) = T, then

AN AXIOMATIZATION 381 A, BAeT, ΎAeT, and v{ίa) = 1. If n>(a) = F, then ΊA, BAeΓ, FAeΓ, itae Γ, and ι/(ta) = 0. If m(a) = t, then tae Γ, ΊTAe Γ, and ι/(ta) = 0. If to(a) = f, then fae Γ, ΊTAe Γ, and v{ίa) = 0. Consider FA. If to (A) = T, then TAe Γ, ΊFAe Γ, and v{ψa) = 0. If w(a) = F, then FAe Γ, v(ψa) = 1. If n>(a)e{t, f}, then ΊBAe Γ, ΊFAe Γ, v(fa) = 0. Consider XA. If w(a) = T, then TAe Γ, ΊtAe Γ, and v{\a) = 0. If m(a) = F, then FAe Γ, ΊtAe Γ, and ι/(ta) = 0. If w(a) = t, then tae Γ, and v{xa) = 1. If m(a) = f, then fae Γ, ΊtAe Γ, and *(ta) = 0. Consider fa. If m(a) = T, then TAe Γ, ΊfAe Γ, and ι/(fa) = 0. If w(a) = F, then FAe Γ, ΊfAe Γ, and ι/(fa) = 0. If tυ(a) = t, then TAe Γ, ΊfAe Γ, and v{ίa) = 0. If w(a) = f, then fae Γ, and o(fa) = 1. For (3) consider first ΊA. If υ(a) = 1, then BAe Γ, B ΊAe Γ, and *(A) = 1. If υ(a) = 0, then ΊBAe Γ, ΊB ΊAe Γ, B ΊA/Γ, and tι(ίa) = 0. Consider A & B. If \)(A) = υ( ) = 1, then BA, B e Γ, B(A & B) e Γ, and t>(a & B) = 1. If u(a) or II(JB) is 0, then ΊBA or ΊB is in Γ. In either case ΊB(A & B) e Γ and n(a & 5) = 0. For the other connectives observe that since BCA, BBA, BTA, BFA, BtA, BfAe Γ, υ(ca) = υ(ba) = *(TA) = \ι(fa) = n(ta) = n(fa) = 1, no matter what n(a) is. Theorem T \-A iff ΓlhA. Proof: (1) Let Γ ha. Then there exist a finite sequence A 1?..., A n such that A w = A and for all A m, m < n, A n is either an axiom, a member of Γ, or a consequent by modus ponens of previous members. Assume that VI?e Γ, \υ(b) e Zλ But then since all the axioms are designated by any n>, and modus ponens preserves designation, u>(a)ed. (2) Assume T \f-a. Then Γ U {ΊA} is consistent and contained in some maximally consistent Δ. Further there is a m such that Δ is the set of designated formulas of m. Hence m satisfies Γ, yet nι(a)/z). Hence Γ FA. Q.E.D. This axiom system is also adaptable to Herzberger's 2-dimensional rendering of Kleene's strong connectives. Let *W be defined like W except that clause (3) is altered as follows: u(a & B) = 1 if ι/(a) = 0 and *(A) = 1, or v{b) = 0 and *(B) = 1, or t)(a) = \*(B) = 1; n(a & B) = 0 otherwise. We retain the same abbreviations and defined connectives as before. truth tables remain the same except for the following changes. *II I x *II & I T F t f & I T F t f I v I T F t f I -> I T F- \ f T 1 1 0 0 T F t f T T T T T F t f F l l l l F F F F T F t f T T T T t O l O O t F t f T t t t T f t f f O l O O f F f f T f t f T t t t The tables for the strong connectives are obtained by identifying t and f with N. (Cf. Kleene [4], pp. 334-335.) Also, the new language **C = <2, *W) remains a conservative extension of classical logic. For the axiomatization, all the previous schemata are retained except 9** which is replaced by The

382 JOHN N. MARTIN *9. B(A & B)<^ (FA vfbv (BA & BB)). The list of previous theorems remains unchanged except for 23** which is replaced by: *23. B(A -> B) <^ (FA v ΊB v (BA & BB)). The proof of the soundness and completeness results remains the same except that the proof of the lemma for clause (3) of the definition of *W should be altered as follows: Consider A & B. If v(a) = v(b) = \>(A) = *(B) = 1, then BA, BBe Γ, BU & B) e Γ, and *(A & B) = 1. If f (A) = 0 and *>(A) = 1, or ι/(5) = 0 and t>( ) = 1, then either ΊA, BAe Γ or Ί, B^e Γ, either FAe Γ or FBe Γ, B(A &ΰ)eΓ, and tι(a & 5) = 1. If t>(a) = n(5) = 0, then IBA, ibbe Γ, ib(a & B)eΓ, and n(a & B) = 0. REFERENCES [1] Herzberger, H. G., "Dimensions of truth," Journal of Philosophical Logic, vol. 2 (1973), pp. 535-556. [2] Herzberger, H. G., "Truth and modality in semantically closed languages," in Paradox of the Liar, R. L. Martin, ed., Yale University Press, New Haven (1970), pp. 25-46. [3] Kleene, S. C, "On a notation for ordinal numbers," The Journal of Symbolic Logic, vol. 3 (1938), pp. 150-155. [4] Kleene, S. C, Introduction to Metamathematics, North Holland Co., Amsterdam (1959). [5] Martin, J. N., "A syntactic characterization of Kleene's strong connectives with two designated values," Zeitschrift fur Mathematische Logik und Grundlagen der Mathematik, vol. 21 (1975), pp. 181-184. University of Cincinnati Cincinnati, Ohio